24.00: Problems of Philosophy
Prof. Sally Haslanger
December 5, 2001
Particularism and Virtue Ethics
I. Universalism and Particularism
We've considered before some basic questions that we would expect a moral theory to answer:
i) Which acts are right and which are wrong? Which acts ought we to perform (understanding the "ought" as a moral
"ought")?
ii) What makes a particular action right or wrong? What is it about the action that determines its moral status?
iii) How do we know what is right and wrong?
Both utilitarianism and Kantianism (and egoism) are what are sometimes called universalistic moral theories: they provide
a single general characterization of what makes an action right or wrong that determines for anyone at any time what is the
right (or wrong) thing to do. A utilitarian holds that actions are right insofar as they maximize happiness [pleasure, utility];
a Kantian holds that actions are right insofar as they satisfy the categorical imperative. These views are universalistic
because regardless of who you are, where you came from, what role you currently occupy, or what your own
desires/preferences are, the same principle that determines what you ought to do, determines what everyone else ought to
do. (Note that it doesn't follow that you can always tell what it is that you ought to do; sometimes it is difficult to apply the
principle to get a clear result because we don't have enough information, etc.)
We've noted before that utilitarianism and Kantianism (and egoism) are also objectivist moral theories, i.e., they are
committed to there being objective moral truth; morality is not just a matter of what a particular group or individual
believes to be right or wrong. But not all objectivist moral theories are universalistic. According to some moral theories,
what you ought to do in a particular situation may depend in part on particular facts about yourself, your culture, and your
social role, that a universalistic theory would not regard as morally significant. Another way of putting it is that
universalistic theories tend to view morality in terms of what our responsibilities are to each other as persons, where this
might mean viewing us as individuals capable of happiness [pleasure, utility], or as individuals capable of rationality or
freedom. What is morally significant about us, i.e., what is the proper subject of moral agency and the object of moral
concern, is the same for all. From the universalistic perspective, arguably, the moral stance is a stance of impartiality: to
act morally is to act, in a sense, with due respect to the equal personhood of all.
In contrast to universalistic theories, some moral theories are particularist. Particularist theories resist the idea that
morality consists in universal principles that apply to all of us as persons. Although a particularist may allow that there are
some universal principles, or that there are some moral requirements that apply to us as persons, this does not exhaust the
moral domain. More specifically, the particularist is concerned to emphasize the way in which our actions are embedded in
particular social roles and relationships that structure what is right and wrong for each of us. Note that this is not a return to
a form of (cultural) relativism. The particularist is not saying that whether I ought to perform an action A is entirely a
matter of what my culture says I ought to do. The particularist holds that there are objective facts about what I ought to do.
But what I ought to do is not determined simply by my personhood (and the personhood of those affected), but is at least
partly determined by particular social and historical facts about me (and those around me). (Hopefully the contrast between
particularism and relativism will become clearer as we proceed.)
II. MacIntyre's Virtue Ethics
There are different versions of particularism. We will look briefly at a form of virtue ethics espoused by Alasdair
MacIntyre that is plausibly particularist (note that there are many forms of virtue ethics too!). Virtue ethics is often
inspired by the ancient Greek approach to ethics found in Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. For the ancient Greeks, the notion
of virtue is tied to the notion of function. The virtues of something are what enable it to perform excellently its proper
function. Virtue extends beyond the realm of morality; it concerns the excellent performance of any function. For example
the function of a paring knife is to cut fruits and vegetables. A paring knife "has virtues" relative to that function, e.g., a
good paring knife is sharp, strong, easy to handle, etc. From this it appears that our own broad idea of virtue retains the
Greek suggestion that virtue is excellence in performing one's proper function.
MacIntyre argues that there are three stages in his account of the virtues. In the first stage he links virtue with practices; in
the second stage he links virtue with the good life for humans; in the third stage he links virtue with traditions. (See, e.g.,
p. 245) Let's consider each in turn:
i) Virtues and practices
Begin with the idea of a role. Typically for professional roles there are specific tasks one is expected to perform and a
particular function one is supposed to serve. So, e.g., the function of a doctor is to heal, of a professor is to teach, of a cab
driver to deliver people to their destinations. Being a good doctor, professor, or cab driver, will involve particular "virtues"
specific to the role. MacIntyre calls these "professional skills"; they are virtues in the narrowest sense. (p. 239) Virtues are
broader than this, however, for they concern our dispositions to act across a wider range of situations. But still, MacIntyre
suggests, virtues are grounded in narratives that provide unity to our lives. In asking, "What should I do?" one must first
situate oneself in a narrative that gives the context for one's intentions and the expected consequences. [Example of man
working in the garden. p. 240-1] The answer, then, will depend on one's role in this broad narrative. For example, in acting
in the context in question is one acting as a wife or a husband? a parent or a child? an eldest son? a black sheep of the
family? an unruly daughter? Just as there are "virtues" for a professional role, there are virtues for such narrative roles, i.e.,
there are better and worse ways of "playing the part". In order to make sense of ourselves and others we construct
narratives, situate each other in parts, and evaluate our options (and each other) against the backdrop of the narrative
structure. Internal to these narratives we will be able to achieve certain goods; the relationships of parent/child,
teacher/student, etc. involve a set of practices that enable us to obtain things that are good, and in some cases unique to the
practice (e.g., the pride in getting an "A"). But we're not yet talking about moral virtue.
ii) Virtues and "the good life"
Continuing with the Greek conception of virtue, human virtue is that which enables a human being to perform well or
excellently the proper function of a human being. A virtuous person is one who has the ability to live excellently, i.e., to
live a full, productive, and happy human life. Moral goodness (moral virtue) is a kind of functional goodness: goodness
relative to our proper purpose or function. We may find it odd to speak of the proper goal or function of a human being;
what is the function of human beings? The function of something is linked to what it can do especially well, or what only it
can do. For humans, to put the point broadly, this is to live a distinctively human life; of course what constitutes a
distinctively human life, and distinctively human excellence is controversial.
Here an extended quote from MacIntyre will be helpful in fleshing out his view of the human good, and his version of
virtue ethics:
The virtues therefore are to be understood as those dispositions which will not only sustain practices and enable us
to achieve the goods internal to practices, but which will also sustain us in the relevant kind of quest for the good,
enabling us to overcome the harms, dangers, temptations and distractions which we encounter, and which will
furnish us with increasing self-knowledge and increasing knowledge of the good. The catalogue of the virtues will
therefore include the virtues required to sustain the kind of households and kind of political communities in which
men and women can seek the good together and the virtues necessary for philosophical enquiry about the
character of the good....the good life for [human beings] is the life spent in seeking for the good life for [human
beings], and the virtues necessary for the seeking are those which will enable us to understand what more and
what else the good life for [human beings] is. (p. 245)
Each virtue enables one to perform well in a particular sphere of life, and the virtues together enable one to live a good life
as a whole. For example, bravery enables one to perform well in situations of danger; justice enables one to carry out
successfully one's dealings with the others in a community; having all of the virtues enables one to perform excellently in
all aspects of life. Truly living well--achieving the good life--requires that one have all of the virtues; complete virtue is
the key to happiness.
iii) Virtues and traditions: social identity and moral particularity
The link between virtue and the good life provides a basis for an overarching set of human virtues common to us all.
However, remember MacIntyre is a particularist. So we still need to understand where the particularism is located in his
view. As a particularist, MacIntyre needs to argue that what I ought to do in a situation is not necessarily what another
ought to do; there are at least some cases in which no universal principle can adequately direct us. He says:
I am never able to seek for the good or exercise the virtues only qua individual...it is not just that different
individuals live in different social circumstances; it is also that we all approach our own circumstances as bearers
of a particular social identity. I am someone's son or daughter, someone's cousin or uncle; I am a citizen of this or
that city, a member of this or that guild or profession; I belong to this clan, that tribe, this nation. Hence what is
good for me has to be the good for one who inhabits these roles. As such, I inherit from the past of my family, my
city, my tribe, my nation, a variety of debts, inheritances, rightful expectations and obligations. These constitute
the given of my life, my moral starting point. This is in part what gives my life its own moral particularity. (p.
245)
He goes on to emphasize that we need not be limited by the traditions and the history that give us our social identities; in
fact we can go on to critique and repudiate the values implicit in them. However, one enters moral life already possessing a
substantive identity (one is not born a moral "blank slate"), and even if one rejects this identity, this too is a move in a
particular narrative and is possible only within certain traditions.
III. Impartiality and Virtue
According to a virtue ethics, one's moral obligations are derived, at least in part, from one's particular social identity, one's
social roles, one's tradition. E.g., a wife has different obligations towards her husband than others have, and what
obligations she has qua wife depend on the cultural meaning of the relationship between husband and wife. In cultures that
lack the social role of wife, there are no specifically wifely obligations.
In his essay, "Impartiality, Beneficence, and Friendship," Lawrence Blum argues that our duty to be impartial, insofar as
there is one, is derived from particular social roles and does not apply to us generally. E.g., we are obligated to be impartial
when in the role of judge, or teacher, but in our ordinary dealings with others we are entitled to be partial towards our
friends and family. Although Blum does not endorse the full extent of MacIntyre's virtue ethics, his argument is
compatible with MacIntyre's account, and with the basic strategies of virtue ethics. Very briefly, his argument is this (see
especially p. 103):
1. There is no general moral requirement to be impartial regarding people's interests per se. I.e., one is not morally
obligated to treat everyone's interests equally. (This is argued for in section II, pp. 101-2)
2. We have a duty to be impartial between legitimate claims on us, i.e., we must attempt "with equal care" to satisfy all
legitimate claims. (And a legitimate claim is not generated automatically by having interests.)
3. Legitimate claims on us are derived from our particular social relationships to others, e.g., being a parent, a friend, a
lawyer, an employer.
4. So insofar as impartiality is a duty, it derives from particular social relationships to others. (1, 2, 3)
5. So, we are not required to be impartial between those we have an established relationship with and those we do not. (4)
From this we can conclude that we have no obligation, then, to give significant amounts to aid distant others with whom
we have no relationship. It would appear that this provides a way out of Singer's conclusions. How would Singer respond?
One strategy would be to note that the argument as it stands is not conclusive. Blum argues that we don't have a general
moral obligation to respond impartially to people's interests per se, and we do have an obligation to respond to legitimate
claims on us derived from particular relationships. But these options are not necessarily exhaustive. Perhaps we also have a
duty to respond impartially to extreme human need; or perhaps those in danger of extreme suffering and death do have
legitimate claims on us even if they do not have an established relationship with us. And Blum seems to grant this latter
point. (p. 102) So although virtue ethics provides a strategy for responding to Singer, it has not offered a conclusive
rebuttal.
Questions:
1. Is there a real difference between MacIntyre's particularism and universalism? Isn't there a way to formulate a general
moral requirement that he himself suggests, e.g., "[we need] to recognize the existence of an additional virtue...the virtue
of having an adequate sense of traditions to which one belongs or which confront one..." (p. 248)?
2. Why should we think that individuals "inherit" the moral obligations, etc., of their history and tradition? Aren't we each
free to make our own path in life? Isn't what's good for me a matter of my choices and preferences? What reasons does
MacIntyre give for denying this?