THE UNIVERISITY OF MELBOURNE
FACULTY OF LAW
Public Law and Legal Theory
Research Paper No. 33
2002
INTERNATIONAL LAW AS A TOOL OF
CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION
Kristen Walker
This paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network Electronic Library at:
http://ssrn.com/abstract_id=319921
INTERNATIONAL LAW AS A TOOL OF CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION
Kristen Walker
*
INTRODUCTION
In a series of judgments in the past five years Justice Kirby has developed an
interpretive principle concerning the use of international law in constitutional
interpretation. He has adapted the words of Brennan J in Mabo v Queensland [No
2]
1
to formulate the proposition that:
The common law, and constitutional law, do not necessarily conform with
international law. However, international law is a legitimate and important
influence on the development of the common law and constitutional law,
especially when international law declares the existence of universal and
fundamental rights.
2
So far, he is very much alone in his endeavour, though as Kirby J himself has noted,
"today's heresies sometimes become tomorrow's orthodoxy".
3
In this paper I will explain and assess Kirby J's interpretive principle. I shall argue
that international law should, as Kirby J asserts, be considered a legitimate influence
on constitutional interpretation. I also argue that Kirby J's approach is not entirely
new, as there is support for the use of international law in constitutional interpretation
*
BSc LLB(Hons) LLM (Melb), LLM (Columbia). Senior Lecturer in Law, The University of Melbourne.
I would like to thank Simona Gory for research assistance; all errors remain my own. A version of this
paper was presented at the Public Law Weekend, ANU Law School, 2 November 2001.
1
Mabo v Queensland [No 2] (1992) 175 CLR 1, 42.
2
Newcrest Mining (WA) v The Commonwealth (1997) 190 CLR 513, 657. And see Kartinyeri v The
Commonwealth (1998) 195 CLR 337, 417–418, Sinanovic v R (1998) 154 ALR 702, 708; Re Minister
for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs; Ex parte Epeabaka (2001) 179 ALR 296, 314; Levy v Victoria
(1997) 189 CLR 589, 644–5; Re East; Ex parte Nguyen (1998) 196 CLR 354, 380–1; Michael Kirby,
"International Law: Down in the Engineroom", ANZSIL/ASIL Joint Meeting, 26 June 2000, 6–7,
http://www.hcourt.gov.au/speeches/kirbyj/kirbyj_inter_law.htm; Michael Kirby, "Domestic
Implementation of Human Rights Norms" ANU Conference on Implementing International Human
Rights, 6 December 1997, 29–32, http://www.hcourt.gov.au/speeches/kirbyj/kirbyj_inthrts.htm.
3
Kirby, "Domestic Implementation", 32.
in several cases over the course of the last century. What is new about Kirby J's
approach is that he has articulated an explicit interpretive principle, whereas previous
cases had involved the ad hoc and unexplained use of international law. It might
also be argued that Kirby J's approach is not new in that he is merely extending an
existing principle of statutory interpretation to the Constitution. I disagree with such a
characterisation, however, as I do not consider the Constitution to be the equivalent
to an ordinary statute. Rather, the Constitution is a "special" statute
4
— that is,
although technically an Imperial statute, it is our foundational legal document,
developed in Australia and adopted after referenda in each colony. It stands in a
special position,
5
subject to a distinct body of jurisprudence concerning its
interpretation. Thus although it is correct to say that Kirby J has extended an existing
principle into the constitutional arena, I regard this extension as novel — and indeed,
as controversial, as the discussion of judicial responses to Kirby J's approach in Part
II of this paper reveals.
In Part I of this article, I shall briefly outline the cases in which members of the High
Court have, over the years, drawn on international law in interpreting the
Constitution. In Part II I shall explore in greater detail Kirby J's approach to the use of
international law in constitutional interpretation and consider the reaction to that
approach by other members of the present High Court. In Part III I shall provide a
normative argument concerning the interaction of international law and constitutional
law. I conclude that, while international law has had and should have a role to play in
constitutional interpretation, a robust role for international law is unlikely to be
accepted by a majority of the Court as presently constituted.
4
Kartinyeri 419.
2
I note at this point that I will not be dealing in any detail with the more general
question of the relationship between international law and domestic law – that is, the
incorporation/transformation debate. Although this is a constitutional question, it is
not the question on which I wish to focus, and it has been dealt with extensively
elsewhere.
6
Briefly, however, it may be noted that in our legal system treaties are not
automatically "part of" domestic law. Rather, an act of transformation is required to
give treaties direct effect in Australian law.
7
In relation to customary international law,
the position is more complex. It is still possible to argue that customary international
law is "part of" the Australian common law without requiring legislation to transform
customary international law into Australian law, based on English authorities (such as
Triquet v Bath
8
and Trendtex Trading Corporation v Central Bank of Nigeria
9
) and
some older Australian cases (such as Polites v The Commonwealth
10
and Chow
Hung Ching v R
11
). However, such a proposition was rejected by Dixon CJ in Chow
Hung Ching
12
and, more recently, impliedly rejected by a majority of the Full Federal
Court in Nulyarimma v Thompson.
13
There is no recent High Court support for an
5
Ibid 384 (Gummow and Hayne JJ), Polites 78 (Dixon J).
6
See, eg, Kristen Walker, "Treaties and the Internationalisation of Australian Law" in Cheryl Saunders,
ed, Courts of Final Jurisdiction (1995); Andrew Mitchell, "Genocide, Human Rights Implementation
And The Relationship Between International And Domestic Law : Nulyarimma v Thompson" (2000) 24
MULR 15; James Crawford and William Edeson, “International Law and Australian Law” in KW Ryan
(ed), International Law in Australia (2
nd
ed, 1984) 71; C Alexandrowicz, "International Law in the
Municipal Sphere According to Australian Decisions" (1964) 13 International and Comparative Law
Quarterly 78.
7
For a fuller discussion of the relationship between treaties and Australian law, see Kristen Walker,
"Treaties and the Internationalisation of Australian Law" in Cheryl Saunders, ed, Courts of Final
Jurisdiction (1995) 204.
8
(1764) 3 Burr 1478 [97 ER 777].
9
[1977] 1 QB 529.
10
(1945) 70 CLR 60.
11
(1948) 77 CLR 449.
12
Ibid 477.
13
[1999] FCA 1192 (1 Sept 1999), paras 24, 52.
3
incorporation approach to customary international law and Sir Anthony Mason, in his
extra–judicial writings, has noted that in Australia we seem to prefer the
transformation approach to customary international law.
14
However, both treaties
and customary international law have been used quite frequently by the Courts in the
development of the common law and in the interpretation of legislation.
15
More
recently, treaties have been used in the area of legitimate expectations in
administrative law.
16
The question that remains is whether and how international law
may be used in constitutional cases.
I. INTERNATIONAL LAW IN CONSTITUTIONAL CASES: 1901–1996
International law has been raised in various constitutional cases over the years in
relation to diverse issues, including:
(a) international law as a limitation on legislative power;
17
(b) international law as a source of legislative power;
18
(c) the determination of the existence of a sufficient nexus between a State
and the subject matter of a State law;
19
(d) the interpretation of section 44 of the Constitution;
20
14
Anthony Mason, "International Law as a Source of Domestic Law" in Brian Opeskin (ed),
International Law and Australian Federalism (1997) , 218. And see generally the discussion in
Mitchell, above n 6.
15
See discussion in Walker, above n 6, 209-218; Rosalie Balkin, "International Law and Domestic
Law" in Sam Blay, Ryszard Piotrowicz and Martin Tsamenyi (eds), Public International Law: An
Australian Perspective (1997) 119, 122, 132-135
16
Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v Teoh (1995) 183 CLR 273.
17
Polites v The Commonwealth (1945) 70 CLR 60; Horta v The Commonwealth (1994) 181 CLR 183;
Polyukhovich v The Commonwealth (1991) 172 CLR 501.
18
Roche v Kronheimer (1921) 29 CLR 329; R v Burgess; Ex parte Henry (1936) 55 CLR 608; R v
Poole; Ex parte Henry ([No 2] (1939) 61 CLR 634; Airlines of New South Wales Pty Ltd v New South
Wales [No 2] (1965) 113 CLR 54; The Commonwealth v Tasmania (1983) 158 CLR 1; Kirmani v
Captain Cook Cruises Pty Ltd (1985) 158 CLR 351; Gerhardy v Brown (1985) 159 CLR 70;
Richardson v Forestry Commission (1988) 164 CLR 261; Queensland v The Commonwealth (1989)
167 CLR 232 (The Queensland Rainforest Case); Victoria v The Commonwealth (1996) 187 CLR 416
(The Industrial Relations case).
19
Union Steamship Co of Australia Pty Ltd v King (1988) 166 CLR 1.
4
(e) the determination of the constitutionality of legislation regulating New
Guinea (and later Papua and New Guinea) under the League of
Nations mandate system (and later the United Nations trusteeship
system);
21
and
(f) the freedom of political communication cases; and the interpretation of
Ch III of the Constitution.
22
I will not consider all of these areas in detail — suffice it to say that international law
was, as we know, rejected as a limitation on legislative power in both Polites and
Horta, with the exception of some legislation enacted under the external affairs
power.
23
Evatt J's attempts to confine the Commonwealth's power over trust and
mandated territories failed.
24
Constitutionally, of course, international law has proved
significant as a source of legislative power because of the Commonwealth
Parliament's capacity to legislate to give effect to Australia's international obligations,
but that has been much written about elsewhere
25
and thus will not be addressed
here. Rather, I will focus on two areas where international law has been used in
determining a constitutional issue: Ch III of the Constitution and the implied freedom
of political communication.
20
Sykes v Cleary (1992) 176 CLR 77.
21
Jolley v Mainka(1993) 49 CLR 243; Ffrost v Stevenson (1937) 58 CLR 528; Fishwick v Cleland
(1960) 106 CLR 186.
22
Nationwide News v Wills (1992) 177 CLR 1; Australian Capital Television Pty Ltd v The
Commonwealth (1992) 177 CLR 106; Theophanous v Herald & Weekly Times Ltd (1994) 124 ALR 1.
23
That is, legislation enacted in reliance on a treaty must be "reasonably capable of being considered
appropriate and adapted" to implementing the treaty: Industrial Relations case, (1996) 187 CLR 416,
508-9.
24
See n 21, above.
25
See, eg, Andrew Byrnes and Hilary Charlesworth, “Federalism and the International Legal Order:
Recent Developments in Australia” (1985) 79 American Journal of International Law 622; Kidwai,
“External Affairs Power and the Constitutions of British Dominions” (1976) 9 University of Queensland
Law Journal 167; JT Ludeke, “The External Affairs Power: Another Province for Law and Order”
(1994) 68 Australian Law Journal 250; Brian Opeskin and Don Rothwell, “The Impact of Treaties on
Australian Federalism” (1995) 27 Case Western Journal of International Law 1; Don Rothwell, “The
High Court and the External Affairs Power: A Consideration of its Inner and Outer Limits” (1993) 15
Adelaide Law Review 209; James Crawford and William Edeson, “International Law and Australian
Law” in KW Ryan (ed), International Law in Australia (2nd ed, 1984) 71; Geoffrey Sawer, “Australian
Constitutional Law in Relation to International Relations and International Law” in KW Ryan,
International Law in Australia (2nd ed, Sydney) 35; Leslie Zines, The High Court and the Constitution
(3rd ed, 1992).
5
1. Ch III of the Constitution
Chapter III of the Constitution may not appear at first glance to be fertile ground for
arguments based on international law. However, international law has had some
relevance in determining whether Ch III precludes the enactment of ex post facto
criminal laws and, if it does, precisely what amounts to such a law. These issues
were raised in Polyukhovich, which concerned the validity of the Commonwealth War
Crimes Act. Deane J concluded that Ch III did preclude ex post facto criminal laws
26
and, although his Honour’s decision was based primarily on his conception of the
nature of the judicial process, he also drew support from international human rights
conventions, such as the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights
(“ECHR”) and the American Convention on Human Rights, which provided protection
against the imposition of retrospective criminal guilt.
27
Australia is not a party to
either of these conventions, but Deane J used them to support his conclusion that “ex
post facto criminal legislation lies outside the proper limits of the legislative function”
as a matter of principle.
28
Both Deane J and Gaudron J also made use of principles of international law
in their application of the prohibition on ex post facto criminal laws stemming from Ch
III of the Constitution. Because they concluded that such a prohibition existed, it was
necessary for them to establish whether the War Crimes Act violated the prohibition.
It was accepted that the conduct criminalised by the Act was not criminal in domestic
law at the time of its commission; however, both judges considered it necessary to
26
(1991) 172 CLR 501, 611-2.
27
Ibid 612.
28
Ibid 611.
6
determine whether the conduct was criminal at international law at that time, in order
to determine whether the legislation was truly retrospective.
29
They concluded that
the relevant conduct was not criminalised in international law at the time it occurred,
and thus the legislation was retroactive in nature.
Worth mentioning, too, are some obiter comments of Deane J to the effect
that, if Australia was participating in the establishment and functioning of an
international tribunal for the trial and punishment of international crimes, Ch III of the
Constitution would be inapplicable because the judicial power of the international
community, rather than that of the Commonwealth, would be involved.
30
In addition,
he foreshadowed a possible further exception to the applicability of Ch III, where a
local tribunal is vested with jurisdiction in relation to an alleged crime against
international law:
It may be arguable that, in such a case, the judicial power of the
Commonwealth is not involved for so long as the alleged crime against
international law is made punishable as such in the local court. Alternatively,
at least where violations of the laws and customs of war are alone involved,
analogy with the disciplinary powers of military tribunals and largely pragmatic
considerations might combine to dictate recognition of a special jurisdiction
standing outside Ch III.
31
This comment on the potential for international law to take a criminal prosecution
outside the protection afforded by Ch III is surprising, as Deane J has been one of
the leaders of the Court in developing Ch III as a protective mechanism, particularly
in the area of military courts-martial.
32
These comments will be of particular interest
if, as expected, Australia ratifies the Statute of the International Criminal Court.
29
Ibid 627-8, 631, 699-700, 707.
30
Ibid 627.
31
Ibid.
32
See, eg, Re Tyler; Ex parte Foley (1994) 181 CLR 18; Re Nolan; Ex parte Young (1991) 172 CLR
460; Re Tracey; Ex parte Ryan (1989) 166 CLR 518.
7
2. The Implied Freedom of Political Communication
Several members of the Court have also referred to international conventions
in decisions concerning the implied freedom of political communication. In Australian
Capital Television and Nationwide News, Mason CJ, Brennan J and Gaudron J used
the European Convention on Human Rights in support of the fundamental
importance of freedom of communication to representative democracy.
33
These
judges did not engage in any in depth discussion or analysis of freedom of
expression as guaranteed by the ECHR; rather, they merely used the ECHR (to
which, of course, Australia is not a party) to demonstrate that other representative
democracies value freedom of expression.
The ECHR was also used by Brennan J in Australian Capital Television in his
assessment of whether the freedom of political communication had been violated.
He noted that in X and the Association of Z v United Kingdom a challenge under the
ECHR to a ban on political advertisements on British television had failed.
34
Brennan
J paid some attention to this case, which was directly on point although not referred
to by Mason CJ or Gaudron J. Ultimately, Brennan J concluded that the ban on paid
political advertising did not violate the implied right to freedom of political expression,
and the European case, although not decisive, was influential in reaching that
conclusion.
McHugh J, too, considered the ECHR , but found it unnecessary to discuss X
and the Association of Z, because he concluded that the constitutional context in
which the guarantee of freedom of expression operated in Australia meant that there
was no valid analogy between the international instruments and the Commonwealth
33
Nationwide News Pty Ltd v Wills (1992) 177 CLR 1, 47 (Brennan J); Australian Capital Television
Pty Ltd v The Commonwealth (1992) 177 CLR 106, 140 (Mason J), 211 (Gaudron J).
34
(1992) 177 CLR 106, 154.
8
Constitution.
35
Curiously, in the next freedom of expression case, Theophanous v
Herald & Weekly Times Ltd,
36
Brennan J approached the relevance of the ECHR in
the same way as McHugh J had in Australian Capital Television.
37
It is difficult to
reconcile Brennan J’s use of the ECHR in Australian Capital Television and his
rejection of it in Theophanous.
3. Conclusion
Up to 1996 the High Court had referred to international law in various cases
involving constitutional issues, though such references have not been frequent.
However, it cannot be said that there was any coherent approach to the use of
international law in constitutional interpretation, other than in relation to the external
affairs power. There was no in-depth discussion of the role that international law
might play in the determination of constitutional issues or why international law might
be relevant. Apart from section 51(29), the Court has been largely reluctant to allow
international law to play a significant role, though there are some areas where it has
been drawn on in aid of particular conclusions. When international law was used, it
was generally as an indication of international values, to give added legitimacy to the
right being implied into the Constitution, rather than in any determinative way.
Kirby J's interpretative principle would give international law a greater role to play in
constitutional questions, and it is to a discussion of that approach that I will now turn.
35
Ibid 240.
36
(1994) 124 ALR 1.
37
Ibid 44.
9
II JUSTICE KIRBY'S INTERPRETIVE PRINCIPLE
The first case in which Kirby J used international law in the resolution of a
constitutional issue was Wilson v Minister for Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander
Affairs.
38
The case concerned the separation of powers and the tasks that might
legitimately be conferred upon a judge of the Federal Court as a persona designata.
The question for the court was, in Kirby J's words, to "decide where 'the constitutional
wall' that separates the exercise of judicial power from the other powers of
government stands".
39
This task, he acknowledged, involved a question of
judgement drawing on the "language and design of the Constitution, past authority of
the Court and an understanding of the legal principles and policy which that authority
upholds".
40
He then used international law to assist in determining the content of
those "legal principles and policy" — specifically, the Universal Declaration on
Human Rights, the ICCPR and the Draft Universal Declaration on the Independence
of Judges. These were used to support the proposition that part of the "principles
and policy" is the "fundamental right of every individual … to have access to courts
which are 'competent, independent and impartial' and 'established by law'".
41
Of course, Kirby J could quite easily have obtained these principles from more
local sources than international law — there are various domestic authorities in
support of the importance of judicial independence. However, he chose to use
international law to support his argument on this point. Thus, while not determinative
of the outcome, international law played a role in legitimating Kirby J's approach. At
this point, however, he had not formulated any general statement about the use of
38
(1996) 189 CLR 1.
39
Ibid, 40.
40
Ibid.
41
Ibid.
10
international law in constitutional interpretation. This was to come in Newcrest
Mining (WA) Limited v Commonwealth.
42
Newcrest concerned the operation of section 51(31) of the Constitution: the
acquisition of property on just terms. The Commonwealth had enacted legislation
(the National Parks and Wildlife Conservation Amendment Act 1987 (Cth)) in reliance
on both the external affairs power and, in so far as the territories were concerned, on
s 122 of the Constitution. Newcrest argued that the legislation amounted to an
acquisition of property other than on just terms and was thus invalid. One question
for the Court was whether s 51(31) fettered the Commonwealth's power under s 122.
Three judges — Gaudron, Gummow and Kirby JJ — concluded that it did. In
reaching this conclusion, Kirby J called in aid international law and articulated his
interpretative principle.
Kirby J began with the proposition that, "where the Constitution is ambiguous,
[the] High Court should adopt that meaning which conforms to the principles of
fundamental rights rather than an interpretation which would involve a departure from
such rights".
43
This proposition does not, of itself, relate specifically to international
law, but the context of Kirby J's discussion made it clear that international human
rights law was central to the issue. He acknowledged that, where the Constitution is
clear, "the Court must (as in the interpretation of any legislation) give effect to its
terms".
44
The Court should not "adopt an interpretative principle as a means of
introducing, by the backdoor, provisions of international treaties or other international
law concerning fundamental rights not yet incorporated into domestic law".
45
42
(1997) 190 CLR 513.
43
Ibid, 657.
44
Ibid.
45
Ibid.
11
However, he went on to adapt Brennan J's comments from Mabo, quoted in the
Introduction to this paper, to recognise that international law, particularly international
human rights law, is "a legitimate influence on the development of … constitutional
law".
46
Kirby J stated that, "to the extent that its text permits, Australia's Constitution,
as the fundamental law of government in this country, accommodates itself to
international law".
47
In his judgment, Kirby J described the role of international law in the specific
case as "one final consideration which reinforces the view to which I am driven for
[other] reasons".
48
It is also an approach applicable only where there is ambiguity in
the terms of the Constitution — in that sense, international law does not control the
meaning to be given to the text of the Constitution.
Kirby J relied upon Art 17 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
(UDHR) in support of an internationally recognised right to own property and not be
deprived of it arbitrarily.
49
This is an interesting, if not controversial, application of
Kirby J's interpretative principle, as the UDHR is not in its own terms binding on
nations and there is no equivalent of Art 17 in the ICCPR or the ICESCR, which are
binding. And while much of the UDHR is now accepted as reflecting customary
international law, it is by no means universally accepted that the property rights
mentioned in Art 17 have crystallised into a norm of customary international law,
particularly given their absence from the ICCPR and ICESCR,
50
although Kirby J
46
Ibid.
47
Ibid 657–8.
48
Ibid 657.
49
Ibid, 658.
50
See, eg, Richard B. Lillich, International Human Rights: Problems Of Law, Policy And Practice (3rd
ed. 1995) 163ff; Richard B Lillich, "Civil Rights" in Theodor Meron, Human Rights in International Law
(1984) 156, ff; Louis Henkin, Gerald Neuman, Diane Orentlicher and David Leebron, Human Rights
(1999) 1118, 1124. As Henkin et al note, the right to property is included in all the regional human
12
states confidently, but without international authority, that there is such a norm.
51
I
would suggest that, if international law is to be given a more robust role in
constitutional interpretation, then reliance on particular international legal norms
needs to be more rigorous than this.
Kirby J also expounded his interpretative principle in Kartinyeri v
Commonwealth,
52
concerning the interpretation of the races power in s 51(26) of the
Constitution. Again, he used international law to reinforce a conclusion he had
reached on other grounds.
53
The broad statement of the principle was similar to that
in Newcrest, and thus need not be set out in full. Kirby J also noted that to draw on
international law in this way:
Does not involve the spectre, portrayed by some submissions in these
proceedings, of mechanically applying international treaties, made by the
Executive Government of the Commonwealth, and perhaps unincorporated, to
distort the meaning of the Constitution. It does not authorise the creation of
ambiguities by reference to international law where none exist. It is not a
means for remaking the Constitution without the "irksome" involvement of the
people required by s 128.
54
Once again Kirby J emphasised the need for ambiguity before recourse to
international law is appropriate, but had no difficulty discerning ambiguity in relation
to the races power.
55
In this case, Kirby J's use of international law — specifically the
prohibition of discrimination on the basis of race — was more rigorous, as he relied
rights instruments, and it may well be that such a right has now emerged as a norm of customary
international law, but this has certainly been controversial over the years.
51
Newcrest, 660. Kirby J cites the provision of various domestic constitutions in support of his
conclusion. These might provide evidence of state practice, but this is not discussed in detail, and
there is no evidence of opinio juris.
52
(1998) 195 CLR 337.
53
Ibid 417.
54
Ibid 417–8.
55
Ibid 418.
13
upon numerous international treaties and the decision of Judge Tanaka of the
International Court of Justice in the South West Africa Cases (Second Phase).
56
In a series of other cases — Levy v Victoria,
57
Re East; Ex parte Nguyen,
58
Sinanovic v R
59
and Re Minister for Immigration and Multicultural Affairs; Ex parte
Epeabaka
60
— Kirby J made passing reference to the role of international law in
constitutional adjudication. These references might be termed simply "regard
courteous", to use Crawford's term.
61
Or they might be viewed as an attempt to build
up a body of caselaw in support of Kirby J's approach. In any event, they need not
be discussed in detail.
From Kirby J's judgments, one can draw several conclusions about the
application of his interpretative principle. First, there are in my view two different
formulations of the role of international law in constitutional interpretation in Kirby J's
judgments that need to be considered. On the one had, there is the adaptation of
Mabo: the statement that international law is a "legitimate influence on constitutional
law" but that constitutional law does not "necessarily conform with international law".
This approach gives international law a role, but a relatively minor one in most cases
56
[1996] ICJR 3. Kirby J does not acknowledge, however, that Judge Tanaka was in dissent in that
case.
57
(1997) 189 CLR 579, 644–5: "Wherever possible, Australian law on such subjects should be
developed in harmony with such universal international principles to which Australia has given its
concurrence."
58
(1998) 196 CLR 354, 380–1: "Treaties may influence Australian domestic law in other ways. This is
particularly so where they declare fundamental human rights as recognised by international law and
accepted by civilised countries. In such circumstances the provisions of treaties expressing
international law may, by analogy, contribute to judicial reasoning to resolve ambiguities in the
Australian Constitution."
59
(1998) 154 ALR 702, 708: "[C]ourts may be assisted by … universal principles [of international law]
when constitutional or other rights are involved which are ambiguous and which may be made clear by
reference to such principles."
60
(2001) 179 ALR 296, 314: "It is inevitable as the influence of international law spreads, that
decisions on the requirements of [human rights] treaties (and like requirements of regional and
national instruments) will come to influence the interpretation of relevant Australian legislation and
even of the Constitution itself."
14
— there is no imperative to interpret the Constitution consistently with international
law. On the other hand, there is the stronger approach to the use of international
law: that, where there is an ambiguity, the Constitution should be interpreted
consistently with international law. This approach gives international law a more
significant role to play, though it still does not allow international law to override the
clear words of the Constitution. Kirby J does not directly distinguish between these
two approaches, rather he uses them both together.
Second, Kirby J's approach is rights focused — that is, it is concerned with
ensuring that, where the Constitution is ambiguous, it is interpreted so as to protect
fundamental human rights, not to violate them. The content of fundamental human
rights is then ascertained from examining international law, which "expresses
universal and basic rights".
62
This suggests that Kirby J's principle may not extend to
the use of general international law in constitutional interpretation, though this
remains to be tested.
Third, there needs to be an ambiguity before international law can be used in
this way. The clear words or meaning of the Constitution cannot be displaced by
international law. This is consistent with the approach to the uses of international law
in statutory interpretation and also with extensive High Court authority on the
interaction between international law and domestic law beginning with Polites. The
ambiguity cannot be created by reference to international law — it must be otherwise
apparent.
Fourth, it seems to me that international law has not been the determining
factor in Kirby J's judgments — rather, it has been used as an additional legitimating
61
James Crawford, “General International Law and the Common Law: A Decade of Developments”
(1982) 76 Proceedings of the American Society of International Law 232.
62
Kartinyeri, 418.
15
argument to support a conclusion already reached. In this respect, Kirby J's use of
international law is not dissimilar from the uses to which it has been put in previous
cases — what is different is that Kirby J has articulated a principle to guide the use of
international law, rather than simply referring to international law in an ad hoc fashion
where convenient.
Judicial Responses to Kirby J's Approach
There have been few direct responses to Kirby J's new interpretative principle from
the other judges of the High Court. However, in two cases other members of the
Court have expressly rejected the proposition that the Constitution should be
interpreted, so far as its language permits, in conformity with international law. In
Kartinyeri, Gummow and Hayne JJ spent several pages discussing the question.
They noted that, although there is a principle to that effect where statutory
interpretation is concerned, "the legislative powers of the Parliament given by the
Constitution itself stand in a special position".
63
They quoted Dixon J in Polites on
the application of the principle of statutory interpretation to the Constitution itself:
Within the matters placed under its authority, the power of the Parliament was
intended to be supreme and to construe it down by reference to the
presumption is to apply to the establishment of legislative power a rule for the
construction of legislation passed in its exercise. It is nothing to the power that
the Constitution derives its force from an Imperial enactment. It is nonetheless
a Constitution.
64
They also referred to the Court's rejection of international law as a limitation on
legislative power in Horta. Thus because of the special nature of the Constitution,
Gummow and Hayne JJ rejected any interpretative principle that requires the
Constitution to be interpreted consistently with international law. This does not seem
63
Kartinyeri, 384.
64
Polites (1945) 70 CLR 60, 78.
16
to preclude judges from using international law in deciding on the meaning of the
Constitution, and certainly Gummow and Hayne JJ did not suggest that earlier cases
where judges used international law, discussed above, were incorrect in that respect.
But they certainly rejected a robust role for international law in the sense of a
presumption or rule of construction.
Subsequently, in AMS v AIF,
65
Gleeson CJ, McHugh and Gummow JJ
reiterated, more briefly, the comments made in Kartinyeri by Hayne and Gummow JJ.
They stated simply that:
As to the Constitution, its provisions are not to be construed as subject to an
implication said to be derived from international law.
66
Hayne J agreed.
These comments indicate that it is unlikely that a majority of the Court will
adopt Kirby J's approach in the near future. However, in a recent speech McHugh J
seemed to leave room for international law to influence the interpretation of Ch III of
the Constitution in its protection of a right to a fair trial.
67
Thus it may be that a
majority could accept a less robust use for international law — as a legitimate
influence, but without a presumption of conformity. That is, Kirby J's approach may
state the case for international law too highly in so far as it suggests that international
law could be used to compel a particular interpretation. But a lesser role, in simply
providing an additional reason for a particular interpretation, may be acceptable.
This appears to be the way in which earlier judges, including Mason CJ, Deane J,
Brennan J, Dawson J and Gaudron J, used international law in constitutional cases.
65
[1999] HCA 26 (17 June 1999).
66
Ibid para 50.
67
Justice McHugh, "Does Chapter III of the Constitution protect substantive as well as procedural
rights?" (2001) 21 Australian Bar Review 235, 241.
17
Indeed, it is in this way that Kirby J himself appears to have used international law,
rather than in the more robust way his formulation of principle seems to suggest.
III A NORMATIVE ANALYSIS OF THE ROLE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW IN
CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION
It is appropriate to consider the normative question concerning the role that
international law should play in the interpretation of the Constitution, if any. Kirby J
did not engage in extensive consideration of this issue. He primarily asserted that
international law is a legitimate influence on the development of constitutional law.
However, he also stated that:
[T]he Constitution, which is a special statute, does not operate in a vacuum. It
speaks to the people of Australia. But it also speaks to the international
community as the basic law of the Australian nation which is a member of that
community.
68
This appears to be offered as a justification for the use of international law in
constitutional interpretation, although ultimately I do not find it particularly convincing.
The fact that Australia's Constitution "speaks to" the international community as the
basic law of Australia does not logically require that the Constitution be interpreted in
accordance with international law. Rather, it seems to me, the question is to what
extent does international law "speak to" Australian constitutional law?
Gummow and Hayne JJ, in their rejection of Kirby J's approach, did not deal
directly with the normative basis for rejecting international law as an interpretative
tool, but they did make reference to comments of Scalia J in the US context.
69
Scalia
J has rejected reliance upon international law in interpreting the US Constitution,
emphasising that it is American conceptions of decency, not international law or
68
Kartinyeri, 419
69
Ibid 383.
18
values, that must inform the Supreme Court's approach to the Eighth Amendment
(prohibiting cruel and unusual punishment).
70
In this regard, Scalia J in fact departed
from earlier cases where the Supreme Court had used international standards in
determining "evolving standards of decency".
71
It is not clear, however, that
Gummow and Hayne JJ cited Scalia J with approval, as they also referred to the
contrasting practice of the Canadian Supreme Court.
72
What, then are the arguments for and against international law being used in
constitutional interpretation? Arguments against include that made by Scalia J —
that what is paramount in constitutional interpretation are the values of the
community whose constitution is being interpreted, not those of outsiders. I will
return to this issue — to whose values should judges look — later. In the Australian
context, there is also the fact that treaties are entered into by the executive without
any substantive parliamentary involvement
73
and without the possibility of judicial
review.
74
It is thus possible for Australia to enter into a treaty that is illegal under
international law, for example — an example being the Timor Gap Treaty between
Indonesia and Australia, considered by the High Court in Horta. It does not seem to
me to be appropriate that such a treaty should be used to inform constitutional
interpretation. Indeed, the mere fact that the executive has chosen to enter into
70
Stanford v Kentucky 492 US 361, 369 (1989).
71
See, eg, Trop v Dulles 356 US 86 (1958); Estelle v Gamble 429 US 97 (1976), Thompson v
Oklahoma 108 S Ct 2687 (1988), cited in Richard Lillich, "The United States Constitution and
International Human Rights Law" (1990) 3 Harvard Human Rights Journal 53, 77–8.
72
Kartinyeri, 383, referring to R v Rahey [1987] 1 SCR 588 at 633 and to two academic
commentators. Notably, the Canadian use of international law in constitutional interpretation has
largely been confined to interpretation of the Charter, which was enacted in part to give effect to
Canada's international human rights obligations. The use of international law in this way is thus not of
direct relevance to the Australian position.
73
Although the Parliament now has a much greater role in treaty-making than it once had, via the Joint
Standing Committee on Treaties (see Daryl Williams, "Treaties and the Parliamentary Process" (1996)
7 Public Law Review 199), that role does not extend to a power to veto an executive decision to enter
into a treaty.
74
See discussion in Thorpe v Commonwealth of Australia [No 3] (1997) 144 ALR 677, 690.
19
certain contractual arrangements
75
with another nation or nations does not seem of
itself to require any strong principle that the Constitution should be interpreted in
conformity with such arrangements. It is possible to argue that ratification of a treaty
reflects values accepted in Australian society and thus a treaty may be relevant to
constitutional interpretation in that way. This was the approach taken by Gaudron J
to the use of the Convention on the Rights of the Child in Teoh in the area of
administrative law. There her Honour stated that:
The significance of the Convention, in my view, is that it gives expression to a
fundamental human right which is taken for granted by Australian society, in
the sense that it is valued and respected here as in other civilised countries.
And if there were any doubt whether that were so, ratification would tend to
confirm the significance of the right within our society. Given that the
Convention gives rise to an important right valued by the Australian
community, it is reasonable to speak of an expectation that the Convention
would be given effect. However, that may not be so in the case of a treaty or
convention that is not in harmony with community values and expectations.
76
Gaudron J here seems to give primacy to Australian community values, using the
treaty to confirm those values. However, she acknowledges that some treaties may
diverge form Australian community values and, if so, they would not be of use in the
75
Treaties are often described as a "source" of international law as a result of being included in Art
38(1) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice (ICJ). This, it might be argued, means that
treaties are more than simply contractual arrangements between states. However, I disagree with
such an argument. Article 38(1)(a) directs the ICJ to apply various rules of law, including "international
conventions, whether general or particular, establishing rules expressly recognised by the parties". Art
38(1) does not state that treaties are a "source" of law in any general sense, as opposed to a source
of international legal obligation adopted by states through mutual agreement. Thus some
commentators have suggested that use of the term "source" be abandoned: Georg Schwarzenberger,
International Law (3
rd
ed, 1957), vol 1, 27, cited in David Harris, Cases and Materials on International
Law (4
th
ed, 1991) 24. Sir Gerald Fitzmaurice also took the view that treaties "are a source of
obligation rather than law. The law is that the obligation must be carried out, but the obligation is not,
in itself, law.": "Some Problems Regarding the Formal Sources of International Law" (1958) Symbolae
Verzijl 153, cited in Harris, ibid, 46.
Art 38(1)(a) does not negate the fundamental principles governing treaties — in particular, that
treaties bind only the parties to the treaty and create obligations for a state only vis-à-vis other parties.
In this respect, a treaty is aptly described as a contractual obligation between states (See Vienna
Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), Art 34). A treaty to which a state is not a party cannot be
applied by the ICJ to a dispute involving that state under Art 38(1)(a). It is of course possible that a
treaty reflects customary international law and thus non-parties may be bound by a rule included in a
treaty (VCLT, Art 38) — but then non-parties are bound not by the treaty qua treaty, but by the rule of
customary international law.
20
administrative law area. This points up one of the problems with the use of treaties
as an influence on constitutional interpretation — ratification of a treaty by the
executive is no guarantee that the treaty will reflect the values of the Australian
community, though it is possible that the greater involvement of the parliament in the
treaty-making process
77
improves the chances of this being so.
It may be, too, that a distinction should be drawn between bilateral treaties, or
treaties involving only a small number of states, and multilateral treaties involving
many states that can be said to represent the views of the international community,
or a significant sector thereof. I suggest that this distinction will not always easily be
drawn, and that even multilateral treaties are, in a technical sense, simply contractual
arrangements between states. What a multilateral treaty will often do, however, is
reflect or generate customary international law, and it is to the use of customary
international law in constitutional interpretation that I now turn.
I argue that a stronger case for the use of international law in constitutional
interpretation may be made with respect to customary international law than for
treaties. Customary international law — be it in the area of human rights or
elsewhere — is more than a mere contractual arrangement between nations.
Rather, it consists of principles of near universal acceptance, principles derived not
from the mere decision of the executive but from state practice demonstrated over
time, which will include not only executive action but also parliamentary and judicial
action. Thus the relevance of customary international law is in its reflection of
essentially universal values, rather than simply (a) the decision of the executive or (b)
the values of the Australian community.
76
Teoh, 304-5.
77
Discussed at n 73, above.
21
Of course, it might be argued that the use of treaties in the domestic legal
system is of greater legitimacy than the use of customary international law, as
treaties set out obligations voluntarily assumed by Australia. For example, in
Nulyarimma, when dealing with the question whether customary international law
was directly incorporated into Australian law, Wilcox J thought it would be "curious" if
"an international obligation incurred pursuant to customary international law has
greater domestic consequences than an obligation incurred, expressly and
voluntarily, by Australia signing and ratifying an international convention".
78
With
respect, his Honour seems to have overlooked the fact that the reason that treaties
require legislation to have direct effect in Australian law is precisely because they are
entered into by the executive, an arm of government that in our constitutional system
has no independent law-making power. The crucial aspect of customary
international law is that it is not developed through the unilateral action of the
executive and is thus more apt for direct application in Australian law without
legislative transformation. Furthermore, in the context of constitutional interpretation,
the question is not one of direct application but of influence. My argument is that it is
preferable to rely on customary international law as a tool of constitutional
interpretation, as it will reflect the near universal values of the international
community. On the other hand, those treaties that do not reflect customary
international law
79
will reflect only the values of the parties — which could be as few
as two states.
The question remains, of course, as to why internationally accepted values
should be relevant, particularly if they conflict with Australian community values. And
78
Nulyarimma, 162.
79
Treaties that do reflect customary international law will of course be legitimately used under my
approach.
22
if they do not conflict with Australian values, then one may ask what customary
international law adds to the argument. To these questions, two answers may be
made. First, "Australian community values" will be notoriously difficult to
demonstrate, if they indeed exist as a coherent concept; in contrast, customary
international law, while often difficult to prove, is nonetheless proved by way of
objective actions undertaken by states, coupled with a requirement of opinio juris.
80
In that sense, the universal values of customary international law can be ascertained,
while the values of the Australian community may not be able to be ascertained or, if
they can be, may be various and divergent. Second, if it can be satisfactorily
demonstrated that a norm of customary international law exists (and I do not deny
that this can be difficult), then the fact that there is near universal acceptance of such
a norm gives it, I argue, great moral weight that can translate into legal weight in
constitutional interpretation (though only, of course, as an influence, not as a superior
rule of law). Further, as Hughlett argues:
Because the interpretative norm has reached the level of an international rule
of law, the use of the norm decreases the judge's subjectivity in interpreting
constitutional provisions. The international norm is tied to demonstrable state
practice and agreements which articulate the principle.
81
If one accepts this, there remains of course the difficulty of proving the norm of
customary international law in question. Yet in many areas of international law, that
is not difficult. There is general acceptance that genocide is contrary to customary
international law.
82
Likewise there is general acceptance that many articles of the
80
This is the classic formulation of customary international law: see, eg, Continental Shelf (Libyan
Arab Jamahiriya/Malta) [1985] ICJ Rep 1, para 27; Nicaragua v United States (Merits) [1986] ICJ Rep
14, para 184; JG Starke, Introduction to International Law (10th ed, 1989), 35–41.
81
Tamela Hughlett, "International Law: The Use of International Law as a Guide to Interpretation of
the United States Constitution" (1992) 45 Oklahoma Law Review 169, 182.
82
Nulyarimma, above n 13; Mitchell, above n 6, 24–5.
23
UDHR and ICCPR reflect customary international law.
83
It is in this way that many
multilateral treaties become relevant to constitutional interpretation — not as treaties
qua treaties, but as reflections of customary international law. Thus I argue it is
appropriate for domestic courts to have regard to many major international treaties —
including the human rights treaties — in interpreting the Constitution.
There is also the question of how strong a role customary international law
should play in constitutional interpretation. That is, should customary international
law simply be one tool of interpretation among many that can assist the Court in
reaching a conclusion, which seems to be the role that international law has played
to date? Or should there be a stronger principle that, in the case of ambiguity, the
Court should prefer the interpretation that is consistent with customary international
law, as Kirby J suggests? I would suggest that the latter is an appropriate
interpretative principle, one that gives significant weight to customary international
law but does not allow international law to override the clear terms of the
Constitution. If an ambiguity exists, then the judges need some tools to assist them
in deciding what interpretation to prefer. Rules of near universal acceptance in the
international community are a useful way to resolve such a problem — and arguably
more useful that the views of the framers, which reflect views from the 19
th
century.
IV CONCLUSION
International law is of increasing importance in Australian law, though its relevance to
constitutional interpretation is only recently being articulated. Kirby J, in his
interpretative principle is, I argue, building on (though not expressly) existing uses of
international law in constitutional cases. But he is the first judge to have explored in
83
See, eg, Henry Steiner and Philip Alston, International Human Rights in Context (2
nd
ed, 2000) 143.
24
any depth the appropriate role of international law. Other judges have remained
hostile to Kirby J's approach, but I suggest that, in its weaker form, the modified
Mabo statement, that approach reflects what judges have been doing for many years
and may yet gain explicit acceptance.
I also suggest that this is a positive development, at least in relation to
customary international law, which reflects near universal consensus on particular
issues. However, this approach is unlikely to give international law a decisive role in
constitutional cases — rather, it may support conclusions reached on other grounds,
as has occurred to date. What seems unlikely to occur is the judicial acceptance of a
stronger presumption that, in cases of ambiguity, the Constitution should be
interpreted consistently with international law.
25