University of California at Berkeley
School of Law
International Law:
A Compliance Based Theory
by Andrew T. Guzman
UC Berkeley School of Law
Public Law and Legal Theory
Working Paper No. 47
April 2001
UC Berkeley Public Law and
Legal Theory Working Paper Series
UC Berkeley School of Law, Boalt Hall, Berkeley, CA 94720-7200
This paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network Paper Collection at
http://papers.ssrn.com/paper.taf?abstract_id=260257
INTERNATIONAL LAW:
A COMPLIANCE BASED THEORY
Andrew T. Guzman
?
April 2001
?
Assistant Professor of Law, Boalt Hall School of Law, University of
California at Berkeley. I owe thanks to David Caron, Stephen Choi, Jack
Goldsmith, Benedict Kingsbury, Eric Posner, Beth Simmons, John Yoo, and
participants at the Boalt Hall International Law and Politics Workshop for helpful
discussions and comments. Special thanks to Jeannie Sears and Nicholas James.
Ryan Waterman provided excellent research assistance. I am grateful to the John
M. Olin Foundation for financial assistance. Contact: guzman@law.berkeley.edu.
Abstract
This Article examines international law from the perspective of compliance.
Using insights from international relations theory, the Article adopts a theory in which
compliance comes about in a model of rational, self-interested states. Specifically, states
are concerned about both reputational and direct sanctions for their conduct.
The model allows us to consider international law in a new light. Most
strikingly, one is forced to reconsider two of the most fundamental doctrinal points in
the field – the definitions of customary international law (CIL) and of international law
itself. A reputational model of compliance makes it clear that CIL affects the behavior
of a state because other states believe that the first state has a commitment that it must
honor. A failure to honor that commitment hurts a state’s reputation because it signals
that it is prepared to breach its obligations. This implies a definition that turns on the
existence of an obligation in the eyes of other states rather than the conventional
requirements of state practice and a sense of legal obligation felt by the breaching state.
Classical definitions of international law look to two primary sources of law –
treaties and CIL. A reputational theory, however, would label as international law any
commitment that materially alters state incentives. This includes agreements that fall
short of the traditional definition, including what is often referred to as “soft law.” The
Article points out that there is no way to categorize treaties and CIL as “law” without
also including soft law. Agreements such as ministerial accords or memoranda of
understanding represent commitments by a state which, if breached, will have a
reputational impact. For this reason, these soft law agreements should be included in
the definition of international law.
The Article also calls for a refocusing of international law scholarship. Because
international law works through reputational and direct sanctions, we must recognize
that these sanctions have limited force. As a result, international law is more likely to
have an impact on events when the stakes are relatively modest. The implication is that
many of the topics that receive the most attention in international law – the laws of war,
territorial limits, arms agreements, and so on – are unlikely to be affected by
international law. On the other hand, issues such as international economic matters,
environmental issues, and so on, can more easily be affected by international law. This
suggests that the international law academy should focus greater attention on the latter
subjects and less on the former.
INTERNATIONAL LAW: A COMPLIANCE BASED THEORY
I. INTRODUCTION.............................................................................1
II. EXISTING THEORIES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW.................5
A. Traditional Legal Theories ..........................................................6
B. International Relations Theories ................................................13
III. A THEORY OF COMPLIANCE.................................................18
A. A Theory of the Irrelevance of International Law.....................19
B. A Model of International Law ...................................................22
C. Applying the Model – Bilateral Investment Treaties.................29
D. Dynamic Issues ..........................................................................31
E. The Level of Commitment .........................................................34
F. International Law and Coordination ..........................................36
IV. VIOLATION AND COMPLIANCE ...........................................40
A. Reputational Sanctions ..............................................................40
B. Direct Sanctions .........................................................................45
C. When Will Sanctions Work Best? .............................................49
D. Acceptance of Sanctions ............................................................51
V. RETHINKING INTERNATIONAL LAW...................................53
A. Treaties ......................................................................................53
B. A New Definition of Customary International Law ..................54
C. A New Definition of International Law.....................................60
D. Revisiting Existing Theories .....................................................65
E. The Problem of Large Stakes .....................................................68
VI. CONCLUSION ............................................................................72
I. INTRODUCTION
International law scholarship has only just begun to feel the influence of the sort
of interdisciplinary research that has revolutionized much of the legal academy. Starting
with Professor Abbott’s 1989 article, Modern International Relations Theory: A Prospectus
for International Lawyers,1 scholars with interests in international relations and
economics have begun to apply the tools of these other disciplines to international law.2
The resulting scholarship has presented international law in a new light, and posed new
challenges for traditional international law scholars.
Most legal scholars and practitioners believe that international law matters in
the sense that it affects the behavior of states.3 Conventional theories advanced by legal
scholars, however, are considered flawed because they are difficult to reconcile with
modern international relations theory, rely heavily on axiomatic claims about national
behavior, and lack a coherent theory of compliance with international law. It is fair to
say that most conventional international law scholarship does not ask why there is
compliance but rather simply assumes as much.4 International relations theory, on the
other hand, offers a set of competing theories and a more satisfying account of national
behavior. These theories are often skeptical of the role international law has to play in
1 Kenneth W. Abbott, Modern International Relations Theory: A Prospectus for International
Lawyers, 14 YALE J. INT’L L. 335 (1989) (hereinafter Prospectus).
2 The most prominent interdisciplinary articles include Kenneth W. Abbott, International
Relations Theory, International Law, and the Regime Governing Atrocities in Internal Conflicts, 93 AM. J. INT’L
L. 361 (1999); Anne-Marie Slaughter, Andrew S. Tulumello & Stepan Wood, International Law and
International Relations Theory: A New Generations of Interdisciplinary Scholarship, 93 AM. J. INT’L L. 367
(1998); Anne-Marie Slaughter Burley, International Law and International Relations Theory: A Dual Agenda,
87 AM. J. INT’L L. 205 (1993); Jack L. Goldsmith & Eric A. Posner, A Theory of Customary International
Law, 66 U. CHI. L. REV. 1113 (1999); Jeffrey L. Dunoff & Joel P. Trachtman, Economic Analysis of
International Law, 24 YALE J. INT’L L. 1 (1999); John K. Setear, An Iterative Perspective on Treaties: A
Synthesis of International Relations Theory and International Law, 37 HARV. J. INT’L L. 139 (1996); Harold
H. Koh, Why Do Nations Obey International Law?, 106 YALE L.J. 2599 (1997); John K. Setear, Responses to
Breach of a Treaty and Rationalist International Relations Theory: The Rules of Release and Remediation in the
Law of Treaties and the Law of State Responsibility, 83 VA. L. REV. 1 (1997); Edwin M. Smith,
Understanding Dynamic Obligations: Arms Control Agreements, 64 S. CAL. L. REV. 1549 (1991). In
addition, a recent issue of INTERNATIONAL ORGANIZATIONS (Summer 2000) is devoted to an
international relations approach to questions of international law.
3 See LOUIS HENKIN, HOW NATIONS BEHAVE 46-48 (1979); Abram Chayes & Antonia Chayes,
On Compliance, 47 INT’L ORG. 175, 176 (1993).
4 See e.g., ABRAM CHAYES & ANTONIA HANDLER CHAYES, THE NEW SOVEREIGNTY:
COMPLIANCE WITH INTERNATIONAL REGULATORY AGREEMENTS 3 (1995) (“foreign policy practitioners
operate on the assumption of a general propensity of states to comply with international obligations”).
Compliance-Based Theory
2
the governance of the international system,5 and often ignore “international law”
altogether.6
To date, neither conventional international law scholars, nor those adopting an
international relations approach, has presented a satisfactory model that is capable of
explaining why states comply with international law in some circumstances and violate
it in others.7 International law scholarship assumes a high level of compliance and
provides little theoretical framework within which to examine the compliance decision
while international relations scholars largely ignore the role of international law in
national decision making. The failure to understand the compliance decision is
troubling because compliance is one of the most central questions in international law.
Without a theory of compliance, we cannot examine the role of treaties, customary
international law, of other agreements. Nor can we consider how to improve the
functioning of the international legal system, or develop a workable theory of
international legal and regulatory cooperation.
This Article uses the insights of international relations scholarship to address the
question of compliance. Unlike traditional international law scholarship, the Article
adopts a comprehensive theory in which compliance with international law comes about
in a model of rational, self-interested states. Compliance exists because states are
concerned with the reputational implications and the direct sanctions of violating the
law. The model explains not only why nations comply, but also why and when they
violate international law. Using the tools of international relations theory and
5 See Beth A. Simmons, Money and the Law: Why Comply with the Public International Law of
Money?, 25 YALE J. INT’L L. 323, 323-24 (2000) (“[L]egal scholars and practitioners believe that the rules
at the center of their analysis do indeed matter . . . . Scholars of international relations . . . have been far
more skeptical.”); George W. Downs, et. al., Is the Good News About Compliance Good News About
Cooperation?, 50 INT’L ORG. 379 (1996).
6 See MICHAEL BYERS, CUSTOM, POWER AND THE POWER OF RULES: INTERNATIONAL
RELATIONS AND CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW 8 (1999) (“International Relations scholars have
traditionally had little time for such questions. Instead, they have regarded international law as
something of an epiphenomena, with rules of international law being dependent on power, subject to
short-term alteration by power-applying states, and therefore of little relevance to how states actually
behave.” )
7 See, e.g., Robert O. Keohane, International Relations and International Law: Two Optics, 38
HARV. INT’L L. J. 487, 491 (1997) (“We do not yet have a well-specified or empirically tested
instrumentalist theory of compliance with international commitments.”); Beth A. Simmons, Compliance
with International Agreements, 1 ANN. REV. POL. SCI. 75, 76 (1998) (“far less attention has been devoted
to understanding why governments actually comply with such agreements.”); Koh, supra note 2, at 2599
(“Why do nations obey international law? This remains among the most perplexing questions in
international relations.”); Thomas M. Franck, Legitimacy in the International System, 82 AM. J. INT’L L. 705,
705 (1988) (“The surprising thing about international law is that nations ever obey its strictures or carry
our its mandates.”); Benedict Kingsbury, The Concept of Compliance as a Function of Competing Conceptions
of International Law, 19 MICH. J. INT’L L. 345, 345 (1998) (“‘Compliance’ is one of the central concepts in
current and proposed research projects using social science methods to study the effect and significance of
international law.”).
Compliance-Based Theory
3
economics, the article focuses explicitly on international law, explaining why countries
care about it, and why they will expend resources in order to avoid violating it (or being
perceived to violate it).
The Article offers a reply to critics who argue that international law does not
matter. To the extent those arguments are based on a theoretical claim, this Article
demonstrates that it is possible to construct a theory of rational self-interested states in
which international law does, in fact, matter. Because the model is consistent with both
conventional wisdom and empirical evidence showing that international law matters,8 as
well as the observation that the law is sometimes violated, it offers support to the
longstanding claims of international legal scholars that international law affects the
behavior of states.
On the other hand, the model also raises fundamental questions about
international law as it is currently studied. By taking the question of compliance
seriously, we gain a new perspective on international law, and that new perspective
forces us to question some of the central issues in international law.
First, the analysis suggests the need for a new definition of customary
international law (CIL). The existing definition of CIL has been the subject of a great
deal of criticism, and some have gone so far as to suggest that no such law exists.9
Rather than attempting to salvage the traditional definition, this Article proposes a new
one that focuses on whether or not a rule of customary international law affects
behavior. It is shown that the requirements of widespread state practice and a sense of
legal obligation do not contribute to a useful understanding of CIL. By studying CIL
within a reputational model, and with a focus on compliance, it is possible to achieve a
deeper understanding of that form of international law.
Second, the Article proposes a new, functional definition of international law.
Once international law is considered from the perspective of compliance, it is clear that
the classical definition of “international law” is under-inclusive, and should be
broadened to include not only treaties and customary international law, but also
agreements such as ministerial accords, memoranda of understanding, and so on. Like
treaties and customary international law, these instruments affect the incentives of
countries and, therefore, should be considered international law. Including them allows
us to study the full range of international obligations within a single theoretical
framework, and, unlike traditional theories, explains why such agreements exist and why
they are so popular.
Third, it is demonstrated that international law is most likely to affect outcomes
when there are many repeated interactions and each of those interactions involves
8 See, e.g., Beth A. Simmons, Money and the Law: Why Comply with the Public International Law of
Money, 25 YALE J. INT’L L. 323 (presenting empirical evidence that international law impacts government
behavior).
9 See infra V.B.
Compliance-Based Theory
4
relatively small stakes. Although this claim is not new, it leads to the conclusion that
the topics which have traditionally held center stage in international law -- such as the
laws of war, neutrality, arms control, and so on -- are precisely the topics in which
international law is least likely to be relevant. This conclusion has two lessons for
international law scholarship. The first is that international law scholarship may be
unduly focused on these topics. The fact they are arguably the most important issues in
international relations does not imply that they should form the centerpiece of
international law because international law will often be unable to affect outcomes.
Scholars may have a greater impact on human well-being if they devote more energy to
areas in which international law can alter outcomes more reliably. These include a
range of important areas including economic issues, environmental issues, labor issues,
and so on. The second, somewhat more subtle, lesson is that the study of these issues,
and the design of international institutions should proceed with an understanding of the
limits of international law. International law can play a role in encouraging cooperation,
but can only do so if obligations are structured in a fashion that reduces the importance
of each compliance decision. For example, an arms treaty, by itself may have little
success but a treaty that provides for periodic inspections by a neutral third party may
stand a much greater chance of achieving the goal of arms control.
Fourth, it is shown that sanctions for violations of international law are generally
not optimal. Because sanctions consist primarily of weak military or economic
punishment and reputational losses, they are often too weak to achieve optimal
compliance.10 Under certain circumstances, however, sanctions can be rationalized and
states can be given better incentives. In particular, states can at times be induced to
voluntarily submit to dispute resolution procedures and accept sanctions. This is
possible where a failure to accept a sanction leads to an even greater loss. The Article
discusses the circumstance in which that can occur, and how international interactions
can be structured to encourage it.
Understanding how to encourage participation in dispute resolution procedures
sheds light on the role of international organizations. These bodies have an important
role because they can be used to coordinate international interactions in such a way as
to increase the likelihood that states will submit themselves to the authority of dispute
resolution bodies. The obvious example of this sort of behavior is seen at the World
Trade Organization (WTO). Although certainly not a flawless process, the WTO is
able to resolve disputes among members and impose sanctions closer to the optimal
level.
In summary, the Article seeks to address both critics and proponents of
international law. It demonstrates to critics that the existence of international law does
not present a theoretical problem, and that attacks on the discipline that proceed from a
10 See Chayes & Chayes, supra note 4, at 29-33. Even when they are effective, direct punitive
sanctions such as embargoes may at time be too harsh, which also fails to generate optimal compliance.
Compliance-Based Theory
5
theoretical perspective are not persuasive. On the other hand, the Article
acknowledges that some of the views held by international law scholars are inconsistent
with a theoretical model in which international law matters. It demonstrates to
proponents of international law that we must devote greater attention to the
compliance question, and we must rethink much of the discipline if we are to provide a
coherent response to the claim that international law is irrelevant.
The Article proceeds as follows. Part II discusses the most prominent theories of
international law from both traditional legal scholarship and international relations
perspectives. Part III presents the model of compliance. Any theory of compliance
must come to terms with the fact that international law, however that terms is defined,
has virtually no enforcement mechanism.11 When a state violates international law
there are few formal procedures through which other countries can invoke sanctions.12
That is not to say, however, that the violation of international law is without cost. Two
costs are of central importance and will be the focus of this Article. First, following a
country’s breach of an international obligation, other states may choose to impose some
form of sanction. This may range from criticism of the offending state to economic or
even military sanction. The second cost of violating an international obligation is
reputational. If a country violates international law, other states may refuse to enter
into future agreements, may demand greater concessions when entering into such
agreements, or may lose faith in the strength of existing agreements.
Part IV presents a detailed discussion of how reputational and direct sanctions
affect states and how the magnitude of those sanctions changes depending on the
circumstances of the violation. Part V develops some of the implications of the theory,
explaining how it affects our understanding of treaties and customary international law
and explaining why the definition of international law should be expanded. The
interaction of this theory of compliance with other theories of international law is also
explored. Finally, the Article discusses the fact that some of the traditional topics of
interest to international legal scholars are unlikely to be affected by international law,
and calls for a refocusing of scholarship on other areas, where international law can
have a greater impact.
II. EXISTING THEORIES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW
Compliance is central to international law and its role in regulating the
interaction of nations. Unless international law provides an incentive toward
11 See Franck, supra note 7, at 707 (“Why should rules, unsupported by an effective structure of
coercion comparable to a national police force, nevertheless elicit so much compliance, even against
perceived self-interest, on the part of sovereign states?”).
12 See ABRAM CHAYES & ANTONIA HANDLER CHAYES, THE NEW SOVEREIGNTY: COMPLIANCE
WITH INTERNATIONAL REGULATORY AGREEMENTS 2-3; 29-108 (discussing the weakness of punitive
sanctions for violation of international law).
Compliance-Based Theory
6
compliance, the time, energy and other resources devoted to the creation and
maintenance of international legal structures is wasted and the study of that subject is a
futile endeavor that should be abandoned. Despite the fundamental importance of the
compliance question, and the deep faith that international legal scholars have in the
importance of international law, the legal academy has failed to develop a satisfactory
theory to explain it. This Part presents the most prominent attempts of the
international law literature to explain compliance. It also presents theories from
international relations that have begun to filter into the international law literature,
including the institutionalist theory that this article builds upon.
A. Traditional Legal Theories13
Although a great deal of ink has been spilled in the discussion of international
law and its impact on states, international legal scholarship still lacks a satisfactory
theory of compliance.14 This section presents four prominent theories advanced by legal
scholars. The first, the managerial model, is a useful and well reasoned theory, but only
applies to that subset of international agreements that resolve coordination problems.
The remaining three theories are less useful and really do not offer sufficient theoretical
structure to further our understanding of international law and compliance.
1. The Managerial Model
Perhaps the most satisfying of the traditional legal theories of international law
and compliance is provided by Chayes & Chayes.15 They argue that the “enforcement
model” of compliance – in which compliance is achieved through coercive mechanisms
such as sanctions – should be replaced with what they term the managerial model,
which relies primarily on “a cooperative, problem-solving approach.”16 Chayes &
Chayes claim that states have a general propensity to comply with international law that
is the product of three factors. First, compliance avoids the need to recalculate the costs
and benefits of a decision, and therefore, saves transaction costs, generating an
efficiency based rationale for compliance.17 Second, they argue that treaties are
consent-based instruments that, therefore, serve the interests of the participating
states.18 Finally, they argue that compliance is furthered by a general norm of
compliance.
13 For an account of “ancient and primitive” international law, which predates the traditional
views described herein, see Koh, supra note 2, at 2604-2606 and corresponding notes.
14 See Dunoff & Trachtman, supra note 2, at 28 (“Past efforts to identify an underlying structure
for the law of treaties have proven unsatisfactory”). Koh, supra note 2, at 2599-2560; Setear, supra note
2, at 147 (criticizing two theoretical justifications for the law of treaties).
15 See supra note 12.
16 Id. at 3.
17 See id. at 4.
18 “[I]f the agreement is well designed – sensible, comprehensible, and with a practical eye to
probable patterns of conduct and interaction – compliance problems and enforcement issues are likely to
Compliance-Based Theory
7
The managerial model presents a thoughtful and useful account of a certain class
of treaties, but falls short of a general theory of compliance or a complete description of
international legal agreements. The Chayes & Chayes model provides a satisfying
account of agreements designed to resolve coordination problems, but does explain how
international law assists in other situations.
In the case of coordination games, it is true that states are likely to comply with
an agreement if it is well specified. If that is the case, Chayes & Chayes are correct that
there is no need to focus on enforcement. Resources are better directed at the sort of
managerial issues that they recommend, including transparency to ensure successful
coordination,19 dispute settlement,20 and capacity building.21 Each of these techniques,
as described by Chayes & Chayes, assists coordination efforts.
The managerial model, however, is less useful when considering the use of
international law beyond coordination games. Consider first the explanation of why
nations comply with the law. Although it is true that transactions costs are saved
through a rule of compliance, these costs are not likely to be large and, in any event,
there are many other strategies that can lead to similar cost savings. For example, a
better strategy from the perspective of a state would be to make its compliance decisions
based on the available evidence without any presumption in favor or against
compliance. This would maximize the probability of making the appropriate choice, and
avoid transaction costs. Other strategies would be better still. In general the best
strategy is to invest in information gathering until the marginal cost of additional
information is equal to the marginal benefit of that information in terms of its effect on
the probability of making the correct choice and the cost of a mistake. Once the
optimal amount of information is gathered, the optimal strategy is to base the decision
on that information without a presumption in favor of compliance.
The second explanation for compliance is the consent based theory which is
discussed in Part II.A.2 below. As is stated in that section, the consent theory cannot
explain why state behavior would be influenced by the existence of an international
legal obligation.
Finally, Chayes & Chayes makes a general appeal to norms in order to explain
compliance. The claim that a norm exists in favor of compliance, however, is little more
than an assertion that nations comply with the law. It provides no theoretical
explanation, and is not helpful in understanding state behavior.
be manageable. If issues of noncompliance and enforcement are endemic, the real problem is likely to be
that the negotiating process did not succeed in incorporating a broad enough range of the parties
interests.” Id. at 7.
19 See id. at 135-153.
20 See id. at 201-225.
21 See id. at 197-201.
Compliance-Based Theory
8
Because the managerial model envisions a coordination game, the proposed
strategies to enhance compliance are not helpful in other contexts. For example,
Chayes & Chayes believe that dispute resolution is a useful feature and can enhance
compliance. They do not believe, however that dispute resolution needs to be
mandatory or that there must be binding sanctions for a failure to comply. Their view of
dispute resolution is supported by a belief that a failure to comply is the result of a
mistake or a lack of communication. If that is true, dispute settlement only needs to
serve as a forum in which information is shared and expectations clarified. In fact, more
can be said under the managerial model. Because states are modeled as cooperative,
there is no need for binding law of any kind. Simple statements if interest and intent,
without any notion of commitment are enough to resolve most coordination games.
There is, therefore, no need for international law, as conceived by this model, to be
“binding” or irrevocable. It is precisely because states do not have to be compelled to
act in a particular way that dispute resolution does not have to be compulsory or backed
by sanctions.
When a state violates the law because the law is contrary to its interests,
however, this form of dispute resolution will fail. When the parties interests are at odds
– as is true in instances of intentional violation – negotiations are conducted “in the
shadow” of the ultimate sanction for violation. In the absence of such sanctions, the
offending party has no incentive to accept a negotiated solution that involves any
punishment or constraint on future behavior. This, in turn, implies that the law
provides no incentive to comply. If one makes the dispute resolution mandatory, on the
other hand, and provides some form of sanction for a failure to comply with the ruling, it
is possible to increase compliance even outside of coordination games.
The managerial model, then, is a useful but incomplete model of international
agreements and compliance. As long as one is only interested in coordination games, it
provides a good guide to compliance and national behavior. If one seeks to understand
games in which states’ make agreements that call upon them to act against their own
interests in exchange for concessions from other states, a different model is needed.
That model is advanced in this Article.
2. Consent and Treaties
The most commonly held rationale for the relevance of international law, and
especially treaties, to national conduct is based on the notion of consent.22 The
consent-based argument begins with the claim that sovereign states are not subject to
22 See Setear, Iterative Perspective, supra note 2, at 156; Smith, supra note 2, at 1565-66. Though
most frequently discussed in the context of treaties, the use of consent as an explanation for the binding
character of international law is also present in discussions of customary international law. See BYERS,
supra note 6, at 7 (1999); M. O. Chibundu, Making Customary International Law Through Municipal
Adjudication: A Structural Inquiry, 39 VA. J. INT'L L. 1069, 1122 (1999).
Compliance-Based Theory
9
any obligation unless they have consented to it.23 For example, Louis Henkin states that
“a state is not subject to any external authority unless it has voluntarily consented to
such authority.”24 This claim is easily reconciled with the law of treaties which includes
detailed rules concerning the question of consent and whether it has been given.25 The
second, and more problematic, step in the consent-based theory invokes the oft-
repeated statement that treaties are to be obeyed.26 Proponents of a consent-based view
argue that consent to be bound generates a legal obligation and causes states to comply
with those obligations.
Critics of the consent-based theory argue that it cannot explain why
international law is binding because it fails to explain why it prevents nations from
simply withdrawing their consent.27 Treaties are of limited use if it is not possible for a
nation to make an irrevocable commitment. Like domestic contracts, treaties are much
more powerful if the law provides a mechanism for such commitments. In the absence
of an ability to commit, a nation could simply withdraw its consent from any treaty
found to be inconvenient. A consent-based view, therefore, might lead one to conclude
that, as a theoretical matter, treaties should have no effect because nations need only
comply when they would comply in the absence of the treaty.28 Although often
repeated, this criticism is itself unsatisfactory. If one can assert that consent is enough
to bind states, why can it not be similarly asserted that it is possible to consent to
irrevocable commitments?29
The real problem with a consent-based view lies not with a state’s ability to
withdraw consent, but with the theory’s failure to explain compliance. The theory
states that consent creates a binding obligation, but it fails to tell us what makes the
obligation binding. There is no explanation of why states comply.
23 “The rules binding upon states therefore emanate from their own free will . . . . Restrictions
upon the independence of states cannot therefore be presumed” S.S. Lotus Case, 1927 P.C.I.J. (ser. A)
No. 10, at 18.
24 Louis Henkin, International Law: Politics, Values and Functions, 216 RECUEIL DES COURS
D’ACADEMIE DE DROIT INTERNATIONAL 27 (1989).
25 See Setear, Iterative Perspective, supra note 2, at 156-157 nn 71-79.
26 See Vienna Convention, art. 26 (“Every treaty in force is binding upon the parties to it and
must be performed by them in good faith.”); Abram Chayes & Antonia Chayes, On Compliance, 47 INT’L
ORG.175, 185 (1993) (“It is often said that the fundamental norm of international law is pacta sunt
servanda (treaties are to be obeyed).”).
27 This criticism is widespread, and will not be elaborated in detail here. More complete versions
of the criticism can be found in Smith, see supra note 2; Setear, Iterative Perspective, supra note 2, at 160;
JAMES L. BRIERLY, THE LAW OF NATIONS: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE INTERNATIONAL LAW OF PEACE
51-54 (H. Walcock ed., 6th ed. 1963).
28 This is a slight exaggeration because even a treaty that can be revoked at will is useful to
resolve coordination games.
29 Accord Setear, Iterative Perspectives, supra note 2, at 161 (“I see nothing casuistic in the
argument that parties to a treaty consent not only to particular terms but also to the general notion that
their consent must not be withdrawn.”).
Compliance-Based Theory
10
Justifications for the consent-based approach fail because they confuse a
(possibly) necessary condition for states to be bound with a sufficient condition. It is
observed that states are only bound when they consent to be bound. This initial
presumption, even if it is assumed to be correct,30 does not lead to the conclusion that
the provision of consent is enough to bind a state. Consent by itself does not provide
states with an incentive to obey the law. The standard rendition of the consent theory
fails to address this point. Rather, advocates of the theory simply recite the maxim that
“treaties are to be obeyed.”31 This statement, however, is either devoid of content or
assumes the conclusion. If the statement is read to mean that treaties should be obeyed,
as a normative matter, it says nothing about how states will actually behave. If, on the
other hand, it is read to mean that states do, in fact, obey treaties, then it is simply
assuming compliance without explanation.
Thus, even if consent is thought to be an important element in the
establishment of an international obligation, it offers no explanation for compliance. In
addition to consent there must be some force that causes states to comply with the
obligations to which they have consented. Because it fails to explain why the behavior
of nations is changed by international law, the consent theory cannot claim to be a
satisfactory explanation of compliance.
3. Legitimacy Theory
Thomas Franck has advanced a general theory of international law that has
come to be known as legitimacy theory.32 The theory attempts to explain why nations
feel compelled to honor their promises. Unlike consent theory, legitimacy theory
attempts to go beyond the statement that treaties are to be obeyed and seeks to explain
why nations might obey them. In the end, however, that attempt takes the inquiry no
further than does consent theory. The fundamental premise underlying legitimacy
theory is that states obey rules that they perceive to have “come into being in
accordance with the right process.”33
Franck argues that four factors determine whether a state complies with
international obligations. These factors are determinacy, symbolic validation,
coherence, and adherence.34 Where these four factors are present, legitimacy theory
predicts a strong pressure toward compliance, and where they are absent it predicts a
very limited impetus to compliance.35
30 I will argue below that it is not quite accurate. See infra Part III.E (discussing how states can be
“bound” by informal agreements, custom, and practice).
31 See supra note 26.
32 Franck, supra note 2; THOMAS M. FRANCK, FAIRNESS IN INTERNATIONAL LAW AND
INSTITUTIONS (1995).
33 Frank, supra note 7, at 706.
34 See FRANCK, supra note 32, at 49.
35 In more general terms, Franck describes legitimacy as “a property of a rule . . . which itself
exerts a pull toward compliance . . . because those addressed believe that the rule or institution has come
Compliance-Based Theory
11
In brief, determinacy refers to the clarity of the rule or norm;36 symbolic
validation refers to the presence of procedural practices or rituals that provide a rule
with symbolic importance and legitimacy;37 coherence refers to the connection between
rational principles and the rule; 38 and adherence refers to the connection between the
rule and those secondary rules used to interpret and apply the primary rule.39
Legitimacy theory does not, however, adequately explain why states do or should
care about legitimacy. It leaves too many of the central questions regarding compliance
and national behavior in the black box of “legitimacy.” The claim that nations violate
international rules because of the “perceived lack of legitimacy of the actual or proposed
rules themselves and of the rule-making and rule-applying institutions of the
international system” begs the question. Why should we expect nations to honor rules
that enjoy legitimacy while ignoring others? In any event, the claim that legitimacy is
the driving force behind compliance is an assertion, rather than the result of a
theoretical framework or empirical study.40
Despite its attempt to identify the reasons for compliance, legitimacy theory fails
for the same reason that the consent based theory fails – it does not provide a model of
compliance so much as an assertion that nations obey the law. It fails to explain why
“legitimacy” leads to compliance, why the four factors discussed by Franck are
important, how they interact with other measures of a nation’s self-interest, and why we
see states violating laws with which they had previously complied. The concept of
legitimacy in this theory, like the bald assertion that treaties are to be obeyed, begs the
question of why states comply with international law.41
4. Transnational Legal Process
Professor Harold Koh has advanced another theory of international law, termed
transnational legal process. The theory focuses on how public and private actors
interact in various fora at both the domestic and international level to make, interpret,
enforce, and internalize rules of transnational law.42
into being and operates in accordance with generally accepted principles of right process.” FRANCK, supra
note 32 at 24-25.
36 See id. at 52.
37 See id. at 90-95.
38 See id. at 150-53.
39 See id. at 184.
40 “To the extent rules exhibit [legitimacy] they appear to exert a strong pull on states to comply
with their commands. To the extent [legitimacy is] not present, rules seem to be easier to avoid by a state
tempted to pursue its short-term self-interest.” Franck, supra note 7, at 712. Notice here that Franck
implies the existence of a tension between a states self-interest and its willingness to comply. In the
model presented in this Article, states always act in their own self-interest.
41 Additional criticisms of legitimacy theory have been advanced elsewhere. Among the
complaints are claims that the four factors involved are vague and difficult to evaluate, and that the
theory does not tell us how to aggregate them. See Koh, supra note 2, at 2541-2645.
42 See Harold H. Koh, Transnational Legal Process, 75 NEBRASKA L. REV. 181, 183-84 (1994);
Compliance-Based Theory
12
Professor Koh criticizes rational actor models of international law for their failure
to incorporate the role of non-state actors. Rather than treating states as unitary actors,
transnational legal process looks to a wider set of decision makers to explain conduct,
including multinational corporations, non-governmental organizations, international
organizations, private individuals, and others. Professor Koh argues that as
transnational actors – including both state and non-state actors – interact, patterns of
behavior and norms emerge which are internalized by the actors. The internalization of
these norms leads to their incorporation within the domestic legal institutions of states
which, in turn, leads to compliance.43
The transnational legal process claim can be divided into two components. The
first is the claim that domestic legal institutions play a critical role. This claim is
certainly correct. There is no doubt that the actual decision of whether or not to
comply with or violate international law is made by domestic institutions. Nor is there
any doubt that domestic politics matter to the compliance question. The extent to
which a state complies with international law is influenced by domestic interest groups,
the power of the executive relative to the legislature, the electoral cycle, the state of the
domestic economy, and so on.44
The second claim of the transnational legal process theory is that domestic
institutions somehow internalize transnational legal norms and that this leads to
compliance. It is here that the theory becomes problematic. It has no explanation of
why certain legal norms are internalized or how this internalization takes place. Even if
one assumes, like Professor Koh, that international legal norms are internalized, one
would expect domestic legal norms – in particular the norm of pursuing the interests of
domestic decision makers – to be internalized more readily. When international legal
norms are at odds with the self-interest of the state, it is difficult to explain why the
international norms would triumph. If domestic concerns triumph, however, the
internalization of legal norms has no impact on outcomes.
In addition, it appears to be assumed that repeated interaction leads to the
internalization of norms that are consistent with international law, but this assumption
is not explained. It seems equally plausible that the internalized norms are unrelated to
international law. For example, rather than internalize norms of international law,
transnational actors might internalize the norm that powerful nations triumph over
weaker nations, or that economic influence resolves international disputes.
Koh, supra note 2.
43 See Koh, Legal Process, supra note 42, at 204 (“It is through this repeated process of interaction
and internalization that international law acquires its “stickiness,” that nation-states acquire their
identity, and that nations define promoting the rule of international law as part of their national self-
interest.”)
44 See Part II.B.3.
Compliance-Based Theory
13
Without an understanding of why domestic actors internalize norms of
compliance in the international arena, and a theory of why this internalization tends
toward compliance, the theory lacks force.45 Like the consent based approach and
legitimacy theory, the transnational legal process approach is ultimately founded on as
unsupported assumption that the law is followed. It differs from the prior theories in
that it considers the relevant unit of analysis to be individuals and interest groups rather
that the state, but then simply asserts that these actors follow international law.
Without a more complete theory of why these actors follow the law, the theory remains
unsatisfactory. Attempts to rescue the theory by arguing that law-abiding behavior is
internalized because domestic institutions and actors observe the compliance of foreign
states and foreign transnational actors is simply to assume the existence of compliance
rather than explain it.
Perhaps the most serious problem with the theory is that it does not provide any
real theoretical structure. Ultimately, it is simply an assertion that internalization takes
place and leads to compliance. Without a proper theoretical apparatus, the theory
cannot explain why a particular legal norm may be respected in one context and ignored
in another. Nor does it provide a model of decision making by the state.46 Without
such a model, the theory cannot be applied to produce predictions about when states
will comply with the law and when they will not, nor can it offer strategies to increase
the level of compliance. Finally, because the theory boils down to a simple assertion
about national behavior, it cannot explain why some states are considered law-abiding
while others are considered pariahs. In fact, the theory suggests just the opposite – it
suggests that states will move inexorably toward greater compliance.47
B. International Relations Theories
Although traditional approaches to legal scholarship remain common, in recent
years a new approach has emerged to challenge the traditional methodology. This
approach comes primarily from political science and the theory of international
relations, although it also has roots in the economics literature.48 A detailed taxonomy
and review of the international relations literature is beyond the scope of this paper.
Instead, this section offers a thumbnail sketch of the most relevant schools of thought.49
45 The assumption that states internalize a norm of compliance with international law is, in some
sense, an assumption of the very conduct that the theory seeks to explain.
46 In fact, because the theory recognizes that state decisions are actually the result of an internal
political process, what is needed is a public choice theory of state action.
47 “The process of interaction and internalization in turn leads a national government to engage
in new modes of interest-recognition and identity-formation in a way that eventually leads the nation-
state back into compliance.” Koh, Legal Process, supra note 42.
48 See supra note 1.
49 Professor Abbott has usefully categorized the international relations literature. See Abbott,
Prospectus, supra note 1.
Compliance-Based Theory
14
1. Neo-Realists
Neo-realist theory, an outgrowth of classical realism,50 treats states as unitary
actors and the relevant unit in international relations. Under these assumptions,
international cooperation will exist only when it is in the interest of the affected states.
The interests of states are believed to be power and security, and power is considered to
be the primary influence on international behavior.51 Concerns about power and
security cause states to focus not only on the absolute gains they might make from
cooperation, but also on the relative gains. This is so because a state is always
concerned that even if it gains from cooperation, another state may gain even more –
making that other state a greater potential security threat. This concern makes states
reluctant to engage in cooperation when its partners stand to gain more than it does.
The conclusion of this literature, at least for some scholars, is that international
law has little or no independent impact on the behavior of states.52 Compliance with
international law is explained as a coincidence between international law – whose
content is said to be largely controlled by powerful states in any event – and the self-
interest of nations.53 International law, therefore, is simply an epiphenomenon.
Criticism of neorealism can be found in the international relations literature, and
it serves no purpose to reproduce all of that criticism here. For present purposes it is
sufficient to simply identify some of the difficulties with adopting a realist perspective on
international law.54
The realist conclusion that international law is irrelevant is difficult to reconcile
with the observation that a great deal of time, energy, and money are spent in order to
create international law. For example, the Uruguay Round negotiations that led to the
establishment of the WTO lasted eight years and consumed enormous resources. It also
affected the political fortunes of governments around the world. If it is the case that
international law does not matter, why did states devote so many resources to these
negotiations? Just as rational individuals would not expend resources in order to
50 For a discussion of classical realism, see E.H. CARR, THE TWENTY YEAR CRISIS 1919-1939;
GEORGE F. KENNAN, AMERICAN DIPLOMACY 1900-1950 (1951); HANS J. MORGENTHAU, POLITICS
AMONG NATIONS: THE STRUGGLE FOR POWER AND PEACE (1948); Hans J. Morgenthau, Positivism,
Functionalism, and International Law, 34 AMER. J. INT’L L. 260 (1940).
51 See Joseph M. Grieco, Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest
Liberal Institutionalism, 42 International Organization (1988).
52 See F.A. Boyle, The Irrelevance of International Law, CALIF. WEST. INT’L L. J. 10 (1980); R.H.
Bork, The Limits of ‘International Law,’ 18 NATIONAL INTEREST 3 (1989-90).
53 See STEPHEN D. KRASNER, SOVEREIGNTY: ORGANIZED HYPOCRISY (199); Abbott, supra note 2,
at 364-65; Slaughter Burley, supra note 2, at 217 (“For Waltz, norms of any sort, qua norms, lacked
independent causal force.”). Hans Morgenthau, one of the great realists, conceded that international law
is generally observed, but considered this to be the result of either power relations or convergent interests.
See Simmons, supra note 7, at 79.
54 For detailed discussion of the problems with neo-realism see NEOREALISM AND ITS CRITICS
(Robert O. Keohane, ed. 1986).
Compliance-Based Theory
15
complete a contract that has no effect on behavior, there is no reason to think that
states would spend resources in order to complete treaties and other agreements that
have no impact on states. Nor would states or non-state actors expend resources in
order to influence the status of customary international law, as has been done in such
fields as foreign investment,55 human rights,56 and environmental law.57 In addition,
when it is claimed that a law has been violated (though it is not clear why anyone would
even bother to make such a claim), states would have no reason to proclaim their
innocence as they so often do.58 Furthermore, empirical and anecdotal evidence has
begun to emerge indicating that international law does, indeed, influence state
behavior.59
2. Institutionalist Theory
The second important category of international relations theories is that of
institutionalists.60 Like neorealism, institutionalism views states as the primary
international actors and treats them as rational unitary agents interacting in an
anarchical world.61 Furthermore, like neorealism, institutionalism takes a game
55 See Andrew T. Guzman, Why LDCs Sign Treaties that Hurt Them: Explaining the Popularity of
Bilateral Investment Treaties, 38 VA. J. INT’L . 639. 644-51 (1998).
56 FRANK NEWMAN & DAVID WEISSBRODT, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS LAW, POLICY,
AND PROCESS 18 (2d ed. 1996).
57 See THE IMPLEMENTATION AND EFFECTIVENESS OF INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENTAL
COMMITMENTS: THEORY AND PRACTICE (David G. Victor, et al. eds., 1998).
58 See LOUIS HENKIN, HOW NATIONS BEHAVE 43 (“While nations, generally, still deny that they
are violating international law, often the denial merely falsifies the facts.”)
59 See, e.g., Beth A. Simmons, Money and the Law: Why Comply with the Public International Law of
Money?, 25 YALE J. INT’L L. 323, 327 (2000) (presenting an empirical study of state compliance with IMF
obligations and concluding that “international law has a significant impact on governments’ behavior.”);
Stephen M. Schwebel, Commentary, in COMPLIANCE WITH JUDGMENTS OF INTERNATIONAL COURTS 39,
39 (M.K. Bulterman & M. Kuijer eds., 1996) (arguing that states tend to comply with the decisions of
international tribunals.); Ronald B. Mitchell, Compliance with International Treaties: Lessons from
Intentional Oil Pollution, 37 ENVIRONMENT 10 (1995).
60 See Abbott, Atrocities, supra note 2, at 365. Among the important and useful institutionalist
contributions are Duncan Snidal, The Game Theory of International Politics, 30 WORLD POL. 25 (1985);
Duncan Snidal, The Limits of Hegemonic Stability Theory, 39 INT’L ORG. 579 (1985); Duncan Snidal,
Coordination Versus Prisoners’ Dilemma: Implications for International Cooperation and Regimes, 79 AM. POL.
SCI. REV. 923 (1985); Arthur Stein, Coordination and Collaboration: Regimes in an Anarchic World, 36
INT’L ORG. 299 (1982); Robert Jervis, Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma, 30 WORLD POL. 167
(1978); Robert Jervis, Security Regimes, 36 INT’L ORG. 357 (1982); Kenneth Oye, Explaining Cooperation
Under Anarchy: Hypotheses and Strategies, 38 WORLD POL. 1 (1985);, COOPERATION UNDER ANARCHY
(Kenneth Oye ed., 1986); Stephan Haggard & Beth Simmons, Theories of International Regimes, 41 INT’L
ORG. 491 (1987).
61 See Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation 3 (1984); Robert Axelrod & Robert O.
Keohane, Achieving Cooperation Under Anarchy: Strategies and Institutions, 38 WORLD POLITICS 226, 226
(1985). Many, and perhaps most institutionalists recognize that state decisions are the product of a
domestic political process in which different interests compete for influence. Nevertheless, like this
Article, institutionalists usually model the state as a single actor in order to simplify the analysis. See
Compliance-Based Theory
16
theoretic approach to the study of international relations. This approach has significant
promise for the study of international law, but it has yet to be widely applied by
international law scholars.62
Unlike neo-realists, however, institutionalists believe that international
cooperation is possible, and that international institutions can play a role in facilitating
that cooperation. They argue that these institutions can help states overcome prisoner’s
dilemma type problems that are often faced in international affairs. Specifically,
institutionalists argue that institutions can reduce verification costs in international
affairs, reduce the cost of punishing cheaters, and increase the repeated nature of games
– all of which make cooperation more likely.
This Article is in the institutionalist tradition in the sense that it argues that the
institution of international law can play a role in influencing state behavior. It adopts a
basic repeated game model of national behavior to demonstrate that international law
can influence states. It is assumed that states are independent and that they act only in
their own self-interest, consistent with both neorealism and institutionalism. Unlike
most institutionalist discussions of international law, however, treaties do not represent
the exclusive focus of the Article.63 Although treaties represent an important
component of the international law that is being explained, many other forms of
cooperation are also addressed.
An institutionalist approach to international law not only reveals that
international law matters more than realists claim, it also reveals that it matters less
than many international law scholars seem to assume. It is shown that international law
represents a force in state behavior, but one that is of limited power, and that is much
more likely to affect outcomes in some cases than in others. As a result, international
law scholars must take a fresh look at their discipline, reconsider the role of
international law in contributing to international order, and reevaluate the manner in
which international law is deployed by states.
3. Liberal Theories
A third international relations theory, known as liberal theory,64 focuses on the
interest group dynamics within each state. The liberal theory begins with the
assumption that the key actors for the study of international relations are individuals
and private groups, rather than states. Accordingly, the theory is interested in the
Abbott, Governing Atrocities, supra note 2, at 365.
62 The theory has begun to find its way into the legal literature. See supra note 2.
63 See Abbott, Governing Atrocities, supra note 2, at 366 (“In practice, though, institutionalist
scholarship focuses on treaties.”).
64 See Andrew Moravcsik, Taking Preferences Seriously: A Liberal Theory of International Politics, 51
INT’L ORG. 513 (1997); Anne-Marie Slaughter, International Law in a World of Liberal States, 6 EUR. J.
INT’L L. 503 (1995); Anne-Marie Slaughter, The Liberal Agenda for Peace: International Relations Theory
and the Future of the United Nations, 4 TRANSNAT’L L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 377 (1995).
Compliance-Based Theory
17
particulars of domestic politics in addition to the interaction of states. A focus on sub-
national entities leads to the study of institutions such as courts, legislatures, and
administrative agencies.65 Although a more realistic view than the state-actor approach
of realists and most institutionalists, the liberal approach leads to a much more complex
methodology.
The most prominent advocate of the liberal theory within the legal academy is
Professor Anne-Marie Slaughter. She argues that compliance with international law is
determined in significant part by the domestic structure of a country. She claims that
states with a “liberal” structure, by which is meant representative government,
protection of civil and political rights, and a judicial system guided by the rule of law,
tend to follow international law, at least among themselves.66
Liberal theories of international law, like public choice theories in the study of
domestic law, are hampered by the complexity of a model that rejects the assumption of
unitary state actors. An examination of compliance within a liberal framework is really
an examination of the domestic politics of countries that might lead to a decision to
comply with international law. The problem is that interactions among domestic
interest groups are unpredictable and the results may not be stable over time. Because
of the complexity of interest group politics, it is difficult to generate predictions about
how nations behave.67 Instead, the constitutional and political realities of each country
must be considered. The problem with liberal theories, then, is that they are overly
complex. Because they are better suited to positive accounts of behavior rather than
predictions, they do not lead to a general model of compliance.68
Although this Article does not adopt a liberal approach, it is not in conflict with
that school. The theory advanced here and the liberal school are best viewed as
complementary.69 The assumption herein is that states are unitary actors engaged in the
pursuit of national goals. Left unspecified are the particular goals of the country.
Liberal theory is one way of studying these goals. Thus, one can view liberal theory as a
methodology whose output – the policy desires of states – is used as an input for the
theory of compliance presented here.
65 See Laurence R. Helfer & Anne-Marie Slaughter, Toward a Theory of Effective Supranational
Adjudication, 107 YALE L.J. 273 (1997).
66 See Anne-Marie Burley, Law Among Liberal States: Liberal Internationalism and the Act of State
Doctrine, 92 COLUM. L. REV. 1907, 1920-21 (1992); Slaughter Burley, Dual Agenda, supra note 2;
Slaughter, supra note 64.
67 See ROBERT O. KEOHANE, AFTER HEGEMONY: COOPERATION AND DISCORD IN THE WORLD
POLITICAL ECONOMY 25 (1984) (“Parsimonious theory, even as a partial ‘first cut,’ becomes impossible if
one starts analysis [at the sub-national level], amidst a confusing plethora of seemingly relevant facts.”).
It should, however, be noted that liberal theorists are attempting to generate general theoretical claims
despite the challenge of doing so within a liberal model. See Helfer & Slaughter, supra note 65.
68 The complexity of liberal theories, of course, is an asset in certain circumstances – such as
attempts to explain the results of case studies.
69 See Part V.D.2.
Compliance-Based Theory
18
III. A THEORY OF COMPLIANCE
This Part presents the basic theory of compliance with international law. A
good theory should be able to explain both instances of compliance and instances of
breach. As discussed in the previous Part, traditional legal theories of compliance with
international law do not provide a constructive way to think about compliance in part
because they cannot explain instances of breach. On the other hand, a model also must
be able to explain how international law can act as an independent force toward
compliance. Realists do not deny that nations often act in a manner that is consistent
with international law. They argue that the existence of international law has no effect
on national behavior and that instances of “compliance” are merely cases in which the
nation’s policy happens to be consistent with international law. A model of compliance
in which international law matters, therefore, must explain how national behavior is
changed by the existence of the law. The presentation of the model proceeds in two
steps. First, a one period model is developed in which international law is irrelevant.
The assumption of a single period is then relaxed and it is shown how in a model with
repeated play one can develop a theory in which international law matters.
The model makes standard assumptions about government behavior. It is
assumed that states are rational and act in their own self-interest, and that they are
aware of the impact of international law on behavior.70 Notice that although it is
assumed that states act in a self-interested fashion, no assumption is made regarding the
way in which states identify their self-interest. The traditional way of modeling national
interest is to assume that the government pursues the public interest. An alternative
view, public choice theory views government decisions as the product of interest group
politics and argues that these decisions will not, in general, lead to behavior that is
consistent with the national interest. Under this public choice or liberal view, decision
makers are modeled as individuals pursuing their own objectives rather than as the
faithful agents of their constituencies.71 The advantage of a public choice approach is its
ability to provide a positive account of government activity that is difficult to explain
through more traditional models of government behavior.72 The difficulty in applying
public choice to normative analyses, however, is that the outcome of interest group
politics is very difficult to predict.73 For the purposes of this article it is not necessary to
70 See Abbott, Prospectus, supra note 1, at 349; ROBERT O. KEOHANE, AFTER HEGEMONY:
COOPERATION AND DISCORD IN THE WORLD POLITICAL ECONOMY 27 (1984).
71 See Michael E. Levine & Jennifer L. Forrence, Regulatory Capture, Public Interest, and the Public
Agenda, 6 J.L. ECON. & ORG. 167 (special issue 1990) (“[Public choice] analysts postulate that people
should be expected to act no less rationally or self-interestedly as politicians or bureaucrats than they do
in the course of their private exchanges in markets.”); George J. Stigler, The Theory of Economic
Regulation, 2 BELL J. ECON. & MGMT. SCI. 3 (1971); DANIEL A. FARBER & PHILLIP F. FRICKEY, LAW &
PUBLIC CHOICE: A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION 17 (1991).
72 See Part V.D.2..
73 See Abbott, Prospectus, supra note 1; Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2.
Compliance-Based Theory
19
choose between the public interest and public choice models. This is so because the
Article does not attempt to model the process by which national goals are determined.
Rather, national goals are assumed to be given and the model explains the conditions
under which the pursuit of such goals leads to compliance with international law. For
this reason, the Article can accommodate both theories of government behavior.74
A. A Theory of the Irrelevance of International Law
The first step in understanding the theory of compliance with international law
is to understand a theory of the irrelevance of international law. This is so because the
simplest rational actor model of country behavior leads to the conclusion that
international law does not matter. Just such a model is presented in this section. Once
that basic model is understood, it is possible to identify the assumptions of the model
that lead to the irrelevance result. By relaxing those assumptions, as is done in the next
section, a model of compliance is generated in which international law matters.
The most basic model of country behavior is a one-shot game in which states
decide whether or not to comply with a particular rule of international law.75 For
concreteness, suppose that two countries have agreed to a ban on satellite-based
weapons and the decision at hand is whether or not to comply with the ban.
Assume that each country is better off if it violates the agreement while the
other country complies. Furthermore, assume that both are better off if they both
comply than if they both violate. This situation is represented in Figure I. The game is
simply the prisoner’s dilemma and the well known equilibrium is for both countries to
violate their international obligation.
74 See infra Part V.D.2.
75 The basics of game theory are available in many other sources, and will not be repeated here.
For relevant discussions in the context of international law, see Setear, supra note 2; Abbott, Prospectus,
supra note 1; Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2. For more comprehensive presentations of game theory,
see DOUGLAS G. BAIRD, ROBERT H. GERTNER, & RANDALL C. PICKER, GAME THEORY AND THE LAW
(1994); ERIC RASMUSSEN, GAMES AND INFORMATION: AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY (1989);
DREW FUDENBERG & JEAN TIROLE, GAME THEORY (1991),
Compliance-Based Theory
20
Figure I76
Country 2
Comply Violate
Comply 5,5 2,6
Country 1
Violate 6,2 3,3
If Figure I is an accurate depiction of international relations, however, we would
expect to see a world of chaos in which there is no cooperation and no compliance with
international law. Such an observation is clearly at odds with what we observe in the
world because, as observed by Louis Henkin, “almost all nations observe almost all
principles of international law and almost all of their obligations almost all of the
time.”77 International law scholars have cited the widespread compliance with
international commitments as evidence that international law matters.
A simple extension of the above model, however, shows that a high level of
compliance need not imply that international law affects national behavior. Adding an
additional round to the game explains how countries can regularly act in a manner that
is consistent with their international obligations even if those obligations have no
impact on state behavior.
Imagine that the above game is unchanged, but that it represents only a sub-
game, meaning a portion of a larger game. In the larger game, there is an initial period
in which the state of nature is determined. Assume that there are two possible states of
nature, which are labeled “good” and “bad.”78 The bad state of nature is represented by
Figure I and the above discussion. In the example of a treaty regulating the
development of space-based weapons the bad state corresponds to a situation in which
76 The first entry in each cell represents the payoff to country 1 while the second entry represents
the payoff to country 2.
77 HENKIN, supra note 58, at 47.
78 Limiting the number of states to two makes the exposition simpler, but does not affect the
results.
Compliance-Based Theory
21
the parties have an incentive to develop space-based weapons because, for example,
doing so enhances their security.
The good state corresponds to the situation in which the parties have an
incentive to comply with the treaty provisions independently of their international
obligation. Imagine, for example, that the technology for the construction of a satellite-
based weapons system is too primitive to make the system effective and the cost is
prohibitive, making it a poor use of government resources. In this situation, neither
party would develop satellite-based weapons, even if there were no treaty in force.
Figure II represents the good state, in which the treaty is irrelevant.
Figure II
Country 2
Comply Violate
Comply 10,10 6,8
Country 1
Violate 8,6 4,4
In Figure II, if both countries violate the treaty they are both worse off because,
for example, they will have spent a large sum of money for a system that is unreliable. If
Country One violates the treaty, that country is worse off as a result of the money spent
and the other country also suffers a loss because even an unreliable weapons system in
the hands of a potential enemy is undesirable. If both comply with the treaty, however,
both enjoy the maximum possible payoff. More importantly, compliance is the
dominant strategy for both parties. Regardless of the action taken by the other party,
each country is better of if it complies with the treaty.
Combining the good and bad outcomes yields a theory of national behavior that
is consistent with the observation that countries obey their international obligations
much of the time. The analysis is also consistent with the view that international law
does not matter. Rather than consider international law, countries simply do what is in
their interest. Sometimes this happens to be consistent with their international
obligations and other times it is not, but the existence of an obligation plays no role in
Compliance-Based Theory
22
the outcome. This model – in which international law is irrelevant – has been advanced
by the neo-realist school in international relations.79
The above model has the merit of being simple and elegant, and is able to
explain instances of both observed compliance with international obligations and
violations thereof. The theory cannot, however, explain other observed behavior. It
cannot explain, for example, why countries conclude treaties in the first place. The
negotiation of international treaties and other international legal instruments consumes
resources that could be used in other ways. If international law does not have any
impact on behavior, there is no reason for a country to waste resources on international
legal conventions and negotiations. The same funds, human capital, and political
energy could be devoted to other governmental objectives. Nor can it explain why
countries invest resources to demonstrate that they are in compliance with international
law. If international law has no impact on behavior, countries should ignore it. What
we observe, however, is attempts by countries to justify their actions under international
law. The model also fails to explain the existence of international law dispute resolution
processes to which nations sometimes submit their disputes. If international law does
not matter, there is no reason for such procedures. Finally, the theory is contradicted by
empirical data suggesting that international law does, indeed, influence state behavior.80
B. A Model of International Law
In a finitely repeated prisoner’s dilemma, like that presented in the previous
section, the irrelevance of international law is inevitable. By adopting a finitely repeated
game, one ensures that the equilibrium in a prisoner’s dilemma context is defection.
This amounts to an assumption that cooperation will fail and that international law does
not matter.
In a domestic setting even one shot prisoner’s dilemmas can yield the
cooperative outcome through the use of contract. Imagine, for example, that two
individuals agree to swap vacation homes for the summer. They each agree to care for
the other’s home, including certain regular maintenance chores. While on vacation,
however, maintenance is time consuming, expensive, and boring, so there is an
incentive to avoid doing so. The standard prisoner’s dilemma model predicts that
neither party will honor their promise to care for the other’s home. If, however, the
agreement is enforceable, then a party that fails to do so must pay damages. If the
damages are high enough, both parties can be induced to carry out the promised
maintenance. The prisoner’s dilemma is solved by the addition of a penalty for the party
that fails to honor its obligation. In other words, law changes the payoffs received by the
parties. To change the equilibrium, the penalty must change the payoffs enough to
make cooperation a dominant strategy for each party.
79 See supra Part II.B.1.
80 See supra note 59.
Compliance-Based Theory
23
Just as compliance with promises at the domestic level requires the existence of
damages, a model of compliance with international law requires a mechanism through
which nations are sanctioned for violations thereof. The finitely repeated game of the
previous section can generate a model of effective international law only if there exists
an entity that can credibly commit to sanctioning those who violate international law,
much like courts sanction domestic violations.
Those who argue that international law has little or no impact on national
behavior, therefore, are actually making the claim that the existing penalties for a
violation of international law are insufficient to change the equilibrium of the game. As
mentioned, the use of a finitely repeated game without a coercive compliance
mechanism, is equivalent to assuming that result.
To generate a model in which international law matters, then, it is necessary to
identify a mechanism through which violations are sanctioned in some fashion. Even
those who believe that international law plays an important role in regulating conduct
in the international community must concede that there is at best a weak system of
meting out punishments for violations of law. Nevertheless, a model of international
law must turn on the impact of sanctions on states.81 It is important to note, however,
that the term sanction as used above encompasses more than just direct punishments
resulting from a failure to live up to one’s international obligations. It includes all costs
associated with such a failure, including the punishment or retaliation by other states
and reputational costs that affect a state’s ability to make commitments in the future.
To take the role of reputation into account, we adopt an infinitely repeated
game model.82 Before laying out the model in detail, it is useful to remember one of the
most basic elements of contract theory. It is well established that in the absence of
transaction costs, parties to a contract will generally negotiate to the most efficient
outcome.83 This implies that the best possible rule – both for individuals in the domestic
context and for states in the international context – is to give the parties complete
freedom of contract, including the ability to make irrevocable commitments. In the
domestic setting, the power to commit oneself exists because the courts stand ready to
enforce contracts. In the international setting, states must rely on the imperfect system
81 If one relaxes the assumption of a rational state that is pursuing the national interest, the
model could also turn on the consequences of violations on interest groups and decision makers. See Part
V.D.2.
82 International relations theorists are aware of how an infinitely repeated game can affect the
analysis and have used such models to advance theories of international cooperation. The model
presented here resembles some of these theories. See Michael Taylor, The Possibility of Cooperation
(1987); KEOHANE, supra note 70, at 75. Others have used infinitely repeated games to model
international law, though not in the way it is used here. See Duncan Snidal, Coordination Versus Prisoners’
Dilemma: Implications for International Cooperation and Regimes, 79 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 923 (1985);
Duncan Snidal, The Game Theory of International Politics, 38 WORLD POL. 226 (1985); Setear, Iterative
Perspective, supra note 2.
83 See A. MITCHELL POLINSKY, AN INTRODUCTION TO LAW AND ECONOMICS 31 (1989).
Compliance-Based Theory
24
of international sanctions and reputational effects. Recognizing that states are not able
to make fully irrevocable commitments, it is clear that the greater a state’s ability to
commit itself, the better off it is.84
The model of international law used in this Article operates as follows. Any
given international obligation is modeled as a two-stage game. In the first stage, states
negotiate over the content of the law and the level of commitment.85 In the second
stage, states decide whether or not to comply with their international obligations.
A state’s compliance decision is made based on an assessment of its self-interest.
That self-interest can be affected by international law in two ways. First, it can lead to
the imposition of direct sanctions – such as trade, military, or diplomatic sanctions.86
Second, it can lead to a loss of reputational capital in the international arena.87 If the
direct and reputational costs of violating international law are outweighed by the
benefits thereof, a state will violate that law.
Figure III presents the international law game. In the first period, states decide
whether or not to enter into a legal obligation. For present purposes, an obligation is
defined as a promise to other states. Put aside for the moment the precise form of the
promise, which could be a treaty, an informal agreement, customary international law,
or any other forms of promise. If no promise is made, the state is free to engage in
whatever conduct it chooses in period 2 without suffering any sanction. In period 2 the
state of the world is revealed. In the “good” state, the interests of the relevant countries
converge and those that comply with the agreement receive a higher payoff than if they
had violated the agreement. As a result, all countries comply and each receives a payoff
of 10 in this period and 10 in each period thereafter.88 Letting “r” represent the
84 There are some circumstances in which the ability to commit may be harmful. For example, a
country that is being asked by an ally to promise military aid in the event of war may be better off if it is
simply unable to make such a commitment because it can then avoid the risk of involvement in a war
without angering the requesting country. An inability to commit, however, is only beneficial in
exceptional cases. As a general matter states, like private parties, are better off if they are able to make
irrevocable commitments.
85 The term “negotiate” is used as a shorthand. This stage represents the decision of one or more
countries to enter into an international agreement, regardless of whether the terms of that agreement are
bargained over at the time. For example, in the case of customary international law, there is no process of
formal negotiations. Nevertheless, a country can seek to reduce its obligation by remaining a persistent
objector. Another example would be the decision by a state to join (or not join) an existing agreement.
For example, if Poland were invited to join the EU, its decision to accept or decline the invitation would
qualify as “negotiation” for present purposes.
86 It can also lead to a sanction through formal dispute settlement mechanisms, such as those of
the WTO. Under appropriate circumstances, these sanctions are especially likely to be successful, as is
discussed infra Part IV.B.
87 I am not the first to identify reputation as an important issue in international law. See HENKIN,
supra note 58, at 46-59 (listing factors in a country’s decision to observe international law, including
reputational consequences); Keohane, supra note 7, at 496-499.
88 For simplicity it is assumed that the state of the world does not change after the first period.
Compliance-Based Theory
25
discount rate – that is, the extent to which the country values benefits today over
benefits later – each country receives a payoff stream of 10 + 10/(1+r) + 10(1+r)2 +
…. = 10(1+r)/r.89 To simplify further, let R=(1+r)/r. We can then represent the
payoff to each country as 10R. In the good state countries behave in the same way
whether there is an agreement or not, indicating that international law does not affect
the behavior of states.
[FIGURE III GOES HERE]
If the countries find themselves in the “bad” state, however, they face a
prisoner’s dilemma. If there is no agreement in place, countries behave in a non-
cooperative fashion (they “defect” in game theoretic parlance), and receive the
corresponding payoff of 3 in this period and every period thereafter, which translates
into a total payoff of 3R. This is the realist result, presented in Figure I and the
accompanying discussion, which leads to the conclusion that international law has no
effect.
Now consider how reputation can alter the equilibrium. For simplicity, begin by
assuming that countries will only enter into agreements with countries that have a good
reputation. A good reputation is maintained as long as a country honors all its previous
international commitments. A country that has a good reputation stands to earn a
payoff of 5 in the current period by complying with its international obligation, and a
payoff of 5 in each future period (assuming the other country also complies). If the state
violates its commitment, while the other country complies, it earns 6 in the current
period and three in each period thereafter.90 Thus, the country must choose between
two possible payoff streams:
If it continues to comply: 5 + 5/(1+r) + 5/(1+r)2 + ….
If it does not comply: 6 + 3/(1+r) + 3/(1+r)2 + ….
Put another way, if an agreement is in place, “cheating” carries with it a
reputational sanction. In the example given, we can represent the subgame in which
the parties are in the bad state of the world and have a legal obligation as follows:
89 Calculation of the payoffs in Figures III and IV is straightforward once it is recognized that x +
x/(1+r) + x/(1+r)2 + … = x(1+r)/r.
90 That is, it earns 6 in this period because the other party complies while it violates the
agreement, but in each period thereafter there is no agreement in place so both parties defect and the
country earns 3.
Compliance-Based Theory
26
Figure IV
Country 2
Comply Violate
Comply 5R, 5R 3R-1, 3 + 3R
Country 1
Violate 3+3R, 3R -1 3R, 3R
The payoff to a country that cheats, therefore, is 3+3R91 if the other country
complies and 3R if the other country cheats. The payoff for a country that complies is
5R if the other country complies and 3R-1 if the other country violates the law.
Figure IV demonstrates how the reputational effect of a violation alters the
decision process. An equilibrium in which both countries comply in every period is
sustainable in this game for a sufficiently low discount rate (corresponding to a
sufficiently large R). In other words, for a sufficiently low discount rate a country will
comply with its international obligation even when it would not have done so in the
absence of that obligation. It complies in order to avoid the reputational loss that would
come with a violation of international law.
Reputation, therefore, causes future relationships to be affected by today’s
actions.92 A decision to violate international law will increase today’s payoff but reduce
tomorrow’s. Notice that this model does not merely explain why nations comply with
international law despite the weakness of existing enforcement mechanisms. It also
explains why they sometimes choose to violate the law. Unlike some existing theories of
international law, it is able to reconcile the claim that international law affects behavior
with the fact that the law is not always followed. The existence of a reputational effect
impacts country incentives, but in some instances that impact will be insufficient to alter
country behavior.
The use of numbers in the above examples and throughout the Article should
not be taken to imply that the calculation of costs and benefits takes place in an
91 Note that because R=(1+r)/r, R is always greater than 1.
92 The impact of direct sanctions are put to the side for the moment. These also increase the
cost of violating international law and provide an additional incentive to comply.
Compliance-Based Theory
27
environment of great certainty. Because reputational sanctions (and, indeed, non-
reputational ones) are uncertain, it is rarely the case that one can predict the precise
consequences of an action. This fact does not, however, undermine the theory
presented. It is the role of the decision maker to assess these future costs and benefits
before choosing a course of action.93 The subjective nature of this process is one reason
why the identity of national leaders is important.
In the absence of other enforcement mechanisms, then, a state’s commitment is
only as strong as its reputation. In entering into an international commitment, a
country offers its reputation for living up to its commitments as a form of collateral.94
The value of that collateral, of course, varies from country to country. It may also vary
depending on the identity of the country on the other side of the agreement. Thus, for
example, a treaty between Canada and the United States benefits from a very high level
of reputation and trust. The two countries have a long history of cooperative dealings,
and to violate a promise would have a negative effect on many other interactions. As a
result, the violation of a treaty commitment between the countries requires that the
benefits from such a violation be extremely high. A treaty between the United States
and Iraq, on the other hand, would enjoy a lower level of reputational collateral. Iraq,
and Saddam Hussein in particular, is not considered a reliable treaty partners – in large
part because of earlier violations of international legal commitments.95
A country that develops a reputation for compliance with international
obligations signals to other countries that it is cooperative. This action allows the state
to enjoy long-term relationships with other cooperative states. Among the benefits are
both a greater ability to make binding promises and a reduction in the perceived need
for monitoring and verification. The development of a reputation for compliance,
therefore, provides benefits to a country. A failure to live up to one’s commitments
harms one’s reputation and makes future commitments less credible. As a result,
potential partners are less willing to offer concession in exchange for a promised course
of action.96 For example, during the early negotiations prior to the Uruguay Round of
93 In more formal terms, the decision maker uses the available information in order to determine
the probability distribution of costs and benefits. Based on that probability distribution the expected costs
and benefits can be determined.
94 See KEOHANE, supra note 70, at 26 (“International regimes alter the information available to
governments and the opportunities open to them; commitments made to support such institutions can
only be broken at a cost to reputation. International regimes therefore change the calculations of
advantage that governments make.”)
95 The invasion of Kuwait is the most obvious such violation, but it is not the only one. The
continued refusal to honor the terms of the peace agreement that followed the Persian Gulf War, the
perception that Iraq has sponsored international terrorist activity, and earlier treaty violations such as the
1981 unilateral “cancellation” of the 1975 border agreement between Iran and Iraq all represent instances
in which Iraq has shown itself to be an unreliable partner. See UNITED NATIONS, YEARBOOK OF THE
UNITED NATIONS, 1981, vol. 35 (United Nations 1985) at 238-39.
96 See Simmons, Law of Money, supra note 5, at 325 (“Governments comply with their legal
commitments largely to preserve their reputation.”).
Compliance-Based Theory
28
trade talks, the United States and other western states faced resistance to the idea of
expanding GATT’s authority because those countries were not honoring their existing
commitments.97 Similarly, when the United States government abducted Mexican
citizens in violation of international law in the Alvarez-Machain incident,98 the
negotiations of the NAFTA agreement were negatively affected.99
The point here is that a country’s reputation has value, and a country will
hesitate before compromising that reputation. If a country suffers a loss of reputation, it
must rebuild the reputation by demonstrating a pattern of compliance with international
law. If a country’s reputation is sufficiently tarnished, of course, attempts to rebuild the
reputation may not be worthwhile.100
It is worth noting that the development of a strong reputation for compliance
with international agreements is, itself, subject to a cost-benefit analysis by nations. The
development and destruction of a reputation occurs over longer periods of time than do
individual decisions regarding compliance with an obligation, but they are nevertheless
the result of government decisions.
Nothing in the theory advanced in this Article suggests that all countries will
want to preserve a reputation for honoring their commitments. Countries that decide
against developing a strong reputation for compliance with international obligations
choose short-term benefits over long-term gains. Those countries are more likely to
ignore international commitments and, as a result, are less likely to find partners willing
to rely on such commitments. In the extreme case of a country that has zero
97 See RAY AUGUST, INTERNATIONAL BUSINESS LAW 359 (2000).
98 United States v. Alvarez-Machain, 504 U.S. 655 (1992).
99 See Koh, supra note 42, at 203. In this example it may be the case that the reaction of
Mexican authorities was a form of retaliation rather than a reaction to a change in the reputation of the
United States. Even if this is true, however, reputation is in the background because the reason to
retaliate for misconduct by the U.S. is to establish a reputation for such retaliation in the hope of
influencing future behavior. For a discussion of Alvarez-Machain see William J. Aceves, The Legality Of
Transborder Abductions: A Study Of United States v. Alvarez-Machain, 3 SW. J.L. & TRADE AM. 101
(1996); Andrew L. Strauss, A Global Paradigm Shattered: The Jurisdictional Nihilism of the Supreme Court's
Abduction Decision in Alvarez-Machain, 67 TEMP. L. REV. 1209 (1994); Kristin Berdan Weissman,
Comment, Extraterritorial Abduction: The Endangerment of Future Peace, 27 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 459
(1994); Manuel R. Angulo & James D. Reardon, Jr., The Apparent Political and Administrative Expediency
Exception Established by the Supreme Court in United States v. Humberto Alvarez-Machain to the Rule of Law
as Reflected by Recognized Principles of International Law, 16 B.C. INT'L & COMP. L. REV. 245 (1993).
100 I should note at this point that international legal scholars have long understood that
reputation matters. Although the effect of reputational constraints have not been explored as formally
and fully as this Article tries to do, one can find comments scattered throughout the international law
literature implying that these scholars understood all along that reputation and repeat play were
important in the international legal system. See, e.g., Ian Johnstone, Treaty Interpretation: The Authority of
Interpretive Communities, 12 MICH. J. INT’L L. 371 (1991) (reprinted in INTERNATIONAL LAW ANTHOLOGY
121 (Anthony D’Amato, ed. 1994) (“Because all states have a stake in maintaining a reputation for good
faith compliance with treaty commitments, they will hesitate before publicly announcing a construction
likely to be branded as improper or far-fetched.”).
Compliance-Based Theory
29
reputational capital, international law acts as an independent force only to the extent
that it generates direct sanctions, as discussed in Part IV.B.
Finally, note that reputation, when examined in all its dimensions, need not
always be a force toward compliance with international law. Nations prefer a reputation
for compliance with international law so that they are better able to bind themselves in
the future, but they are also concerned about other aspects of their reputation. For
example, a reputation of siding with allies can be valuable, as can a reputation for
toughness.101 For example, during the Cold War, the United States at various times
sought to establish a reputation for adherence to a policy of containment of
communism. Such forces can provide incentives either for or against compliance,
depending on the circumstances. These other aspects of reputation, therefore, must be
taken into account when considering the compliance question. This observation does
nothing to undermine the theory being advanced as long as it is recognized that this
Article focuses on only one aspect of reputation. Rather than undermine the theory,
this point reminds us that the reputational issues discussed herein have limited force –
they cannot prevent all violations of international law and in some circumstances, may
not prevent any such violations.102
C. Applying the Model – Bilateral Investment Treaties
The reputational theory of international law can be applied to a wide range of
state behavior. For reasons discussed below, it predicts that international law will have a
greater impact on economic matters than on military and security matters.103 To
illustrate how the theory can be applied to a specific topic, this section discusses bilateral
investment treaties (BITs) and how they affect country behavior.104
Consider a country that has signed a BIT in which it promises not to expropriate
foreign investment.105 Assume for the purposes of this example that the country makes
this promise because doing so increases the flow of foreign direct investment into the
country.106 Even after making the promise, of course, the country could choose to
101 See Keohane, Two Optics, supra note 7, at 497; Kingsbury, supra note 7, at 352-53.
102 See Part V.E, discussing circumstances in which international law is unlikely to have
substantial effect.
103 See Part V.E.
104 For a detailed discussion of BITs, see Andrew T. Guzman, Why LDCs Sign Treaties that Hurt
Them: Explaining the Popularity of Bilateral Investment Treaties, 38 VA. J. INT’L L. 639 (1998); Kenneth J.
Vandevelde, U.S. Bilateral Investment Treaties: The Second Wave, 14 MICH. J. INT’L L. 621 (1993).
105 Other examples could obviously be chosen here. Bilateral investment treaties are selected
because the costs and benefits are more easily understood and evaluated in the context of such treaties
than in many other examples. It is important to note, however, that difficulty expressing costs and
benefits in dollar terms does not represent a problem for the theory presented.
106 The expropriation of foreign owned assets occurred numerous times in the twentieth century.
Some examples include the Mexican expropriation of agrarian and oil properties between 1915 and 1940;
the Soviet expropriations following the Russian revolution; the Egyptian expropriations that led to the
Compliance-Based Theory
30
expropriate the local assets of foreign firms. To make the example concrete, assume
that the available assets have a total value to the country of $100 Million. This
potential gain of $100 Million must be weighed against the cost of an expropriation,
which might include several components. First, the violating country loses the benefits
currently being provided by foreign firms including, for example, the tax revenues from
these firms, technological transfers provided, employment, and so on.107 Suppose that
this loss amounts to $40 Million.108 Second, the country is likely to suffer a reputational
loss in the eyes of foreign investors. The act of expropriation signals a willingness to
seize the assets of foreigners, and reduces the attractiveness of the country to potential
future investors. Foreign investors are less likely to invest if they believe the host
country may expropriate their investment. Suppose that the reputational loss translates
into a loss of future investment, which the country values at $40 Million. Finally, the
country will suffer a loss of reputational capital with respect to other countries.
Potential treaty partners will view the country as a less reliable partner and will be less
willing to enter into future agreements. Assume that this loss is equivalent to $30
Million.
Notice that only a portion of the above costs can be attributed to international
law. Benefits that are lost because existing foreign firms either stop operating or operate
less efficiently after expropriation are not affected by the legal commitments of the
country. The loss of reputation in the eyes of other states, however, is the result of a
violation of an international obligation. The act of expropriating in the face of a treaty
promising not to do so demonstrates a willingness on the part of the country to violate
international commitments. Other countries will take this into account when dealing
with the country. Finally, the reaction of potential foreign investors is partially, though
not entirely, a function of the existence of international law. Even in the absence of an
international legal commitment,109 a decision to expropriate will have a chilling effect on
future investment. This effect is independent of the existence of an international legal
commitment. To the extent that investors view the legal obligation contained in the
BIT as a credible commitment, however, the country becomes more attractive to
investors and may enjoy higher levels of investment. If expropriation undermines this
Suez crisis; Cuban expropriations following the rise to power of Fidel Castro; the taking of partial
ownership in copper mines in Chile in 1971; and expropriations by Iran following the fall of the Shah. See
LIPSON, STANDING GUARD, PROTECTING FOREIGN CAPITAL IN THE NINETEENTH AND TWENTIETH
CENTURIES (1985); Burton & Inoue, Expropriation of Foreign-Owned Firms in Developing Countries, 18 J.
WORLD TRADE L. 396 (1984); Detlev Vagts, Foreign Investment Risk Reconsidered: The View from the
1980’s, 2 ICSID REV. 1 (1987).
107 It is true that the expropriating country may be able to generate some of these benefits by
continuing to operate the expropriated firms. Unless the government can operate the firms as efficiently
and introduce innovations as quickly as the former owners, however, the expropriation involves some loss.
108 All of the costs in this example should be treated as the present discounted value of the lost
future stream of revenue.
109 And putting aside, for simplicity, the fact that there may be a rule of customary international
law which prohibits expropriation without full compensation.
Compliance-Based Theory
31
confidence, a portion of the lost investment can be attributed to a reputational effect
resulting from the violation of international law. Future promises not to expropriate will
lack credibility, making it difficult to recapture that investment.
In deciding whether or not to violate its international commitment, the country
compares the total costs of doing so to the total benefits. Using the numbers given
above, it is clear that the country prefers to honor its commitment. A violation of the
treaty would impose a loss of $110 Million and yield a gain of only $100 Million – a net
loss of $10 Million. Notice also that the outcome is changed as a result of international
law. In the absence of a legal obligation, the expropriating country would not suffer the
$30 Million reputational loss in the eyes of other states so its total loss from the
expropriation will be no more than $80 Million. Because the benefits from
expropriation are $100 Million, the expropriation would cause a net gain absent the
international commitment.110 This example demonstrates that a reputational loss can
affect decisions even when the loss is considerably less than the total potential gains
from the action. This is so because there will typically be other costs that the country
must take into account. The reputational consequences of an action can alter the
outcome if they are enough to tip the balance of costs and benefits in favor of
compliance.
If we make different assumptions about the numbers, of course, we can generate
different results. For example, if the gain from expropriation is $200 Million while the
other numbers are unchanged, the country will choose to expropriate even though
doing so is a violation of international law. If, on the other hand, the gain from
expropriation was $20 Million and the other numbers again remained the same, the
country would choose not to expropriate, regardless of whether or not a BIT was in
place.
D. Dynamic Issues
A country’s decision to follow international law reflects a judgment that the
costs of a violation outweigh the benefits. Because the opportunities and risks facing a
country vary both over time and across contexts, however, it is to be expected that a
country may choose to follow a particular law at one time or in one context and violate
it at another time or in another context.
The dynamic aspect of compliance with international law can be illustrated with
the bilateral investment treaty example from the previous section. Suppose that a
country anticipates that the expropriation of foreign investment will lead to a complete
110 Strictly speaking, one should include the fact that the BIT caused an increase in investment –
meaning that absent a BIT, the country would have less investment to begin with, reducing the
attractiveness of expropriation. This detail can easily be added to the above example without changing
the results. It is omitted only for simplicity.
Compliance-Based Theory
32
halt in the flow of investment into the country.111 Assume that the expropriated
investment is worth $100 Million to the country if it is left in the hands of investors, and
that it is worth $200 Million if it is expropriated. The benefit from expropriation,
therefore, is $100 Million.
To evaluate the cost of the expropriation the decision makers must also consider
the value of future investment if it expropriates (which by assumption is zero) as
compared to the value of future investment if it does not expropriate. If the expected
value of future foreign investment changes over time, a country may choose to abide by
its BITs for a period of time but, when conditions change, it may decide to violate those
commitments.
Imagine that times are good and the country is enjoying high levels of foreign
investment that are expected to increase further in the years to come. Future
investments are expected to yield benefits valued at $200 Million. Under these
conditions, expropriation is unattractive. The country can do better by encouraging
more foreign investment and by treating that investment well. Benefits in the form of
tax revenues, employment, technology transfers, and so on, are larger than the benefits
from expropriation.
Now suppose that the political mood in the country changes as the leader of a
populist party emerges to national prominence by blaming the country’s troubles on
foreign capitalists. He points to the high level of foreign investment in the country and
the substantial profits being made by investors, contrasting this with the low wages paid
at some of the facilities of foreign firms. Widespread hostility develops toward foreign
interference in the local economy, and foreign residents are targeted for kidnapping by
newly formed leftist rebel groups. Despite its best efforts, the government cannot
provide sufficient security to ensure the safety of all foreign residents and visitors, and it
fails in its attempts to deflate the popularity of the opposition leader.
From the perspective of a potential investor, these developments greatly reduce
the appeal of the country. Not only are employees at risk from violent rebels, but there
is no way of knowing if the current pro-investor regime will win the next election or if
the country will be consumed by violence and possibly even civil war – an outcome that
would almost surely destroy any investment. As a result of these events, the expected
level and value of future investments falls to the point where the expected stream of
benefits to the country is worth, say, $50 Million.
The country’s expropriation decision is affected by this lower level of expected
future investment. By expropriating, the country still stands to gain $200 Million. If it
does not expropriate, it gains $100 Million from the investment that is in place plus $50
111 This extreme assumption is used to make the illustration clear. It is not necessary for the
results.
Compliance-Based Theory
33
Million from future investment for a total of $150 Million.112 The reduction in future
investment has made expropriation the country’s best strategy.113
Consider how the above dynamic issues might affect debt repayment decisions.
Imagine a country that seeks to borrow funds from international markets. When it
borrows, the sovereign debtor pledges to repay the funds plus interest. A decision to
violate this international commitment represents a judgment that the costs of a failure
to repay are outweighed by the benefits.
Among the costs facing the country if it does not repay is a reputational impact
that makes future borrowing more difficult or perhaps impossible. If the country in
question expects to borrow a great deal in the future – perhaps because it is growing
rapidly and has many uses for the funds – a failure to repay would be very costly. A
country in this situation, therefore, is likely to do everything within its power to repay its
loans.
If, on the other hand, the country does not expect to undertake any future
borrowing, it faces a much lower cost if it does not repay the loans. The fact that
international markets are unwilling to make additional loans does not impose much of
an incentive because the country does not want (or is already foreclosed from obtaining)
future loans. To be sure, the reputational loss will affect the country in other ways, but
the important point is that the cost of a violation is lower for the country with no future
borrowing needs
The history of Russian and Soviet debt in the twentieth century demonstrates
exactly this sort of behavior. When the Soviet Union came into being, it immediately
repudiated debts from the prior Russian Czarist regime.114 The new Soviet Union was
based on a political philosophy that was hostile to the established sources of capital and
the USSR, therefore, stood little chance of securing large foreign loans in the foreseeable
future.115 In that environment, a refusal to pay is easy to understand because the
country had little to lose by offending international capital markets. When the Soviet
Union collapsed, however, the situation was different. The new Russian government
was in need of large capital infusions, including loans from other states and the IMF. In
an effort to improve its reputation among potential creditors, the Russian state pledged
112 These calculations ignore the fact that foreign investments are sure to be less profitable in the
unstable new environment. If this fact were taken into account the temptation to expropriate would be
even greater.
113 In analogous way a country’s compliance decision may vary depending on the context. For
example, a country that has BITs with two different partners may choose to violate one treaty but not the
other if the gains from violating the first are larger than the costs while the costs outweigh the benefit in
the case of the second treaty.
114 Barry Eichengreen & Richard Portes, Debt and Default in the 1930s: Causes and Consequences,
30 EUR. ECON. REV. 599, 613 (1986).
115 The United States did not even recognize the Soviet government until the 1933 Litvinov
Assignment. See United States v. Pink, 315 U.S. 203 (1942).
Compliance-Based Theory
34
to repay not only Soviet debts, but also promised at least some compensation to the
holders of Russian bonds repudiated by the Soviet Union in 1918.116
E. The Level of Commitment
The above discussion demonstrates that a model of rational states is consistent
with the existence of international law. This result is important because, just as the
ability to bind oneself through contract is valuable to private parties, the ability to
commit to a particular action is valuable to states. A state’s ability to signal its
commitment more credibly through an international agreement – whether a treaty or
other form of promise – is welfare increasing because it allows that state to enter into a
broader range of potential agreements. In other words, the ability to make irrevocable
commitments makes states better off.117
In the absence of transaction costs, the parties to an agreement would specify the
precise conditions under which they will perform and those under which they will not.
Agreements would list every possible state of the world and the obligations of the parties
in each state. In a domestic context, such a contract would then be enforceable in
court. In the international context, such a contract would be backed by reputation. As
events unfolded, one could simply refer to the contract in order to identify the
obligations of each party. Notice that a complete specification of terms in this way
would allow countries choosing to develop reputations for honoring their commitments
to make agreements that are fully specified and that make it unnecessary to ever violate
their obligations. By specifying the precise conditions under which they plan to perform,
states also specify the conditions under which they plan to refuse performance. The
agreement itself, therefore, would excuse performance in some situations, and a country
could make agreements that it would never violate. If such agreements were possible,
there would be no reason for the many different types of international commitments.
Rather than sign a “non-binding agreement” for example, a state could simply specify
the conditions under which it promises to carry out the requirements of the treaty and
those under which it will not do so. The agreement could then be included in a binding
treaty under whose terms one or both parties would be excused from performance in
certain circumstances.
In practice, of course, substantial transaction costs prevent international
agreements from specifying every possible future contingency. First, it is often
impossible to know in advance the range of possible future states of the world, let alone
to list them all in an agreement. For example, in the mid 1980s it would have been very
116 Uli Schmetzer, Russia to Pay Off Old Bonds; After 78 Years, the Czar's Markers Are Worthless
No More, CHI. TRIB., Nov. 28, 1996, at 1.
117 The value of a good reputation for states can be compared to the value of a high bond rating.
Just as a good rating increases investor confidence and, therefore, allows the firm to raise money more
cheaply, a strong reputation increases the confidence of counter-parties to an international agreement,
allowing a state to extract more in exchange for its own promises.
Compliance-Based Theory
35
difficult to predict the collapse of communism and the state of Eastern Europe and the
former Soviet Union in the early 1990s. Second, even if the range of possible states of
the world is known, the probability of being in any given state of the world is not. For
example, it is conceivable that a Free Trade Agreement of the Americas will be signed
within the next ten years, but the probability of such an event is difficult to estimate.
Third, identifying the state of the world at any given moment is controversial and
subject to dispute. Countries may disagree, for example, about whether certain practices
constitute protectionist barriers or reasonable health measures. This lack of consensus
introduces questions of interpretation that can lead to a dispute even in the case of a
well-specified treaty. Finally, a long list of contingencies and conditions can make
ratification of international agreements much more difficult. Domestic opposition to an
agreement can choose from the many conditions to advance the argument that the
agreement is contrary to the national interest. Even where an agreement, taken in its
entirety, is a good one, groups opposed to it would have more ammunition with which to
rally public opinion in opposition.118
As a result of these, and other, transaction costs, international agreements do
not list every possible contingency. Instead, the parties recognize that there is a risk of
violation. The problem is that the violation of a treaty leads to a loss of reputation that
is costly. A country that wants to make a promise, but recognizes that there is a high
probability that it will violate that promise, may not want to put too much reputation on
the line. Of course, if the reputational risk is too great, a country can always choose to
simply not make the promise. This strategy is not ideal, however, because the country
may want to make at least a weak promise in order to extract some form of concession
from the other side.
Having the ability to either “commit” or “not commit” is valuable, but the ability
to choose from a range of commitment levels is even more valuable. By varying the
form of its promise, a state is able to choose its level of commitment and signal that
commitment to other states.119 It is possible to identify at least two dimensions along
which international agreements can range in order to adjust the level of commitment.
The first dimension, which is the primary focus of this Article, is what might be termed
the formality of the commitment. Treaties, for example, bind more than informal
agreements. The second dimension is the clarity of the agreement. Where a nation’s
commitment is clear, a breach is more easily observed and the reputational cost is
higher. When possible, therefore, countries that wish to increase the level of
118 In some circumstances an agreement will, in fact, not be in the national interest. In those
cases, the ability to oppose its ratification may be good for a country. Those who draft an agreement,
however, almost always want the agreement to be adopted. Because it is these parties who determine the
level of detail included in the treaty, they are able to keep the agreement simple in order to improve the
chances of adoption.
119 See Charles Lipson, Why are Some International Agreements Informal?, 45 INT’L ORG. 495, 508
(Autumn 1991) (stating that countries use treaties to “signal their intentions with special intensity and
gravity.”)
Compliance-Based Theory
36
commitment prefer detailed agreements. For example, trade negotiations often feature
schedules of commitments that provide a precise enumeration of commitments and
obligation.120 At the other extreme, vague statements regarding national intent lead to
relatively low levels of commitment, in part because it is very difficult to determine
when a country has violated the agreement.
The ability to modulate the level of obligation should not be mistaken for a
system of truly enforceable promises. By choosing one form of international agreement
over another, countries are varying the reputational stake that they have in the
obligation. A violation will impose a higher reputational cost in the case of a treaty than
it will in the case of a non-binding agreement. In neither case should one conclude that
the country “cannot” turn away from its obligation. The strength of reputation remains
limited and even the strongest commitments will sometimes be ignored. On the other
hand, it is a mistake to discount the importance of reputation altogether. As discussed
above, a reputation for compliance with agreements is valuable to a country, so
countries will only compromise that reputation if they receive something else of value in
exchange.121
F. International Law and Coordination
When states cooperate in order to resolve straightforward coordination games, it
is fair to say that international law has a limited role to play. Imagine, for example, that
two countries wish to shut down an international organized crime syndicate. By
cooperating, the countries stand a good chance of success. Neither country is willing to
pursue the syndicate by itself, however, because a single country acting alone stands very
little chance of succeeding. Figure V illustrates such a game. If both countries pursue
the crime syndicate, the expected payoff for each country is 5 – reflecting the high
probability of success. If both ignore the syndicate, both countries must endure the
associated crime, but can use the freed resources to combat other problems, yielding a
gain of 2. If one state pursues the syndicate alone, it expends resources in doing so, but
stands little chance of success, yielding a loss of 3. A state that ignores the syndicate
while the other state pursues it can divert resources to other concerns while still
enjoying at least some chance that the syndicate will be shut down. The total payoff for
a country in this situation is 3.
120 See, e.g., The North American Free Trade Agreement and related documents, available online
at http://www.nafta-sec-alena.org/english/index.htm.
121 See Lipson, supra note 119, at 511.
Compliance-Based Theory
37
Figure V
Country 2
Pursue Ignore
Pursue 5,5 -3,3
Country 1
Ignore 3,-3 2,2
In this game, one would expect the countries to reach an agreement in which
each promises to pursue the syndicate. Once such an agreement is reached, neither
country has an incentive to violate its commitment and no threat of sanction is needed
to achieve cooperation. Furthermore, the form of the agreement is not terribly
important. The countries could sign a treaty agreeing to pursue the crime syndicate, but
a treaty is not necessary. It would be equally effective to reach an informal agreement
between the countries or between the relevant law enforcement agencies. It would also
be sufficient for one country to declare its intention of pursuing the crime syndicate in a
public and credible way by, for example, expending funds to do so. The other state,
seeing that the first state was pursuing the syndicate, would have an incentive to do the
same. Because this game is resolved through simple coordination and without the need
of a sanction in the event of a violation, one can question whether it is an example of
international law at work.122 Although international law may facilitate the selection of a
focal point in cases where there exist multiple equilibria, it does little else.123
If one adopts a more realistic model of a coordination game, however,
international law can play a significant role. There are at least two extensions of the
simple coordination game that make international law important. First, it may be the
case that the parties do not know one another’s payoffs with certainty. In that situation,
even if the actual payoffs are as indicated in Figure V, the countries may not be certain
122 See Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2, at 1127-28.
123 The resolution of coordination games is one explanation for informal agreements among
states. Because coordination games need only a focal point in order to achieve the desired equilibrium,
there is no need for a formal and detailed agreement. Once the focal point is identified, no state has an
incentive to “cheat.”
Compliance-Based Theory
38
that coordination is sufficient to ensure the desirable outcome. Country 1, for example,
may mistakenly believe that the payoffs are as shown in Figure VI rather than Figure V.
Figure VI
Country 2
Pursue Ignore
Pursue 5,5 -3,6
Country 1
Ignore 3,-3 2,2
If country 1 believes that Figure VI represents the payoffs, it will expect country
2 to ignore the syndicate. In this situation, country 1 will not expect mere coordination
to be sufficient to ensure that both countries pursue the syndicate. As a result, country
1 will not pursue the syndicate unless it has some assurance that country 2 will do the
same. The easiest solution, of course, is an international agreement. If the parties sign a
treaty pledging to pursue the crime syndicate, the reputational cost of a failure to do so
may be enough to make country 2’s promise credible to country 1. If so, both countries
will sign the treaty and pursue the syndicate. The lesson here is that if the payoffs are
not common knowledge, international law may help achieve the value-maximizing
outcome in a coordination game.
A second extension of the basic coordination game recognizes that states face
circumstances that change over time. Imagine, for example, that in period 1 everybody
expects the crime syndicate to concentrate its operations in one state during period 2
and simultaneously reduce them in the other state. Once the syndicate has turned its
focus to only one of the countries, the other has no incentive to pursue it. Nobody
knows, however, which state will face a growth in activity and which will witness a
decline. Because neither state is likely to succeed in controlling the syndicate alone,
both are willing to commit to a cooperative effort to defeat the syndicate in the future
rather than risk being the focus of its activity.
In this example, both states are better off ex ante if they are able to commit to a
joint crime fighting effort, but once the uncertainty is resolved, one state will have an
Compliance-Based Theory
39
incentive to ignore the syndicate. Both states, therefore, prefer to commit, in period
one, to working together, but once the uncertainty is resolved one of them will have an
incentive to ignore that commitment.
Figure VII
Country 2
Pursue Ignore
Pursue 5,1 -5,4
Country 1
Ignore -1,-1 -2,3
If commitment is not possible, however, the period 2 payoffs are those given in
Figure VII, which assumes that the crime syndicate concentrates its efforts in country 1.
If both countries pursue the syndicate, country 1 gains 5, just as in Figure VI. Country
2, however, gains only 1 because the crime syndicate’s activities in country 2 have been
reduced, making a successful crime fighting effort less valuable than it is in Figure VI. If
both countries ignore the syndicate in period 2, country 1 suffers a loss of 2 as a result of
the crime. Country 2, however, enjoys a gain of 3 because it can devote its resources to
other priorities. If only country 1 pursues the syndicate, it suffers a loss of 5 because it is
unlikely to succeed in defeating the syndicate, and it uses up valuable resources trying to
do so. Finally, if only country 2 pursue the syndicate, it receives a payoff of -1 because it
uses up resources. Country 1 receives a payoff of –1 if only country 2 pursues the
syndicate because it suffers from the crime but can at least use resources in other areas.
Notice that in period 2, ignoring the crime syndicate is a dominant strategy for
Country 2. Regardless of what country 1 does, country 2 is better off if it chooses to
ignore the syndicate. Knowing this, country 1 will also choose to ignore and we end up
with payoffs of –2 for country 1 and 3 for country 2.
Compliance-Based Theory
40
If international law allows the countries to commit to a particular course of
action, however, they can agree in period 1 to pursue the syndicate.124 Notice that this
result maximizes the payoffs to the countries.
The point here is that although international law has little role to play in a pure
coordination game, the dynamics of international relations may cause countries to enter
into formal agreements even when they appear to face a simple coordination game.
Incomplete information and changes in circumstances can turn a coordination game
into a game in which the ability to commit to a particular course of action has value.
Even when the game at hand appears to be a coordination game, therefore, there may
be reasons to make use of international law and the ability to pledge reputational
capital.
IV. VIOLATION AND COMPLIANCE
This section seeks to examine violations of international law in greater detail. It
provides insights into why states sometimes violate their international commitments and
when they can be expected to do so.
A. Reputational Sanctions
The primary benefit of a rational actor model of international law is its ability to
provide predictions about when countries will choose to violate international legal
obligations. The decision to honor or breach a promise made to another state imposes
costs and benefits upon a country and its decision makers. It is assumed in the model
that decision makers behave in such a way as to maximize the payoffs that result from
their actions.125 Where the benefits of breach outweigh its costs, we expect a country to
violate international law. International law succeeds when it alters the payoffs in such a
way as to get compliance with international law when, in the absence of such law, states
would behave differently.126 Put another way, international law succeeds when promises
made by states generate some compliance pull.
124 It is assumed that a commitment at period one is sufficient to achieve compliance – meaning
that we assume the reputational cost of a violation is large enough that country 2 prefers to honor its
commitment.
125 As previously mentioned, the precise set of payoffs that an actor maximizes need not be the
one that maximize the country’s payoff, it may instead be the one that achieves the leader’s personal
objectives. Decision makers whose goals differ from those of their countries may be more likely to violate
international law because they do not bear the entire cost of such a violation. Such a situation would
generally reduce the role of international law, but does not present a problem for the theory presented in
this Article.
126 Notice that in contrast to the domestic context, most international law cannot hope to
achieve optimal deterrence. In most cases all that can be hoped for is movement in the direction of
optimal deterrence. Conditions that can promote optimal deterrence are discussed in Part III.C.
Compliance-Based Theory
41
To generate predictions about state behavior, one must have a theory about the
magnitude of the reputational loss as a result of violations of law. It seems clear that the
reputational impact of a violation of international law varies depending on the nature of
the violation. For example, a failure to comply with a minor international obligation
that is a result of oversight or human error and that is promptly corrected without
damage to other states is unlikely to have a major reputational impact. In contrast, an
egregious and intentional violation such as support of terrorist activities against another
state is likely to have a profound impact on a nation’s reputation.
A list of factors that influences the reputational impact of a violation, therefore,
should include the severity of the violation, the reasons for the violation, the extent to
which other states know of the violation, and the clarity of the commitment.127 The
discussion that follows outlines some of these factors and discusses the possibility that
states may suffer a reputational loss even when implicit obligations are violated. The
level of commitment taken on by a state is not discussed below because it is addressed in
detail in Part III.E. It should also be noted that although this Article tends to speak of
“a state’s reputation,” it is important to keep in mind that the reputation of a state may
vary from one issue area to another and may depend on the identity of its counterparty.
1. Severity of the violation
The reputational consequence of a violation is most obviously affected by the
severity of that violation. A minor, technical violation will have a small impact
compared to a major violation of an international obligation.128
Related to the severity of the violation is the magnitude of the harm suffered by
other states. A violation that causes substantial and widespread harm does greater
damage to a state’s reputation than a violation that is “victimless” or that imposes only
slight harms. Consider, for example, the impact of violating the territorial waters of
another state. If ships of one state sail through the waters of another in disregard of a
policy requiring permission for such voyages, international law has been violated.129 If
those ships simply pass through the waters without causing any harm to the offended
state or any other state, the violation is unlikely to have major reputational
consequences.130 If, on the other hand, the ship in question is a fishing vessel that
catches fish in the other state’s waters, the consequences are likely to be greater. The
impact on the offending state’s reputation is greater still if the harm is felt by more than
one country. It may be the case, for example, that the relevant waters for fishing
127 This list is not intended to be exhaustive. Other factors may also be relevant.
128 See CHAYES & CHAYES, supra note 12, at 18 (“Flouting a cease-fire under a peace agreement
or refusing to allow inspection of nuclear reactors under the NPT would be expected to evoke very
different responses from a failure to meet the reporting requirements of an environmental treaty.”)
129 For simplicity and clarity, assume that the ships in question are owned by the state.
130 Repeated violations of this type may have greater consequences.
Compliance-Based Theory
42
purposes cross national boundaries.131 If this is so, by fishing in the waters of one
country the offending state is imposing a harm on all countries whose fishing industries
might be affected. The act of fishing in those waters, therefore, may harm the interests
of several states at once.
2. Reasons for violation
The reason for a violation of international law may also play a role. When
entering into an agreement, states hope that their counter party will honor its
obligations. They also recognize, however, that compliance with international
obligations is imperfect and that violations occur. It is understood that under certain
conditions a state will choose to ignore its obligations. For example, violation of a
human rights treaty is viewed in a different light when it takes place under conditions of
great national crisis than if the violation occurs during a period of normalcy.132 A state
that breaches such a treaty in time of crisis may be able to retain a reputation for
compliance with treaties during normal times. When normalcy returns, and the state
seeks to participate in further human rights negotiations, its reputation may not be
unduly compromised. If the violation took place during a period of normalcy, however,
future negotiations will be tainted by the past failure to honor international obligations.
It will be much more difficult, and perhaps impossible, for the country to use its
reputational capital in the human rights arena.
3. Knowledge of the violation
The extent to which a violation is known affects the reputational consequences
of a violation. Obviously if a violation takes place without the knowledge of any other
state, there is no reputational loss. For example, if the ships of one country fish illegally
in the territorial waters of another without that country (or any other) being aware of
the violation, there will be no reputational consequences. A more dramatic example
might be the secret violation of a nuclear non-proliferation treaty. The reputational
consequences will also be less if only a small number of countries know of the violation.
For example, if the ships of one country fish in the waters of another, but only the
offended country becomes aware of the incident, the offending country may only suffer a
reputational loss in the eyes of that other country. As no other country knows of the
violation, there is no loss of reputation with respect to those countries. Even if the
county who suffered the violation attempts to publicize it, the offending country may be
able to deny the accusations in a credible fashion. This explains, for example, why
countries often deny that they have violated international law despite the accusations of
another state.
131 For example, the Northeast coast of the United States represents a fertile fishing ground that
is shared with Canada in the sense that the fish inhabit an area that crosses the Canada-US boundary.
132 Note that this is a claim about how nations view a violation, not how traditional conceptions
of international law view it.
Compliance-Based Theory
43
4. Clarity
An issue closely related to the question of states’ awareness of a violation of
international law is the matter of clarity. Because reputational loss is triggered by a
failure to live up to an international obligation, the clarity of both the obligation and the
violation are important factors. The reputational consequences are most severe when
the obligation is clear and the violation is unambiguous. Where obligations are
uncertain, the reputational cost from a violation is reduced.
The relationship between the reputational cost of a violation and the certainty of
that violation may explain why battles over the content of customary international law
(CIL) are fought. If the existence of a rule of customary law is in doubt, the reputational
cost of a violation will be smaller. Thus, for example, debates over the role of CIL in
human rights issues can be explained by the desire of each side to control the content of
CIL. If a particular set of human rights issues is deemed norms of CIL, states that
violate those rules will pay a higher cost for doing so. This is so because at least the
uncertainty regarding the existence of an obligation is eliminated. The force of the rule
may remain weak, of course, because there may remain uncertainty regarding the exact
content of the rule, the exceptions to the rule, the identity of any persistent objectors,
and so on.
5. Implicit Obligations
Because reputation plays a central role in the compliance question, one must
consider the possibility that a state may suffer a reputational loss for actions that are
consistent with its explicit international obligations. Stated in contractual terms, do the
actions of states create implicit commitments in addition to the explicit commitments
that are agreed to? If so, violation of these implicit promises may also lead to a loss of
reputational capital. Putting aside the semantic question of whether it makes sense to
call such actions violations of law, the consequences for such actions may affect state
behavior.
For example, if a state withdraws from a treaty in a fashion that is consistent
with that treaty but that is contrary to the expectations of other states, there may be
reputational consequences. A withdrawal of this sort may be perceived as a breach of an
implicit promise to honor the treaty for the foreseeable future. To see why this is so,
imagine the United States announcing its intention to withdraw from NAFTA. Under
the terms of the NAFTA agreement, any party can withdraw “six months after it
provides written notice of withdrawal to the other Parties.”133 The United States would
be entirely within its rights, under the terms of the agreement, to take such an action.
Nevertheless, Canada and Mexico, having relied on the presence of NAFTA, having
gone through a period of economic dislocation and adjustment following the adoption of
133 NAFTA art. 2205.
Compliance-Based Theory
44
NAFTA, and having made plans – in both the private and public sectors – that rely on
the continued existence of the treaty are sure to suffer losses as a result of the decision.
In addition, politicians in both Canada and Mexico supported NAFTA and staked their
own political reputations on the deal. These individuals would be personally affected,
and may feel betrayed by American policymakers. Although the countries did not
explicitly commit themselves to NAFTA for more than six months, each country may
believe that there is an implicit promised to honor the treaty for a longer period. One
would expect that an American withdrawal from NAFTA would dampen enthusiasm in
Canada and Mexico for further trade agreements and for reliance on American
commitments. In other words, withdrawal from NAFTA imposes reputational costs on
the United States that resemble those imposed for a violation of the treaty.134
In fairness, it should be noted that the reputational impact in the above example
is limited by the fact that the United States complied with its formal obligations. An
American announcement of an immediate cancellation of the treaty would presumably
increase the reputational cost of a withdrawal from the treaty. One reason for the
different reactions may be that withdrawal in a fashion that is consistent with the treaty
may not signal a willingness to take actions that are contrary to a country’s express
commitments.
Furthermore, it may be possible for a country to suffer a reputational loss as a
result of acting contrary to the terms of an agreement to which the state has not
consented. For example, the Basle Accord establishes minimum capital-asset ratios for
banks. The Accord enjoys widespread compliance, not only among signatory countries,
but also among countries that did not sign and were not involved in the negotiations.
Imagine that Country A chooses to comply with the Basle Accord, even though it was
not a signatory. If country A, after several years of compliance, changes its policies and
decides to ignore the Accord, it might suffer a reputational loss. While country A was
in compliance, other countries may have assumed that it would continue to comply, and
they may have adjusted their policies in reliance.
6. Regime Changes
The above discussion treats each state as an entity that is permanently tainted by
its violations of international law. This is something of an overstatement because not
only will the passage of time reduce the reputational consequences of any particular act,
but the state may be able to neutralize the reputational consequences of prior actions
through a change in leadership. Imagine, for example, that a government continually
134 This example demonstrates in a graphic way the difficulty of separating “legal commitments”
from international relations in general. A country that habitually enters into international obligations
only to withdraw shortly thereafter is a less desirable partner regardless of whether the withdrawals are
consistent with the terms of the agreements or not. It may be the case that violations of explicit
commitments are more costly in terms of reputation than violations of implicit commitments, but both
kinds of actions come with a reputational price tag.
Compliance-Based Theory
45
ignores its international commitments as part of a domestic political platform of
isolation and independence. The government will most likely be unable to obtain
concessions from other states in exchange for its own promises. If that government falls
and is replaced by one that openly favors closer ties with the outside world, compliance
with international legal obligations, and openness, the reputational impact of the past
policies may be partially or even entirely erased.
Something very much like this took place with respect to the flow of foreign
direct investment into Chile during the early 1970s. During the Allende regime foreign
investment was expropriated and conditions were generally unfavorable to foreign
investors, with the predictable result that foreign investment fell virtually to zero.135
Although some of the investment decisions were surely based on pessimism about the
Chilean economy, it seems certain that some were based on concerns about the
potential for future expropriations. Following the successful coup by Pinochet, however,
foreign investment returned in short order. By 1975, the flow of foreign investment
reached USD 50 million, the first time in the decade that it was positive. By 1978,
foreign investment was USD 181 million.136 Again, some of the increase inflow must be
attributed to the fact that the Pinochet regime created a more favorable economic
climate for investment. Nevertheless, it is clear that the reputational concerns that
arose as a result of expropriation and other acts under Allende largely disappeared when
Pinochet rose to power.
The ability of a new regime to avoid the reputational stigma of past actions by
the state will, of course, depend a great deal on the particular circumstances of the case.
If the new administration is perceived to be similar in ideology to prior ones, it will
probably be difficult to shed a negative reputation. In addition, if the former regime is
likely to regain power in the near future, its reputation will continue to affect the
behavior of other states.
B. Direct Sanctions
Up to this point the Article has focused on the reputational impact of violations
of international law. This approach is quite different from the usual way in which
domestic rules are studied. In the domestic setting, it is sanctions imposed by
government that receives the primary focus while reputational effects, if any, are
normally considered to be secondary.137 The weakness of direct sanctions in the
135 In fact, foreign investment during the period was negative because some firms removed their
investments.
136 Source: IMF Balance of Payments Statistics.
137 In recent years there has been a renewed interest in the question of how social norms,
including reputational sanctions, affect behavior. See ERIC POSNER, LAW AND SOCIAL NORMS (June
2000); ROBERT C. ELLICKSON, ORDER WITHOUT LAW: HOW NEIGHBORS SETTLE DISPUTES (1991);
Symposium, Law, Economics, & Norms, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 1697 (1996); Symposium, Social Norms, Social
Meaning, and the Economic Analysis of Law, 27 J. LEGAL STUD. 537 (1998); Lisa Bernstein, Opting Out of
Compliance-Based Theory
46
international arena, however, makes reputational sanctions more important. That is
not to say that direct sanctions are irrelevant. In certain instances they can have an
important impact on a country’s incentives and behavior. This section examines direct
sanctions and discusses when these sanctions are likely to be most effective.
1. Direct Sanctions and Retaliation
The first point to note is that optimal compliance with international law is more
likely if states face direct sanctions for such violations. This is so because reputational
sanctions are generally, though not always, weaker than an optimal sanction. Once
again, analogy to contract law is useful. Just as compliance with a contract is not always
optimal, one hundred percent compliance with international law is not the optimal level
of compliance. This is so because nations are unable to anticipate all possible situations
in their agreements. In certain circumstances the total costs associated with compliance
outweigh the costs associated with a violation of the law. On these occasions, violation
of the law is preferable to compliance. This point is understood in contract law, where it
is well established that expectations damages lead to “efficient breach.”138 In other
words, by adopting expectation damages, contracts are breached if and only if breach is
the value maximizing outcome. The same result holds in international law. When the
total benefits of a violation of international law outweigh the benefits of performance, it
is preferable that there be a violation.139 A regime in which violations of international
law lead to expectation damages will, as in the contracts analog, lead to violations of the
law only when such violations are efficient. In other words, expectation damages lead to
optimal deterrence.140
The most commonly used form of direct sanction consists of retaliatory measures
taken by one or more states against another. For example, following the enactment of
the Hawley-Smoot Tariff Act of 1930, which increased U.S. tariffs dramatically, other
countries retaliated with tariff increases of their own.141 In some cases direct retaliation
the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry, 21 J. LEGAL STUD. 115 (1992);
Robert Cooter, Normative Failure Theory of Law, 82 CORNELL L. REV. 947 (1997); Steven Hetcher,
Creating Safe Social Norms in a Dangerous World, 73 S. CAL. L. REV. 1 (1999); William K. Jones, A Theory
of Social Norms, 1994 U. ILL. L. REV. 545; Jody S. Kraus, Legal Design and the Evolution of Commercial
Norms, 26 J. LEGAL STUD. 377 (1997).
138 See A. MITCHELL POLINSKY, AN INTRODUCTION TO LAW AND ECONOMICS 31 (2d ed. 1989).
139 This is not meant to suggest that there is any simple way to aggregate the interests of states in
order to determine when the benefits of a violation outweigh the costs. The point is simply that this will
be true in some circumstances, implying that infinite sanctions for violations of the law are inappropriate.
140 Note that the damaged referred to here include reputational loss. For this reason, even if
there were a mechanism to impose, say, monetary sanctions, it would be appropriate for these to be
somewhat less than the level of expectations damages so that total damages, including both reputational
and direct sanctions, represent expectation damages.
141 See Thomas D. Grant, Foreign Takeovers Of United States Airlines: Free Trade Process,
Problems, And Progress, 31 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 63, 139-40 (1994); RAY AUGUST, INTERNATIONAL
BUSINESS LAW 354 (2000).
Compliance-Based Theory
47
amounts to a decision by the counter-party of the offending state to terminate its own
compliance with the relevant agreement. This action has the advantage that it imposes
a cost on the offending state and it is often in the interest of the retaliating state. For
example, imagine that country A and country B agree on the implementation of
pollution controls in border areas. Assume that neither country would implement the
controls by itself, but each is willing to do so in order to get the controls imposed by its
neighbor. Suppose that country A violates the agreement by failing to properly monitor
and enforce the new controls. Country B may react by refusing to continue its own
compliance with the agreement. This is a likely reaction by country B because, by
assumption, it agreed to the controls only because it expected country A to do the same.
Compliance was the price country B was willing to pay in order to have country A
change its behavior. Without country A’s compliance, it is in country B’s interest to
ignore the terms of the agreement.
This form of retaliation is relevant to country A’s decision to violate its
international obligation, and in some cases will be enough to prevent such a violation.
In many cases, however, the simple abrogation of the treaty is not enough to prevent a
violation and, more importantly, is not an optimal sanction. To give a simple example,
imagine that countries A and B each expect to receive gains of 5 as a result of the
pollution agreement, but neither is certain of the actual gain. Despite the uncertainty,
both countries consent to the deal in good faith. Suppose that after the agreement is
signed, country A learns that it actually faces a loss of 1 as a result, rather than a gain of
5, while country B stands to gain 5 from the agreement, as expected. If country A
honors its commitment, the total benefit is 4 (5 for country B, minus 1 for country A).
If country A violates its commitment and B in turn abrogates the treaty, the total gain is
zero. Country A will nevertheless violate the agreement (assuming there is no sanction
other than abrogation) precisely because it is better off without it. The threat of
abrogation is insufficient to provide optimal deterrence. Optimal deterrence would
require that country A face a sanction of 5 as a result of its violation of the law. In this
example, the withdrawal of benefits conferred is an inadequate sanction because it bears
no relation to the loss caused by the violation and, therefore, does not lead to optimal
compliance.
In other cases, the sanction consists of actions that are intended to punish the
offending state. That is, rather than a withdrawal of benefits conferred upon the
offending state, sanctions can represent the imposition of a penalty. For example, in
retaliation for Iraq’s actions against Kuwait and its refusal to accept liability for damage
claims arising from the gulf war, western countries placed an embargo on Iraqi oil.
Sanctions of this sort have the advantage that they need not be directly related to the
violation and, therefore, can more easily be tailored to resemble optimal sanctions.
Iraq’s actions were only indirectly related to its oil sales or oil revenues, but the embargo
represented an available and relatively powerful sanction. Putting aside the question of
whether the embargo is appropriate in this instance, it demonstrates that sanctions of
this sort can be severe.
Compliance-Based Theory
48
There are two important problems with the imposition of this sort of penalty.
First, without a dispute settlement procedure,142 it is difficult to distinguish appropriate
sanctions from inappropriate ones. While it is true that punitive sanctions have the
potential to be used as optimal sanctions, they are generally not imposed by neutral third
parties but rather by injured states. There is, therefore, the risk that the sanctions will
be excessive.
Second, the imposition of these sanctions imposes costs on both the sanctioned
and sanctioning states. The embargo has hurt Iraq, but it has also hurt participating
countries because it has reduced the number of potential suppliers of oil. Because
imposing a sanction hurts a country, the incentive to impose optimal sanctions is often
weak, leading to penalties that are too lenient.
Despite their shortcomings, the relevance of punitive sanctions should not be
dismissed too quickly, especially when they are compared to the alternative
international mechanisms for compliance. In some situations it is possible to have such
sanctions imposed and, as a result, provide more efficient incentives to states.
Consider first a one-shot game in which country A violates international law and
country B must decide whether or not to expend resources punishing country A.
Assuming that the punishment is the last play of the game, country B has no incentive
to impose the punishment. Country A realizes that country B will not impose the
punishment, and so country A is not deterred from violating its obligations.143 In a one-
shot game, therefore, countries will not impose sanctions on other countries when doing
so is costly. It is elementary game theory that the same result holds for any finitely
repeated game.144
The situation changes, however, in an infinitely repeated game. Where states
interact repeatedly over time, it may be worthwhile for states to develop reputations for
punishing offenders. By punishing offenders today, states increase the likelihood of
compliance tomorrow because the threat of future punishment is credible. To sustain
such an equilibrium with punishment it must be worthwhile for a state to punish today’s
violation in order to achieve future compliance. These conditions will be met when (i)
the states have relatively low discount rates; (ii) the cost to the punishing state is not
too large relative to the benefit received when other states follow the law; and (iii) the
benefits from violations of the law are not too large relative to the payoff from following
the law.
142 There are, of course, some dispute settlement bodies in the international community,
including the International Court of Justice and the dispute settlement procedures available at the WTO.
There are put to one side for the moment. They are discussed below.
143 Note how different this case is from the withdrawal of benefits conferred, discussed above. If
it is costly for country B to honor its obligations to A, it will stop doing so once it becomes clear that
country A has not kept its own promises.
144 See ERIC RASMUSSEN, GAMES AND INFORMATION: AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY 88
(1990).
Compliance-Based Theory
49
C. When Will Sanctions Work Best?
The above discussion of sanctions describes the working of direct sanctions.
Recognizing these incentive effects allows us to consider the circumstances in which
sanctions are most likely to be imposed. This section addresses two dimensions along
which the effectiveness of a sanction, whether direct, reputational, or both, is likely to
vary. Specifically, one would expect such penalties to be imposed more often in the
form of bilateral rather than multilateral sanctions; and in ongoing relationships more
than in short term relationships.
1. Bilateral v. Multilateral Sanctions
A bilateral sanction signals a willingness to punish illegal conduct within the
bilateral relationship. Because many of the factors that determine a country’s
willingness to impose a sanction – including the relative power of the two countries, the
frequency of their interactions, and the general state of relations between the states –
are slow to change in a bilateral relationship, a reputation for punishing violations is
valuable, relatively easy to establish, and relatively easy to maintain. It is valuable
because it yields benefits in a wide range of interactions. It is easy to establish and
maintain because the sanctioning party enjoys the full benefits of the sanction in the
form of greater compliance by its counter-party. It is, therefore, more likely to be worth
the cost of establishing such a reputation. These factors mean that sanctioning
violations are a relatively attractive strategy in a bilateral relationship.
The use of punitive sanctions is much more difficult in the multilateral context.
Faced with a violation, all countries have an incentive to free-ride on the sanctioning
efforts of others. A country that imposes a sanction gains only a portion of the benefits
from that act – other members of the group also benefit. Since all countries have an
incentive to free-ride, one would expect too little use of these sanctions. This is one
explanation of why international sanctions are so often considered to be ineffective.
The most high-profile sanctions are typically multilateral sanctions which, even once
they are in place, are less likely to be maintained.
The lesson here is that it is difficult to achieve multilateral sanctions. Notice
that the distinction being discussed turns on the nature of the sanction, not the nature
of the underlying obligation. It is not a question of whether the entire relationship is
bilateral or multilateral. Rather, it is a question of whether the punitive sanction is
imposed bilaterally or multilaterally. If, for example, a country has a policy of
sanctioning any violation of a multilateral agreement – regardless of who suffers the
harm, that is a multilateral situation. If, on the other hand, a country sanctions only
violations that impact itself, that is a form of bilateral sanction. The free-rider problem
is present only in the multilateral situation and not in the bilateral situation. The
problem with multilateral sanctions, therefore, need not undermine all multilateral
efforts are cooperation. Multilateral agreements and organizations should take note of
the problems with multilateral sanctions and tailor their dispute resolution and
Compliance-Based Theory
50
enforcement mechanisms accordingly. For example, dispute settlement within the
WTO relies on rules permitting an offended party to sanction a violating state when
other attempts to resolve the dispute have failed. This is a more sensible strategy than
one in which all member countries are asked to impose a sanction even when only one
country is injured.145
2. Complex, Ongoing Relationships v. Simple, Short Term
Relationships
The role of reputation implies that international law is more powerful in
complex, multifaceted relationships than in simple, one-dimensional ones. In a
complex, bilateral relationship, individual interactions between the countries are
normally of modest value when compared to the accumulated reputational capital and
goodwill that exists between the countries.146 Bilateral relationships of this sort might
include Canada and the United States, France and Germany, the United States and
Japan, and so on.
When states interact in many different areas and in many different ways over
time, a reputational loss to one of those countries can be extremely costly. To see why
this is so, compare the case of an ongoing complex bilateral relationship to the case of a
one-time interaction.147 As shown in Figure I and the accompanying discussion,
international law cannot affect a country’s behavior in a one-shot game because there
are no consequences when international law is violated. Specifically, no future
interactions are affected by the violation. Precisely the opposite is true in the case of
complex bilateral relationships, where a blow to a country’s reputation will be felt in
many future interactions – making the cost of violating the law higher. Even without an
explicit sanction, a country has a strong incentive to honor its commitments in such
relationships because any individual interaction is of limited value relative to the entire
relationship. Actions which have a positive impact on a country’s payoff in a single
interaction but that harm the overall relationship are unattractive because the one time
benefit is usually outweighed by the costs imposed on all future interactions.148
145 The WTO provides a dispute settlement mechanism under which, if all else fails, a
complaining party may impose sanctions on a party found to have violated its WTO obligations. Uruguay
Round Understanding on the Rules and Procedures Governing the Settlement of Disputes, art. 22.
146 Cf. Simmons, Law of Money, supra note 5, at 325 (“there is suggestive evidence that the more
a polity has invested in such a reputation, the less willing a government will be to tarnish its reputation
through non-compliance.”).
147 It may be considered something of a fiction to imagine a one-time interaction among states in
the modern world. For expositional purposes, however, it is convenient to assume that states can have
such a relationship. The point that emerges from the analysis is not limited to simple one-shot
interactions versus complex ongoing ones. The more complex a relationship is, and the more the parties
expect a close relationship in the future, the greater is the effect of international law.
148 This conclusion must be qualified slightly because the reputational loss from a single violation
may be less severe in a relationship with many interactions. That is, states in a complex bilateral
relationship may already have definite views about the other state’s willingness to comply with
Compliance-Based Theory
51
Even complex, bilateral relationships of course, are not free from violations of
international law, and the theory presented in this Article does not predict perfect
compliance. The model predicts that such violations will be less common in a complex
bilateral relationship than in simple or multilateral relationships.
Finally, notice that countries engaged in many interactions with one another,
and facing a high cost for violations of international law, have a great deal to gain from a
system in which they are able to select from a menu of commitment levels. States in a
close relationship sometimes prefer to have the most reliable commitment possible – in
the form of treaties. In other cases, they prefer to leave themselves the ability to change
their minds. They may, therefore, enter into a less binding agreement such as an
“understanding” or some other such commitment. By adjusting the level of
commitment, states are able to signal their willingness to honor their promise in the
future and, therefore, can control the amount of reputational capital they stake as
collateral. This flexibility allows states that enjoy a high level of mutual trust to enter
into agreements that come with only low levels of commitment. Without the ability to
modulate the level of reputational capital pledged, states would sometimes choose to
make no deal at all rather than accept an obligation that they may not keep.
An ongoing relationship obviously has an important influence on the usefulness
of punitive sanctions. As already discussed, there is no incentive to apply such
sanctions in a one-shot or finitely repeated game. The more the relationship between
two countries resembles a one-shot, or short-term interaction, the less likely it is that
punitive sanctions will be used. This is so because short-term interactions cause the
participants to have a high discount rate – making it less likely that they will impose a
penalty that is costly to themselves in order to achieve greater compliance in the future.
D. Acceptance of Sanctions
States that violate an international obligation can, under certain conditions, be
induced to accept a sanction voluntarily. If states are willing to submit to a penalty, it is
possible to make the sanction much more effective. Rather than simply imposing a
reputational sanction plus whatever direct sanctions are available, the punishment can
be tailored to the precise violation. The benefits of such a system include the
opportunity to resolve disputes through arbitration or some other form of dispute
resolution, a lower cost imposed on complaining states than is the case with retaliatory
sanctions, the ability to adopt optimal sanctions, and the potential to choose sanctions
that are less disruptive to the international community.
international law. Because reputations have been formed over many, many interactions, a single violation
may have only a small impact. Nevertheless, a complex relationship increases the value of developing and
maintaining a reputation for compliance because the benefits from such a reputation can be felt in all the
different facets of the relationship.
Compliance-Based Theory
52
A state will submit to punishment when the costs of that punishment are
exceeded by the costs of a failure to accept the punishment. Thus, for example,
countries that have signed a bilateral investment treaty (BIT) typically are willing to
submit to arbitration in order to resolve disputes with investors because a failure to do so
may lead to a cancellation of the relevant BIT (and perhaps other BITs) and such
cancellation would be more costly than the sanction imposed by the dispute settlement
process.149 Within the WTO, a state that violates its obligations is expected to
voluntarily bring its conduct into conformity with WTO obligations. If it fails to do so,
the parties to the dispute are to negotiate an appropriate compensation for the injured
party. Finally, if these efforts fail, the injured party can seek authority from the dispute
settlement body to impose retaliatory measures. The offending party is expected to
accept the imposition of these measures.150 Within the European Union, states that lose
decisions before the European Court of Justice comply with those rulings because a
failure to do so imposes too great a risk for the success of the European Union and the
place of the country within the Union.151
More generally, a country is likely to accept established procedures for dealing
with violations of international law when it faces a severe sanction for a failure to accept
punishment (such as expulsion from a treaty or organization), when the consequences of
a failure to accept punishment imposes large costs on the country (such as actions that
risk tearing down the EU), and when a failure to accept punishment imposes large
reputational costs (such as a reputation for ignoring established dispute resolution
procedures).152
If states submit disputes to some form of dispute resolution and agree to abide by
the sanction that is handed down, it becomes possible to construct a more effective and
efficient set of rules. In particular, it is possible to specify sanctions that are consistent
with sound contract principles, the most prominent of which is expectations damages.153
It is well established in the domestic contracts literature that the preferred measure of
149 Even if no BIT is cancelled, a failure to honor the dispute settlement obligation under a BIT
will harm the country’s efforts to attract new investment.
150 Uruguay Round Understanding on the Rules and Procedures Governing the Settlement of
Disputes, art. 21-22.
151 The notion that states may comply with international law because they do not want to
undermine the international legal system has been advanced Professor Trimble. A country “may decide
to forego the short-term advantages derived from violating rules because it has an overriding interest in
maintaining the overall system.” Phillip R. Trimble, International Law, World Order and Critical Legal
Studies, 42 STAN. L. REV. 811, 833 (1990). The claim in this Article is more modest. It is merely asserted
that within an organization – especially one that is still being formed – individual states that value the
organization may comply with the rules of that institution even when doing so imposes some short term
costs.
152 See Charles Lipson, Why are Some International Agreements Informal?, 45 INT’L ORG. 495, 506
(Autumn 1991).
153 The actual identification of appropriate damages for any given offense will be difficult because
it is hard to determine the value of damages caused by violations of international law.
Compliance-Based Theory
53
damages is expectation damages. This is so primarily because it leads to efficient breach.
If countries accept sanctions handed down by a dispute settlement procedure, a system
of expectation damages can be established within the international legal system. As in
the domestic context, this will lead to breach if and only if breach is efficient.154
V. RETHINKING INTERNATIONAL LAW
In this Part the Article uses the theory developed up to this point in order to
take a fresh look at international law. CIL and treaties, the traditional sources of
international law, are reconsidered, as are international obligations that fall short of the
classical definition of international law. The Article then discusses how the theory
advanced herein affects existing theories of international law and compliance. Finally,
the appropriate role of international law is discussed. It is demonstrated why many of
the topics upon which international law has focused the most attention are precisely the
areas in which international law is least likely to influence outcomes. The implications
of this fact are then explored, including the need to redirect some of the energies of
international law scholars.
A. Treaties
The most formal and reliable form of international commitment is the treaty.155
Treaties offer several advantages in addition to signaling a high level of commitment.
They represent clear and well-defined obligations of states, they can provide for explicit
dispute resolution,156 and define rules for accession and exit.157 In addition, third parties
can observe their content with relative ease. Treaties can also provide for sanctions, the
most obvious of which are the ability of counter-parties to cancel the treaty if it is
154 It should be noted that reputation may interfere with the theory of efficient breach in the
international context. To the extent that a country which violates an international commitment and
subsequently submits to the relevant dispute settlement process nevertheless suffers a loss of reputation,
expectation damages would over-deter, causing too little violation of international law. On the other
hand, a regime in which a violating state fully compensates other states for a breach may reduce the role
of reputation. When states agree to a commitment, the reliability of one’s counter-party is less important
if it is known that the counter-party can be sanctioned for a violation. The provision of expectation
damages implies that the party who suffers from a violation of international law will do no worse in the
event of a violation than if the law were complied with. For this reason, that state need not concern itself
with the reputation of other states.
155 Treaties are also the focus of most theories of compliance with international law. See Koh,
supra note 2; Oscar Schacter, Toward a Theory of International Obligation, 8 VA. J. INT’L L. 300, 301
(1968).
156 See e.g., NAFTA.
157 There are various other costs and benefits involved in treaties that are not directly relevant to
the question of how treaties impact behavior. These include, for example, the fact that treaties often take
longer to negotiate than less formal agreements and that they must be approved by signatory governments
(which may increase the chances that the treaty will be honored because it increases the level of domestic
support and may entrench the agreement in domestic laws).
Compliance-Based Theory
54
violated, the potential for a sanction imposed by the treaty itself, and the reputational
impact of a violation. States agree to an elevated level of commitment in the form of a
treaty because doing so is required in order to obtain an elevated level of commitment
from others. A treaty, therefore, should be viewed as a contractual commitment by a
group of states. By using the treaty mechanism states are able to increase one another’s
reputational stake and thereby increase the costs of breach.158
Within traditional international law, all treaties are considered equivalent in the
sense that they are all “binding.”159 Without a theory of compliance, however, it is
impossible to consider the circumstances under which violations take place or to
develop strategies to improve the compliance pull of a treaty.
When viewed through the lens of a reputational model of international law, it is
clear that not all treaties have the same impact on national incentives or the same
chance of influencing a country’s behavior. At least two dimensions are critical to an
understanding of treaty compliance. The first is the reputational impact of a violation,
which has already been discussed.
The second dimension is the cost of compliance, which is informed by the
subject matter of the treaty. Treaties that implicate critical issues of national security
and other issues of central importance to states are less likely to succeed in tipping the
scales in favor of compliance. These treaties implicate issues of profound national
importance and it is unlikely that reputation will be enough to change a country’s course
of action from violation to compliance. In other words, the decision of whether to act in
accordance with the treaty will most likely be made based on costs and benefits that
have nothing to do with international law, but instead relate to questions of national
security.160
B. A New Definition of Customary International Law
Customary international law is the second form of international law that is
recognized by traditional scholars. Unlike treaties, however, CIL is not the product of
explicit bargaining and formal ratification. Under the traditional interpretation, it arises
instead from widespread state practice and opinio juris – a sense of legal obligation. The
theory advanced in this Article suggests that the standard understanding of CIL needs
to be rethought. This section outlines some of the changes that should be made in how
CIL is understood.
158 See Lipson, supra note 152, at 508.
159 See Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, May 23, 1969, U.N. Doc. A/Conf. 39/27
(1969), art. 18.
160 One can certainly imagine cases in which the decision to honor or violate a military treaty is
such a close one that the reputational consequences will make a difference. The more important the
issues at stake, however, the less likely it is that such a case will come about.
Compliance-Based Theory
55
Most international law scholars acknowledge that our understanding of CIL
suffers from a variety of well known problems.161 First, there is no agreement on how
widespread a custom must be in order to satisfy the “state practice requirement” and,
indeed, there is not even a consensus on what counts as state practice. Among the
instruments that are sometimes considered as evidence of state practice are treaties
(both bilateral and multilateral), national laws, and governmental statements of policy.
The required duration of the state practice is similarly difficult to pin down. Related to
the question of duration is the question of continuity. It is difficult to know if a single
act, inconsistent with the practice, is enough to undermine that practice. If it is not,
there is no agreement on how much discontinuity is enough. Second, the opinio juris
requirement fares no better as a theoretical matter than does the state practice
requirement. Professor D’Amato refers to the circularity of opinio juris as its “fatal
defect.” “How can Custom create law if its psychological component requires action in
conscious accordance with preexisting law?”162 The lack of a sound theoretical
foundation for CIL makes it difficult to identify how CIL comes into being and how it
changes over time.163
The problems with CIL have led many to question whether it exists at all as a
relevant force in international law.164 Among the recent critics of CIL are Professors
Goldsmith and Posner, who have offered a forceful challenge to its relevance.165 The
basic model advanced by Goldsmith & Posner is essentially the realist model presented
Part III.A.166 They adopt a one period model, which means that they are assured of
establishing the theoretical result that international law has no independent effect.167
They note that some people believe reputation serves to encourage compliance, but
express considerable skepticism about the role of reputation.168 They suggest that other
161 See ANTONY D’AMATO, THE CONCEPT OF CUSTOM IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 6-10 (Cornell
Univ. Press, 1971).
162 Id., at 66.
163 See BYERS, supra note 22, at 180-83 (1999).
164 See, e.g., Francis A. Boyle, The Irrelevance of International Law: The Schism Between
International Law and International Politics, 10 CALIF. WESTERN INT’L L.J. 193, 198 (“International law is
therefore irrelevant to those matters which count the most, or more forcefully, to those matters which
count for anything in international relations.”)
165 See Godlsmith & Posner, supra note 2; Jack L. Goldsmith & Eric A. Posner, Understanding the
Resemblance between Modern and Traditional Customary International Law, 40 VA. J. INT’L L. 639 (2000).
166 See Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2, at 1121-28.
167 See Part III.A and page 22 (showing that assuming a one shot game is equivalent to assuming
that international law is irrelevant). To be fair to Goldsmith & Posner, they leave open the possibility of
cooperation in an infinitely repeated game, see Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2, at 1124-27, though
they give this case very limited attention and clearly doubt its impact on behavior. See Goldsmith &
Posner, supra note 165, at 641 (“CIL as an independent normative force has little if any impact on
national behavior.”).
168 See Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2, at 1135 (“it is hard to see why reputation would play
an important role in explaining compliance with CIL norms beyond the limited sense in which it describes
a tit-for-tat and related strategies in the repeat bilateral prisoner’s dilemma.”).
Compliance-Based Theory
56
concerns – specifically the desire to violate international law when compliance would
injure local interests – trumps reputational concerns.169 This response to a reputational
argument is unpersuasive, however, because a sophisticated appeal to reputation must
recognize that it operates only at the margins. Where there is a powerful domestic
incentive to violate the law, it is clear that reputation will be insufficient to cause
compliance. On the other hand, reputational concerns may be enough to tip the scales
in favor of compliance in close cases. This argument does not deny the relevance of
national objectives in addition to reputation. Rather it points out that reputation is an
additional factor that must be taken into account.170
Though skeptical of the role of reputation as a theoretical matter, they concede
that it seems to matter in the actual behavior of states.171 Their attempt to explain this
fact leads them close to the position adopted in this Article. They state that “[o]ne
plausible equilibrium is one in which state i keeps its promises even if the promises are
against its immediate interest.”172
Thus, although the tone of Goldsmith & Posner’s CIL article, along with the
main theory they advance, suggests that they view CIL as irrelevant to international law,
they stop short of claiming that CIL has no impact on national behavior.173 In later
writing, however, Goldsmith & Posner adopt a stronger and simpler position, stating
that “[t]he faulty premise is that CIL – either the traditional or the new – influences
national behavior.”174
Although I have disagreements with the conclusions Goldsmith & Posner draw,
they deserve praise for bringing the analytical tools of international relations and
economics to the study of CIL. Like them, I believe that this approach to the study of
international law offers considerable potential and we share the hope that its use will
continue to grow.
169 See id. at 1135.
170 Goldsmith & Posner themselves do not seem to disagree with this claim, stating “[o]ne might
conclude that all things equal, nations will strive to have a reputation for compliance with international
law, but a reputation for compliance will not always be of paramount concern because all things are not
equal.” Id. at 1136. This statement is essentially the same as the observation in the text that reputation is
a factor relevant to decision making. Goldsmith & Posner also make reference to the fact that states may
have reputational concerns that do not lead to increased compliance. For example, states may seek a
reputation for toughness. This Article has already addressed this point, see supra, TAN 101, explaining
that even in the presence of these other factors, the cost of a reputational loss will affect the payoffs felt by
states and, therefore, their incentives.
171 Id. at 1136 (“states seem to care about their reputations under certain circumstances”).
172 Id. at 1137.
173 The concluding sentence in the piece states that “CIL has real content, but it is much less
robust than traditional scholars think, and it operates in a different fashion.” Id. at 1177.
174 See Jack L. Goldsmith & Eric A. Posner, Understanding the Resemblance Between Modern and
Traditional Customary International Law, 40 VA. J. INT’L L. 639, 640 (2000).
Compliance-Based Theory
57
Turning to the substance of their writing, to the extent that they claim CIL is
irrelevant to national conduct, they appear to have gone beyond what either the theory
or the evidence suggest. As the general theory advanced in this Article suggests, it is
possible for CIL to influence state behavior through both reputational and direct
sanctions. Even if direct sanctions are weak – as they surely are with respect to CIL –
reputational sanctions may be enough to generate compliance.
Goldsmith & Posner restrict their claims to CIL, resisting the temptation to
apply their model to treaties and other international agreements. In their view, treaties
“record the action that will count as cooperative moves in an ongoing prisoner’s
dilemma or the actions that achieve the highest joint payoff in a coordination game.”175
This description is consistent with the reputational model of compliance presented in
this Article. They go on to state, however, that “[o]n this view, the treaty itself does
not have independent binding force.”176 On this point we disagree. By allowing states
to establish clear rules and pledge their reputation, treaties cause the behavior of states
to change, which I term independent binding force. Our disagreement, however, may
be no more than semantics as we appear to agree that the use of treaties can alter
outcomes. My definition of “independent binding force” looks to whether or not state
incentives are changed. Their definition requires that states feel a legal obligation.
My objection to their brief discussion of treaties is focused primarily on the
relationship between their theory of CIL and treaties. The distinction that they draw
between treaties and CIL seems to turn on the greater clarity and precision of treaties.
If clarity is the key difference between treaties and CIL, however, it seems that
Goldsmith & Posner’s realist theory would apply to treaties in the same way as it applies
to CIL. Admittedly clarity would make it easier to identify a “law” under a treaty than
under CIL, but it is not clarity that drives their theory of CIL. Rather, their theory relies
on the assumption that the proper model is a one-shot game.177
To distinguish treaties from CIL, therefore, it is necessary to explain why CIL
should be modeled with a one-shot game and treaties should not. Goldsmith and
Posner note that “[s]tates refrain from violating treaties (when they do) because they
fear retaliation from the treaty partner(s), or because they fear a failure of
coordination.”178 Their message is that CIL does not lead to retaliation because its
content is too uncertain to cause retaliation and coordination through CIL is doomed
from the outset.
An alternative interpretation of CIL – one that addresses the theoretical
difficulties with the traditional approach without denying the existence of CIL – is
suggested by the theory advanced in this Article. Under that theory, CIL represents a
175 Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2, at 1171.
176 Id.
177 See Goldsmith & Posner, supra note 2, at 1121-28.
178 Id. at 1171.
Compliance-Based Theory
58
form of legal obligation that countries have toward one another, even without explicit
agreement on their part. That much is consistent with the traditional view of legal
scholars.
When viewed more carefully, however, the traditional perspective on CIL begins
to look incomplete. Most obviously, CIL suffers from severe problems of clarity because
it arises from the practice of states rather than explicit commitments, there is no clear
rule about the number of states required to satisfy the practice requirement, and the
opinio juris concept is difficult to define satisfactorily and even more difficult to apply in
practice. Furthermore, violations of CIL are difficult to identify because the rules
themselves are often vague. Even when violations take place and are unambiguous,
they can sometimes be justified through the use of the persistent objector exception to
CIL.179 The problem of clarity has predictable consequences.180 It weakens the abilities
of states to identify violations, and it reduces the incentive to sanction violators. In
other words, CIL represents a weak form of international law.
Viewing customary international law as a weak form of international
commitment is consistent with both the existence of CIL and all of its “problems.”
Indeed, under this view, the problems of CIL are not problems at all, but rather factors
that either cause CIL to be a weak form of commitment or represent the product of that
weakness. For example, the ambiguity regarding the content of CIL makes it a much
weaker mechanism through which to pledge reputational collateral. Because the
content is uncertain, states can often claim to have complied even when they have
ignored the content of CIL. In other words, the commitment to CIL is more easily
avoided than the commitment to a treaty. Like a contract that can be revoked at any
time, an international commitment that can be avoided has very limited force. To
demonstrate that even the limited force of CIL can matter, however, consider the
example of diplomatic immunity. The immunity of diplomats from the jurisdiction of
local courts was a longstanding principle of CIL,181 and was widely, though not
universally respected. This is what one would expect because the cost of providing
diplomatic immunity is normally small when compared with the reputational cost of
violating it.
The above discussion suggests a new definition of CIL. Under the model
developed in this Article, international law (including CIL) consists of norms whose
violation will harm a country’s reputation as a law-abiding state. Compare this view to
the traditional definition of CIL. The practice requirement, present in traditional
accounts of CIL, is not an explicit factor under a reputational account of international
179 See IAN BROWNLIE, PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 512-15 (4th ed. 1990). But
see Jonathan I. Charney, Universal International Law, 87 AMER. J. INT’L L. 529, 538-39 (1993) (arguing
that the persistent objector rule is rarely used and may not be effective in practice.”).
180 See supra at 43.
181 See IAN BROWNLIE, PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW (3d ed. 1979) 345-59.
Compliance-Based Theory
59
law. The practice requirement becomes important indirectly, however, if it is the only
way in which a particular norm comes to be seen as an obligation.
The traditional definition of CIL requires that the opinio juris requirement be
satisfied. Unlike the traditional conception of opinio juris, what matters under the
theory advanced in this Article is that countries other than the offending state believe
that there is such an obligation. That is, a state faces a norm of CIL if other states
believe that the state has such an obligation and if those other states will view a failure
to honor that obligation as a violation. Only under these circumstances will a violation
by the state lead to a reputational loss. If, for example, respect for the principles of
diplomatic immunity is considered a legal obligation, then a violation of those rules will
be viewed by other states (or perhaps only the offended state) in a negative light, and
cause them to doubt the reliability of the offending state -- making them less prone to
trust state A in the future. One should not exaggerate the impact of such an action, of
course. If the violation is viewed as minor and of little impact on the offended state, the
reputational consequences should be small.
The good news for traditional international law scholars is that this Article offers
a theoretical model that is consistent with the existence of CIL. The bad news,
however, is that the model does not predict that CIL represents a powerful legal
constraint. Problems of clarity and a lack of explicit commitment on the part of states
make CIL weaker than treaties. CIL looks even less potent when one remembers that
reputational constraints have limited power even under ideal circumstances. Thus,
while it is true that the existence of CIL is consistent with the theory presented herein,
the actual impact of CIL on decisions is an empirical question, the answer to which is
left for future research. Therefore, although I do not agree with the claim of Professors
Goldsmith and Posner when they assert that CIL does not matter, I believe that it is a
weak force on international law and may only affect outcomes infrequently.182 If
reputation plays a small enough role, simply ignoring it and adopting a realist model may
be appropriate. Of course, if the reputational impact of a violation of CIL is significant,
the realist model should not be used.
Unfortunately, we simply do not know how much reputational capital is at stake
with respect to CIL. It is clear that CIL is weaker than treaties because CIL is typically
not clearly specified – making its boundaries ambiguous. There is often debate about
whether a particular norm of CIL exists at all, and countries normally have not
consented to CIL in an explicit way – making their commitment to it uncertain. For all
of these reasons, the possibility that CIL is so weak as to be negligible cannot be
dismissed until some form of empirical evidence becomes available.183
182 To the extent that the theory advanced by Professors Goldsmith and Posner is extended
beyond CIL to treaties or other agreements, my disagreement with their theoretical claims becomes more
vigorous.
183 Goldsmith & Posner offer some case studies of CIL in support of their theory. See Goldsmith
& Posner, supra note 2, at 1139-67. This evidence, of course, suffers from the usual problems with case
Compliance-Based Theory
60
Regardless of the empirical importance of CIL as a category, the reputational
model provides a more satisfactory framework within which to view CIL than does the
realist model. Under a realist model one must either treat all international law as
irrelevant – a position that is, to my knowledge, not advocated by any legal scholar – or
treat CIL as different in kind from other forms of international obligation. The latter
option leads to an awkward framework in which each form of international obligation is
explained through a separate theory and it becomes difficult to consider the many
different forms of obligation together. That theory also fails to explain behavior in those
circumstances in which CIL seems to matter, such as diplomatic immunity. The
reputational model, on the other hand, views the many different forms of international
agreement as points on a spectrum. CIL is perhaps the weakest form of international
law, but it is nevertheless part of the general framework. As the level of state
commitment increases, the reputational stake is raised and the commitment becomes
more credible. The theory not only explains CIL, but all forms of international
commitment. It also explains why nations choose one form of commitment over the
other and why states expend resources in order to comply, or appear to comply, with
their commitments.
C. A New Definition of International Law
The previous section proposed a new definition of CIL that turns on the
question of whether a state is perceived, by other states, to have a legal obligation and
whether a failure to live up to that obligation harms the state’s reputation. This section
proposes a broadening of the definition of international law to more explicitly include
obligations that are neither treaties nor CIL.
In the domestic law of contracts, it makes sense to use the term “law” to
distinguish promises that are enforceable from those that are not.184 In that context, a
party to an agreement takes on a legal commitment only if the contract is enforceable.
A legal obligation, therefore, is a promise that is backed by the coercive power of the
studies. First, without observing how countries would behave in the absence of CIL it is difficult to draw
conclusions about how they actually behaved. For example, violations of the three-mile territorial sea rule
that existed during the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries cannot be cited as examples of the failure
of CIL unless one knows that no states were ever affected by the rule. It is impossible to determine if
there would have been more violations in the absence of a rule of CIL. Second, periodic violation of
international law is consistent with the reputational model advanced herein and should be consistent with
any sensible model of compliance. As a result, pointing to incidents of a failure to comply does not
distinguish one theory from another. Finally, if one is trying to support the realist position that CIL has
no effect, one must provide more than evidence that it is sometimes ignored. Rather, one must show that
it is always ignored and that state behavior is never changed by CIL – a task that simply cannot be
accomplished through case studies. On the other hand, even a single example in which CIL can be
shown to influence behavior would be sufficient to disprove the realist theory.
184 Under standard common law principles, for example, a promise without consideration is not
enforceable.
Compliance-Based Theory
61
state. Absent a legal commitment, there is no legal requirement that a promise be
honored.
When using the term “law” in the international context, however, analogies to
domestic contract law are difficult. In particular, it makes no sense to restrict the use of
the term “law” to promises that are legally enforceable because the international arena
lacks a coercive enforcement mechanism. One cannot, therefore, analogize
international promises to domestic promises in order to distinguish promises with a legal
obligation from those without. If one were to pursue an analogy to domestic law closely,
it is difficult to see what would qualify as “law” in the international context. The
associated conclusion that very little of international law qualifies as law, however, does
nothing to help us understand the operation of international law. A vocabulary is
needed to distinguish promises made by states that affect incentives and behavior, and
the term law seems to be sufficient for that purpose.
1. Soft Law
The classical definition of international law limits that term to treaties and
customary international law.185 This definition excludes promises made by states
through instruments that fall short of a full scale treaty such as memorandum of
understanding, executive agreements, nonbonding treaties, joint declarations, final
communiqués, agreements pursuant to legislation, and so on. The place of such
commitments, sometimes referred to as “soft law,” within the framework of international
law is uncertain.186 What is clear is that soft law is considered less “law” than the “hard
law” of treaties and custom. The focus of international legal scholars is often exclusively
on treaties and custom, as if soft law either does not exist or has no impact.187 Although
only occasionally stated explicitly, the general presumption appears to be that soft law is
in some sense less binding than the traditional sources of international law, and states
are accordingly less likely to comply.188
185 Strictly speaking, the most traditional definition of international law also includes “general
principles of law recognized by civilized nations;” and “judicial decisions and the teachings of the most
highly qualified publicists of the various nations, as a subsidiary means for the determination of rules of
law.” See art. 38, Statute of the International Court of Justice.
186 For more about "soft law," see Wellens & Borchardt, Soft Law in European Community Law, 14
EUR. L. REV. 267 (1989); A Hard Look at Soft Law, 82 ASIL PROC. 371 (1988); Gruchalla-Wesierski, A
Framework for Understanding 'Soft Law," 30 McGILL L. J. 37 (1984). The term “soft-law” is used herein to
denote law that falls short of the classical definition of international law. This is a common usage of the
term, but it is not the only one. Some use the term to describe rules that meet the classical definition but
that are imprecise of weak. See Prosper Weil, Toward Relative Normativity in International Law, 77 AM. J.
INT’L L. 413, 414 n. 7 (1983) (“It would seem better to reserve the term “soft law” for rules that are
imprecise and not really compelling, since sublegal obligations are neither “soft law” not “hard law”: They
are simply not law at all.”).
187 See Steven R. Ratner, Does International Law Matter In Preventing Ethnic Conflict?, 32 N.Y.U.J.
INT’L L. & POL. 591, 652 (2000).
188 Pieter van Dijk, Normative Force and Effectiveness of International Norms, 30 GERMAN Y.B.
Compliance-Based Theory
62
Confusion over the role of soft law is due in part to the fact that discussions of
compliance have, by and large, failed to address the question.189 As a result, soft law
remains largely outside the theoretical framework of international legal scholars.190 This
is a curious fact because many instruments that are not considered “law” under the
classical definition have a substantial impact on the behavior of states.191 If the term
“law” is used to identify promises that are particularly difficult to break, there is nothing
to distinguish treaties and CIL from memoranda of understanding, ministerial accords,
executive agreements, non-binding treaties, joint declarations, final communiqués,
agreements pursuant to legislation, and other informal agreements. The latter should
also be considered forms of international law.192
If one is to defend a definition of international law that is limited to treaties and
CIL, it is necessary to argue that other forms of international commitment have no
impact on country behavior. This claim, of course, faces the same problem as realist
claims that international law is irrelevant. It cannot explain why agreements that are
not treaties are concluded at all, why countries want to be seen as being in compliance
with these obligations, or why a country would ever refuse to join a “non-binding”
agreement.193 This view is also challenged by the fact that experts in many fields believe
that agreements that fall short of the classical definition of international law have a
substantial impact on the behavior of states.
Like treaties, non-binding agreements benefit from a high degree of clarity and
are often drafted by specialists with deep technical knowledge. Because these
agreements are not treaties, they are often relatively easy to change and can be
concluded more quickly and with less attention.
Unlike treaties, however, they do not represent a complete pledge of a nation’s
reputational capital. The agreements are made with an understanding that they
INT'L L. 9, 20 (1987). Perhaps the most traditional position views agreements other than treaties as
nothing more than evidence of custom. See Pierre-Marie Dupuy, Soft Law and the International Law of the
Environment, 12 MICH. J. INT’L L. 420, 432 (1991). Under another view, soft law “tends to blur the line
between the law and the non-law, be that because merely aspirational norms are accorded legal status,
albeit of a secondary nature; be that because the intended effect of its usage may be to undermine the
status of established legal norms” Remarks by Professor Handl, A Hard Look at Soft Law, 82 Am. Soc’y
Int’l L. Proc. 371, 371 (1988).
189 Ratner, supra note 187, at 654. But see INTERNATIONAL COMPLIANCE WITH NONBINDING
ACCORDS (Edith Brown Weiss ed., 1997); COMMITMENT AND COMPLIANCE: THE ROLE OF NON-BINDING
NORMS IN THE INTERNATIONAL LEGAL SYSTEM (Dinah Shelton, ed. 2000) (analyzing 'soft law' in
environment and natural resources, trade and finance, human rights, and multilateral arms control).
190 Handl, supra note 188, at 372.
191 “A wide variety of instruments, declarations, joint statements, and expressions, loosely
categorized as “soft law,” are accepted and enforced as constraints by processes that differ little from those
applicable to formal legal undertakings” CHAYES & CHAYES, supra note 4, at 2; Handl, supra note 188, at
372.
192 Lipson, supra note 152, at 502.
193 See supra TAN 80.
Compliance-Based Theory
63
represent a level of commitment that falls below that of a treaty. The violation of such
an agreement, therefore, carries a less severe reputational penalty than would be the
case if it were a treaty. That said, a failure to honor the terms of such an agreement is
not costless. The reputational costs imposed on violations can take two forms. First,
there is the reputational loss to the country itself. A state that routinely ignores
promises that fall short of treaties will find that it cannot extract concessions in
exchange for such promises.
Second, an additional reputational cost is present when the agreement in
question is negotiated and agreed to by government ministers or other agents of the
state. If the commitments of these individuals are not honored by their countries, they
will be handicapped in their future attempts to enter into such agreements. For
example, the Basle Accord was negotiated and agreed to by the central bankers of 12
countries.194 Although this Accord is not a treaty and, as a result, is not considered
binding under traditional definitions of international law, a central banker whose
country failed to supervise banking activity in a manner consistent with the Accord
would surely face a loss of influence in the international regulation of banking and make
it more difficult to enter into future negotiations. The individual government officials
making the promises, therefore, have an incentive not to promise too much and to
encourage their government to honor promises that are made. Failure to do so will lead
to a reduction in international influence for both themselves and their countries.195
One can hardly doubt the important role that these agreements play in the
coordination of international activity. The Basle Accord demonstrates how these
agreements can change state behavior. The Accord was adopted in 1988,196 and
provided for a transition period that expired in 1992. At that time, most international
banks in major industrial countries were in compliance.197 Japan, in particular, made
significant changes to its capital adequacy rules.198
194 The countries are: Belgium, Canada, France, Germany, Italy, Japan, Luxembourg, the
Netherlands, Sweden, Switzerland, the United Kingdom, and the United States. See Duncan E. Alford,
Basle Committee Minimum Standards: International Regulatory Response To The Failure Of BCCI, 26 GEO.
WASH. J. INT'L L. & ECON. 241, 241 n. 1 (1992).
195 It should be noted that agreements that fall short of treaties and that are negotiated by
government agents are often implemented by the same agents that negotiated them. For example, the
Basle Accord was negotiated by central bank governors and bank supervisors. These same individuals and
their institutions had the authority to bring domestic regulations into compliance with Accord. This is an
additional reason why, as a practical matter, these agreements are able to influence the behavior of states.
196 See Frederick M. Struble & Norah Barger, International Capital Standards for Banking
Institutions, in 1 REGULATION OF FOREIGN BANKS (Michael Gruson & Ralph Reisner, eds.).
197 See HAL SCOTT & PHILIP WELLONS, INTERNATIONAL FINANCE: TRANSACTIONS, POLICY &
REGULATION (5th ed. 1998).
198 In 1986, Japan had a ratio of tangible equity to total assets of 1.9 percent. In 1992, four years
after the Accord came into being, that ratio was 3.42 percent.
Compliance-Based Theory
64
Indeed, the reputational cost of a failure to honor the Basle Accord could easily
extend beyond the banking arena. To the extent that such action is perceived as a
signal that a country does not take the promises of its negotiators seriously in the
absence of a formal international legal commitment, such action could undermine all
efforts to negotiate non-binding agreements.
2. A Functional Definition of International Law
Under the model proposed in this Article, the difference between the traditional
sources of international law and promises made by states that traditionally are not
viewed as sources of law is one of degree. Different types of agreements among states
represent different points on a spectrum of commitment. The same reputational issues
influence such promises regardless of the form in which they are made.
This theory implies that the traditional separation of treaties from soft law is
difficult to maintain because there is no clear distinction between treaties and other
promises. The classical formulation is even more problematic when one considers
customary international law. The reputational capital at stake with respect to many
rules of CIL is almost certainly less than what is at stake with some soft law agreements,
such as the Basle Accord. The classical definition of international law, therefore,
identifies the relatively powerful instrument of treaties and the relatively weak
instrument of CIL, but does not recognize obligations whose force often lies between
these two extremes. In other words, tension exists between the classical theory of
international law and its practice.
Reconciling theory and practice requires a new theoretical approach. The most
straightforward way to do so is to revise the definition of international law. It should be
one that is functional rather than doctrinal. Rather than simply a list of what is and is
not considered international law, the new definition should describe the characteristics
of international law. Instruments that fit that definition should then be considered
international law.
The question of interest in this Article is whether the practice of making an
international commitment alters the behavior of countries. It is tempting, therefore, to
define international law in an outcome-based fashion – applying the label of
international law to those international obligations that change behavior and denying it
from obligations that do not. A definition of this sort, however, ignores the fact that
laws, even domestic laws, can do nothing more than alter the incentives of actors. The
law itself cannot determine outcomes. For example, a law against speeding is no less a
law when people speed. It is a law because it increases the expected cost of speeding.
A definition of international law that turns on changed outcomes is also
problematic because an international commitment may be respected in one context but
not in another. Imagine, for example, a state’s commitment to honor certain territorial
boundaries between itself and its two neighbors. The state may choose to violate the
agreed upon boundary between itself and one neighbor, but refrain from violating the
Compliance-Based Theory
65
boundary with its other neighbor. A definition that turns on outcomes would have to
label the commitment international law with respect to one neighbor, but not the other.
In fact, until the moment at which a country decides whether or not to honor the
commitment it would be impossible to determine whether there was an applicable
international law at all. In other words, the term international law would be reduced to
a synonym for honoring commitments.
The definition of international law, therefore, should turn on the impact of a
promise on national incentives. With that in mind, this Article defines international
law to be those international commitments that make compliance materially more
attractive than would be the case in the absence of a commitment. In some instances
this change in incentives will affect outcomes. In other cases, however, it will not.
The term international law, therefore, should be expanded to include a wider
range of international agreements and obligations. Just as domestic legal instruments
that fall short of statutes – including court rulings and administrative regulations -- can
reasonably be referred to as law, so can international instruments such as MOUs and
accords that do not constitute formal treaties. One can analogize the various
instruments of international law to domestic contracts with different liquidated damages
clauses. In the drafting of a contract, the parties can choose to specify the damages
owed in the event of breach. In a similar fashion, by choosing a particular form of
international agreement, states can moderate the amount of reputational capital that
they are pledging and, therefore, control the resulting loss of reputation if they fail to
live up to the agreement.
The proposed functional definition of international law reflects the fact that
international obligation comes in many different forms, with varying levels of
compliance pull. This is a significant departure from the conventional view of
international law which simply declares law to be binding. The new theory recognizes
the discrete categories of treaties, CIL, and soft law, though perhaps useful, do not
themselves define international law or represent the only possible levels of commitment.
Rather, they are attempts to describe the spectrum of commitment from which states
choose the level that suits their purposes at the time.
D. Revisiting Existing Theories
The theory presented in this Article allows us to revisit traditional international
law scholarship. With the perspective of a reputational model in mind, several of the
existing theories of international law can be better understood, critiqued, and
appreciated.
1. Legitimacy Theory
Franck’s legitimacy theory, for example, becomes more powerful and more
insightful once one understands the reputational model. Using that model, it is possible
Compliance-Based Theory
66
to add a more satisfying theoretical foundation to legitimacy theory. Legitimacy, as
Franck defines it, should be viewed as one of the factors that influence a nation’s
perceived level of commitment. Recall that the reputational sanction for a failure to
abide by international law depends on the extent to which other states believe a
violation is evidence of a state’s willingness to ignore the law. Franck’s definition of
legitimacy encompasses variables that determine whether a country is perceived to have
made a serious commitment (what Franck calls symbolic validation and coherence), and
whether that commitment is sufficiently clear for a violation to be unambiguous
(determinacy and adherence in Franck’s terms). Legitimacy, therefore, can be
considered a proxy for the existence of reputational collateral and the clarity of the rule.
Once legitimacy is understood in these terms, the entire framework presented in
this Article can be brought to bear. It becomes possible to understand why states
sometimes violate even the most legitimate laws, anticipate when states are most likely
to violate the law, and consider ways to increase the force of laws.199
Although Franck’s discussion of legitimacy is useful for what it says about
commitment, it is less successful in discussing the motives for compliance. If legitimacy
theory is embedded in a reputational model, however, the motives for compliance
become clear. As international commitments become more clearly defined, they are
perceived to be more binding, thereby increasing the reputational stake of participating
countries. Thus, as the level of legitimacy rises, the costs of violation also rise, making
compliance more attractive.
Although legitimacy theory can be understood within the reputational model, it
is important to recognize that even when viewed through the less of this model, it does
not provide an exhaustive account of how nations commit themselves. It would be a
mistake to simply use legitimacy theory, without more, in order to determine the level of
commitment because other factors – the existing relationship between the states, for
example – are also relevant. Nevertheless, if it is viewed as a proxy for the amount of
reputational collateral that is pledged with a promise, legitimacy theory can be useful.
2. Liberal Theories
The liberal theory championed by Professor Anne-Marie Slaughter can also be
incorporated within a reputational model. Recall that the liberal theory focuses on the
individual decision makers within a state rather than the state itself. Focusing on
individuals rather than states has the advantage of greater realism, but the disadvantage
of greater complexity. Critics of rational choice models featuring a unitary state are
correct when they point out that non-state actors are important. Recognition of this
fact affects the way in which one evaluates government actions. For example, if one
views national decisions as the product of domestic politics and interest groups, one can
199 Franck makes a brief allusion to the consequences of violating rules that are considered to be
legitimate, but does not develop that analysis. See Franck, supra note 7, at 708.
Compliance-Based Theory
67
no longer assume that countries pursue the well-being of their citizens. Instead, they
pursue whatever objectives emerge from the domestic political struggle.
Although this “public choice” approach to international law provides a coherent
and rich theory, it fails to provide clear predictions about national behavior.200 Without
such predictions, of course, it is impossible to develop a complete model of international
law. One is left with a dilemma. One can ignore the public choice issues and proceed
with a model of benign governments pursuing the national interest, or one can
incorporate the fact that governments do not always pursue the interests of their citizens
and accept that the theory will be unable to provide useful predictions.
This Article recognizes the dilemma of public choice issues, and deals with them
by segregating the analysis of national behavior from the analysis of a country’s policy
goals. The theory presented here predicts how countries will behave in an effort to
achieve their goals, but it does not predict what those goals will be or how they will be
identified. Whether the objectives are determined by the national interest, by interest
groups, or by the whims of a despot, the country faces the same set of questions when it
considers compliance with international law. Respect for international law leads to a
good reputation that allows the country to pursue its goals – whatever those goals are –
more effectively. On the other hand, compliance may impose costs that the country
would prefer to avoid – again, depending on its goals.
This Article has not assumed that governments always pursue those policies that
are best for the nation. No such assumption is necessary because neither the model
itself nor the conclusions drawn from it depend on that assumption. The manner in
which national policies are chosen is not specified, and lies outside the theory.
Liberal theories, unlike the theory presented here, seek to understand how
national policies are made. That is, they are interested in the political process that
generates state objectives. Once those objectives are identified, the theory presented in
this Article becomes relevant. Liberal theories, therefore, are best viewed as
complements to the reputational theory of compliance. While those theories offer an
explanation of how national goals are determined, the reputational theory explains how
pursuit of those goals interacts with international law. As Professor Slaughter has
stated, “once state interests are determined, governments do pursue them in a rational
unitary fashion.”201
200 For writings using a public choice approach to international law see, e.g., Warren F. Schwartz
& Alan O. Sykes, Toward A Positive Theory Of The Most Favored Nation Obligation And Its Exceptions In
The WTO/GATT System, 16 INT'L REV. L. & ECON. 27 (1996); Alan O. Sykes, Protectionism As A
"Safeguard": A Positive Analysis Of The GATT "Escape Clause" With Normative Speculations, 58 U. CHI. L.
REV. 255 (1991). For a thoughtful critique of public choice, see Steven P. Croley, Theories of Regulation:
Incorporating the Administrative Process, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 1, 41-56 (1998). For a more extensive
discussion of how public choice concerns can be integrated into a model of country behavior, see Andrew
T. Guzman, Choice of Law: New Foundations, mimeo (2000).
201 See Slaughter Burley, supra note 2, at 227.
Compliance-Based Theory
68
There are, of course, problems with separating domestic political decisions about
policy goals from decisions about compliance. For example, the ability of a country to
commit depends not only on the overall reputation of the country, but also on the
individuals and institutions making decisions. For example, commitments by the United
States to pay its international debts are generally credible, but in the case of its
obligations to pay dues to the United Nations, the commitment is not credible because
the chairman of the Senate Committee on Foreign Relations has tremendous influence
over the issue and is disinclined to have the payments made. In order to deal with these
problems one must use any theory of state behavior cautiously. It must be understood
that although the theory is generally reliable, it sometimes fails to take important
variables into account. As a result, reliance on the theory must be tempered with
judgment.202
E. The Problem of Large Stakes
All else equal, it is reasonable to expect that the compliance pull of international
law will be the weakest when the stakes at issue are large. This is so because
reputational effects have limited power. The likelihood that reputational effects are
sufficient to ensure compliance grows smaller as the stakes grow larger. For example,
the decision to use military force against another state is a serious one for any nation.
Both the costs and benefits from such an action are typically very large.203 Because the
stakes are so high, a country is unlikely to take an action that is otherwise contrary to its
interests in order to preserve its reputation. The value of a reputation for compliance
with international commitments is rarely large enough to affect the outcome when
decisions are of such great magnitude.204
Imagine, for example, that a country must decide whether or not to invade a
neighbor’s territory in violation of international law. Invading promises to provide
202 The interplay between domestic institutions and international law is a rich area of research
that is beyond the scope of this Article. The topic is being tackled by both international relations scholars
and legal scholars who are asking questions such as: are commitments made by and within the control of
the executive more reliable than those that rely on Congress? If private actors have a strong role in
shaping policy, does this make policy more short-sighted (which would reduce the value of reputation) or
more long-sighted? How should non-state actors be treated in the international legal system?
203 By this I mean that the costs of going to war – including human, economic, political, and
social – are large and a country will only choose to do so if it has strong reasons, which represent large
benefits.
204 Formally, it is not merely the magnitudes of the costs and benefits that matter, but also the
state’s discount rate at the time. The reputational cost of a violation of international law is something
that is felt over time. It is the loss of future agreements, opportunities, or good will that hurts a country
when it compromises its reputation. In order to evaluate such costs, a decision-maker must account for
the fact that they are in the future. That is, the present discounted value of those benefits must be
calculated. The discount rate that is applied to future losses varies based on the circumstances. In times
of war, for example, a country will weigh the present much more heavily than the future because there is
no guaranty that the state will continue to exist in its present form.
Compliance-Based Theory
69
benefits in the form of greater territory, resources, and a reduction in the strategic threat
from that neighbor. Label these benefits B.205 The cost of entering into the war includes
loss of life, economic costs, social costs, and so on. Label these costs C. In addition, a
decision to go to war would bring about a reputational loss in the international
community. Label this cost R. The reputational consequences of going to war will only
affect the decision if 0<B-C<R. That is, reputation is enough to prevent a war only if
the country would otherwise have gone to war, but the decision to do so was sufficiently
close that the reputational cost tips the balance in favor of peace. When the costs and
benefits of a particular action are small, there is a good chance that the reputational
consequences will tip the balance in favor of compliance with international law. Where
the costs and benefits other than reputation are relatively large, however, it is less likely
that reputational costs will be enough to alter the outcome.
The above discussion implicitly assumes that the reputational cost of violating an
international obligation is fixed. Under this assumption, international law has less effect
as the magnitudes at stake increase. Although convenient to demonstrate the point
that the most important issues are less likely to be affected by international law, the
assumption of a constant reputational cost for violations of such law is unrealistic.206
That being said, it remains true that reputation plays a more important role when the
costs and benefits of a particular action are small. This is so for at least two reasons.
First, there is an upper bound to the reputational cost that a country can suffer as a
result of a decision. Even a complete loss of reputation has a limited cost for a country,
and the reputation can be rebuilt over time. Furthermore, a single decision to violate
international law is unlikely to cause a complete loss of reputational capital. Faced with
a matter of great importance to a country, therefore, even the most severe reputational
sanction is unlikely to affect national behavior.
Second, although the reputational cost of a violation of international law can
vary based on the circumstances, it does not necessarily increase with the importance of
the issue. For example, a country’s decision to violate an arms control agreement may
impose reputational costs only in the area of arms control. Other states may recognize
that military and national security issues are central to a country’s identity, and that
treaties in that area are not particularly reliable.207 As a result, the violation of this sort
of treaty may not call into question the willingness of the state to honor a treaty in
another area, such as economic matters. Remember that violations of international law
impose a reputational cost because they have a negative impact on other countries’
205 To represent the risk that the war will be lost, B can be thought of as the benefits from a war
multiplied by the probability of victory.
206 See Lipson, supra note 152, at 509 (“Not all violations discredit equally”).
207 See RICHARD BAXTER, INTERNATIONAL LAW IN “HER INFINITE VARIETY,” 551 (stating that
treaties to declare alliances, establish neutral territories, or announce broad policy guidelines are “merely
joint statements of policy which will remain alive only so long as the states concerned see it to be in their
mutual interest to concert their policies. One simply cannot think of ‘violations’ of such instruments.”)
Compliance-Based Theory
70
perception of a state’s willingness to accept short term costs in order to protect long
term relationships and trust. When compliance with international law would impose
extreme losses on a country, violation of that law may not have much impact on
reputation. Such a violation sheds little light on the willingness of a state to violate
agreements when the costs of compliance are smaller.
These implications are significant for the study of international law. Most
obviously, the theory predicts that international law will have the smallest impact in
those areas of greatest importance to countries. This observation suggests that many of
the most central topics in traditional international law scholarship are the most resistant
to influence. Thus, for example, the laws of war, territorial limits (including territorial
seas), neutrality, arms agreements, and military alliances are among the areas least likely
to be affected by international law. Although agreements with large stakes can be
stable, this will rarely be the result of the obligations imposed by international law.
Adherence to such agreements is more likely to be the result of a game in which
international law plays a small part, if any. The existence of an international legal
obligation may be consistent with the outcome, but it is unlikely to alter behavior.
The message for scholars is twofold. First, international law scholars may be
focusing their efforts in the wrong place. Rather than concentrating on those topics
that are of greatest importance to states, they may be better off to devote more attention
to those areas in which international law can yield the greatest benefits. The most
promising fields of study, therefore, are those in which reputational effects are likely to
affect behavior. Some international law scholars may be disheartened by this message.
After all, international law is an interesting subject in part because it concerns itself with
great questions of war, peace, alliances, human rights, and so on.208 To focus on more
mundane questions may be perceived as a diminution of the grandeur of the field of
study. On the other hand, there is also an optimistic side to this conclusion.
International law is often criticized for being irrelevant. By turning the attention of
scholars to areas in which international law matters most, the importance of the subject
can be demonstrated. Furthermore, those areas in which international law matters are
themselves of great importance. These include, for example, the entire range of
international economic issues, from trade to the international regulation of competition
law to environmental regulation. The livelihood and sometimes the lives of millions of
people depend on the effective resolution of international economic issues. Surely this
is a worthwhile subject for international law scholars.
This discussion is not intended to imply that international law scholars must or
should completely abandon the field when it comes to the sort of large stakes questions
that have occupied so much of the discipline in the past. They have a role to play in
208 See e.g., Steven Ratner, Does International Law Mater in Preventing Ethnic Conflict?, 32 N.Y.U.J.
Int'l L. & Pol. 591, 592 (“ The ability of international law to make a difference in ethnic disputes also
goes to the heart of contemporary debates about the pertinence of international law to state decision-
making.”)
Compliance-Based Theory
71
important international agreements because they are uniquely qualified to evaluate the
structure of the institutions that are relevant to those questions and the manner in
which agreements are struck. International law can be used to strengthen national
commitments, but its value depends on the context. Scholars must focus not only on
the legality of state actions, they must study the way in which international law can be
structured to improve compliance. For example, issues involving large stakes can
sometimes be influenced by international law, but this is most likely to be achieved
through an indirect use of international commitments. For example, an agreement not
to develop nuclear weapons is, by itself, unlikely to have much relevance. If it is
combined with obligations whose stakes are lower but that cumulatively achieve the
desired goal, success is more likely. For example, if it is possible to monitor compliance
through regular inspections, countries are less likely to violate their obligation.
Monitoring allows violations to be detected early, which both reduces the benefits of
violation – a nuclear weapons program that is detected early provides fewer benefits to
the violating state – and increases the costs – early detection might cause other
countries to withdraw their own promises, denying the violating country the benefit of
compliance by others. The point here is that when large stakes issues are studied, they
should be approached with compliance in the front of one’s mind, and scholars should
be searching for institutions and agreements that achieve the desired objectives through
a series of discrete, low stakes compliance decisions rather than through a single large
stake decision.
Second, there is also a message for critics of international law. Following the
lead of international law scholars, critics point to the failure of international law in areas
where it is unrealistic to expect success. The use of the easiest cases to criticize
international law, makes attacks on the subject unpersuasive. These attacks should be
aimed at those areas in which international law plays a larger role.
Although a discussion of all the ways in which international agreements can be
designed to improve compliance is beyond the scope of this Article, one example
provides a flavor of how international law scholars can improve the level of compliance
with such agreements. To the extent possible, international obligations should take the
form of many small, low cost, and observable steps toward compliance rather than a
single major obligation. This, combined with thorough monitoring and verification of
compliance, can make international promises more binding. A reliable verification
mechanism will bring violations to light early in the relationship, giving the counter-
party a justification for abandoning its own commitment, thereby undermining the
benefit of cheating. The reaction of a treaty partner need not, of course, rely on
international law but if detection takes place early, it will also impose a reputational cost
and perhaps a cost in the form of a direct sanction. These costs will result from the
violation of the law itself. Where a relatively minor violation is likely to be caught and
can hurt a country’s reputation and its future negotiations, international law can help to
prevent such minor violations. The presence of a monitoring mechanism helps
Compliance-Based Theory
72
countries to identify violations while they are still minor and while reputational costs
can serve to deter them.
VI. CONCLUSION
This Article seeks to achieve several goals. First, it lays out a theory of
international law and compliance in which national behavior is influenced by law. It
does so within the framework of a rational actor model in which states value a
reputation for compliance with international obligations. Along with the possibility of
direct sanctions, it is reputation that provides an incentive for states to comply with
their obligations. By developing and preserving a good reputation, states are able to
extract greater concessions for their promises in the future.
Because reputational sanctions are limited in their magnitude, the Article points
out that they will not always provide sufficient incentive for nations to comply with the
law. This observation explains why one sees violations of international law in some
instances. It also suggests that scholars of international law should keep the limits of the
law in mind. In particular, when individual states decisions are made regarding issues of
fundamental importance to the state, it is unlikely that international law can influence
behavior with any frequency. Where individual decisions are of more modest impact
however – a situation that arises frequently in, for example, the world of international
economic and regulatory cooperation – international law may be able to alter outcomes
more frequently.
The Article also offers a new definition of customary international law. The
theoretical problems with CIL stem from the commitment of legal scholars to the
traditional definition that emphasizes jus cogens and opinio juris. A more useful
definition turns on the extent to which other states believe that a country has a legal
obligation and the extent to which that country’s reputation is harmed by a failure to
honor that obligation.
Taken seriously, a reputational model of compliance leads to important changes
in the way we view international law. It forces us to reject the classical definition of
international law, which considers only treaties and CIL to be “law.” Instead, it leads us
to a more functional definition, in which any international obligation that has a
substantial influence on national incentives is consider to be law. It also forces us to
recognize in an explicit way that not all international law is created equal. Some
obligations are more binding than others, and states choose the level of commitment
against this background fact. We can no longer be satisfied with the conclusion that
“treaties are to be obeyed.”209 Instead, we must consider international obligations in a
more contextual fashion in order to evaluate their impact.
209 See supra TAN 26.
Compliance-Based Theory
73
Above all, the theory advanced in this Article offers a more realistic model of
international law -- one in which both instances of compliance and instances of
violation can be understood, in which the full spectrum of agreements negotiated by
states is explained and in which the role of international law can be understood within a
model of self-interested states.
FIGURE III (10R, 10R)
Comply
Ignore
(2+4R, 4+4R)
Comply
State 1 Ignore Comply (4+4R, 2+4R)
(good)
Ignore
(4R, 4R)
State 2
Obligation (bad) Comply (5R, 5R)
Comply
Ignore
(3R-1, 3+3R)
Ignore Comply
(3+3R, 3R-1)
Ignore
No (3R, 3R)
Obligation
Comply (10R, 10R)
State 1 Comply Ignore (6R, 8R)
(good)
Comply (8R, 6R)
Ignore
State 2 Ignore
(bad) (4R, 4R)
Comply Comply (5R, 5R)
Ignore
Ignore (2R, 6R)
Comply
(6R, 2R)
Ignore
(3R, 3R)