School of Law
Law and Economics Research Paper No. 04
SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
Frank Partnoy
This paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection:
http://papers.ssrn.com/paper.taf?abstract_id=244558
10/9/00 DRAFT
SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
FRANK PARTNOY*
I. INTRODUCTION
II. THE LIMITS TO COMMON LAW
A. The Case for Common Law
1. Evolution and Efficiency
2. The Supply of Legal Rules
B. The Case Against Common Law
1. Devolution and Inefficiency
2. The Shrinking Supply of Legal Rules
III. ALTERNATIVES TO COMMON LAW
A. The Viability of Statutory Law
B. Private Law
C. Opting Out through Private Adjudication
IV. A PROPOSAL: SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
V. USING SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW IN DERIVATIVES DISPUTES
A. Line-Drawing in the Derivatives Market
B. A Critique of the Four Approaches
1. Piecemeal Regulation of Derivatives by Statute
2. Judicial Treatment of Derivatives Disputes
3. The Limited Applicability of Private Law
4. Some Attempts at Arbitration
C. How Synthetic Common Law Could Govern Disputes
D. Institutional Barriers to Synthetic Common Law
VI. CONCLUSION
I. INTRODUCTION
In modern society, most everything is, or can be, synthetic: food,
clothing, shelter, even thought.1 Yet law continues to be real.2 Real
* Associate Professor, University of San Diego School of Law. J.D., Yale Law
School, 1992. Larry Alexander, Kevin Cole, Mitu Gulati, Peter Huang, Shaun Martin,
Dennis Patterson, Sai Prakash, Dan Rodriguez, Emily Sherwin, Tom Smith, Ed Ursin,
and Mary Jo Wiggins provided helpful advice on an earlier draft. I am grateful to the
University of San Diego School of Law for financial support.
1 As to thought, some scholars have attempted to use findings in the field of
artificial intelligence to explain law and legal reasoning. See, e.g, Dan Hunter, Out of
Their Minds: Legal Theory in Neural Networks, 7 ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE & L. 129
(1999) (examining the use of neural networks in modeling legal reasoning).
2 Commentators previously have suggested some replacements for law in
particular areas, but those suggestions have involved either (1) replacing current
public statutes and cases with new public law, see MELVIN A. EISENBERG, THE NATURE
OF THE COMMON LAW 78 (1988); or (2) replacing current public statutes and cases
with new private law in the form of private statutes (i.e., contractual provisions), see
Part III.B. infra. However, no commentator has suggested replacing public statutes
and cases with new private law in the form of synthetic cases (i.e., synthetic common
law). For an excellent review of Professor Eisenberg’s book, see Stephen M.
Bainbridge, Social Propositions and Common Law Adjudication: The Nature of the
Common Law by Melvin A. Eisenberg, 1990 U. ILL. L. REV. 231 (1990).
2 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
parties dispute real cases. Real judges apply real law. Is there a need
for synthetic law?
This article maintains that there is. I advocate a system of
synthetic common law for use primarily in private dispute resolution.
In this system, private synthetic law associations will publish menus
of cases and commit to resolve disputes based on those cases. Private
parties will select from among these competing associations a
particular menu of cases to govern their contracts. The selected
association will adjudicate any disputes based on those cases. Courts
will have limited review of association judgments.
This system will fill a sizeable gap in current law, both in theory
and in practice. In terms of theory, synthetic common law is an
attractive alternative to common law, statutory law, private law, and
private adjudication. Because synthetic common law would be based
on ex ante findings by the parties, it more likely would reflect societal
practice and the parties’ expectations than does common law, which
is based on ex post findings by a judge or jury. Because synthetic
common law would be based on broadly ranging menus of cases, it
would avoid the inflexibility of statute-based regimes.3 Because
synthetic common law would rely on analogical reasoning by private
judges based on cases specified ex ante, it would avoid certain
intractable problems associated with private contract provisions,
including the difficulty of specifying contingencies of rapidly evolving
practices.4 Because synthetic common law would be administered
privately it would generate the benefits of existing private dispute
resolution regimes; moreover, because synthetic common law would
provide to parties a list of cases to govern any dispute, it would avoid
the uncertainty and secrecy associated with private arbitration.
In terms of practice, synthetic common law would enable private
parties to avoid the pitfalls of federal and state legislation, while also
avoiding the ambiguity and uncertainty of modern alternative dispute
resolution. In many instances, it would be cheaper, clearer, and fairer
than current alternatives. The advantages would be especially great
for private parties in areas of rapidly evolving technologies, where
3 To the extent common law regimes generate greater economic benefits than
civil or statutory law regimes, as several recent studies have suggested, synthetic
common law should achieve those benefits, too. For example, studies by Raphael
LaPorta, Florencio Lopez-de-Silanes, Andrei Shleifer, and Robert Vishny of the legal
rules protecting shareholders and creditors in forty-nine countries conclude that
common law governance rules tend to protect investors more than civil law rules.
See Raphael La Porta, et al., Law and Finance, 106 J. POL. ECON. 1113, 1151 (1998);
see also Andrei Shleifer & Robert Vishny, A Survey of Corporate Governance, 52 J.
FIN. 737 (1997); Raphael La Porta, et al., Legal Determinants of External Finance, 52
J. FIN. 1131 (1997). For a criticism of the methodology of these studies, see Frank
Partnoy, Why Markets Crash and What Law Can Do About It, 61 U. PITT. L. REV. #
(forthcoming 2000).
4 Moreover, because private contractual provisions often are written in
impenetrable boilerplate, it is far more likely that private parties will actually read
and consider provisions articulated in narrative case format. Human beings often
find it much more efficient to process information presented in narrative form. By
presenting legal rules as narrative, a synthetic common law regime may level the
playing field between parties facing information or sophistication asymmetry.
Disadvantaged parties often do not read the relevant contractual provisions, but
might read a provision articulated in narrative, case format. See, e.g, Melvin
Eisenberg, Text Anxiety, 59 S. CAL. L. REV. 305 (1986) (discussing argument that it is
reasonable for consumers to refuse to read dense form contracts).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
3
the choice between ever-expanding federal legislation or unpredictable
private arbitration is increasingly unattractive.
In one area in particular – disputes involving complex financial
instruments – synthetic common law could solve a seemingly
intractable problem for private parties. The $100 trillion market for
financial derivatives5 is subject to piecemeal regulation by statute, or
none at all, and the development of common law in this area has been
slow and sporadic. Private contracting, while extensive, has failed to
ameliorate these problems.6 Private parties to such transactions who
end up in disputes face either costly and inefficient statutory law,7
highly uncertain common law,8 or even less certain arbitration.9
Thus, the derivatives markets are plagued by uncertainty. The
costs to the market are substantial, and market participants are
desperate for reform.10 A synthetic common law system would
ameliorate this uncertainty by providing clarity regarding future
disputes immediately while avoiding the high costs associated with
heavy-handed regulation.
More generally, synthetic common law is an alternative regime to
consider for legal scholars writing in the area of institutional
competence and public choice. A public choice analysis need not
compare only a legislature captured by special interests to a sluggish
and ill-equipped judiciary.11 In certain areas of practice, synthetic
common law might be a reasonable middle road.
To the extent a system of synthetic common law is successful in
the derivatives markets, it could be adapted to other areas, especially
those with rapidly evolving technologies. The model system
proposed here for financial derivatives could apply equally well to
private parties contracting in telecommunications, intellectual
5 Derivatives are financial instruments such as options and forward contracts
whose value is derived from some underlying instrument or index. For a detailed
description of the classes and uses of derivatives, see Frank Partnoy, Financial
Derivatives and the Costs of Regulatory Arbitrage, 22 J. CORP. L. 211, 216-26
(1997). Derivatives may be traded on an exchange or over-the-counter (OTC) in
private transactions. The Bank for International Settlements (BIS) has estimated that
the size of the OTC derivatives market in notional amounts as of year-end 1999 was
approximately $88.2 trillion. See BANK FOR INTERNATIONAL SETTLEMENTS, THE
GLOBAL OTC DERIVATIVES MARKET AT END-DECEMBER 1999 3 (May 18, 2000)
<http://www.bis.org>. Interestingly, the gross market values of these contracts has
declined dramatically from 4.02 percent of the notional amounts at year-end 1998 to
3.19 percent of the notional amounts at year-end 1999, a decline of more than 20
percent. See id. This decline in market value may be a sign of very large losses in
the industry during 1999, a fact which is very difficult to ascertain. Trading in OTC
derivatives is highly concentrated, with the world’s ten largest banks accounting for
almost 90 percent of OTC derivatives activity worldwide. See ALFRED STEINHERR,
DERIVATIVES: THE WILD BEAST OF FINANCE 155 (2000). The BIS also has estimated
that the OTC derivatives market comprises approximately 86% of the overall
derivatives market. See id. at 152-53. Estimates of the size in notional amount of
the exchange-traded derivatives market are in the $13 to 14 trillion range. See id. at
152. Hence, the total size in notional amount of the derivatives industry is greater
than $100 trillion.
6 See infra Part V.B.3.
7 See infra Part V.B.1.
8 See infra Part V.B.2.
9 See infra Part V.B.4.
10 See infra Part V.A.
11 See, e.g., Ed Rubin, Law and Legislation in the Administrative State, 89
COLUM. L. REV. 369 (1989) (advancing a theory of legislation independent from
judicial interpretation of legislative provisions).
4 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
property, computer law, the Internet, and perhaps commercial or
corporate law.12
Part II critiques and updates the arguments for and against a
common law system. Part III analyzes three alternatives to a
common law system: statutory law, model acts and private law,13 and
private adjudication. Part IV discusses the proposal for synthetic
common law and compares it to the alternatives. Part V considers
how common law and its alternatives have failed in the area of
financial derivatives dispute resolution, and explains the potential
advantages of a synthetic common law regime in resolving such
disputes, and suggest how a synthetic common law regime might be
implemented.
II. THE LIMITS TO COMMON LAW
Oliver Wendell Holmes, one of the great advocates for the
common law,14 also recognized its limitations. Holmes told the story
of a Vermont justice of the peace who, after considering a suit brought
by one farmer against another for breaking a churn, ruled for the
defendant because he had looked through the statutes and could not
find anything about churns.15
The story illustrates some of the limits to common law
adjudication.16 Common law depends on human, and therefore
12 There may also be applications to criminal law. In the sentencing guidelines
context, Albert Alschuler has proposed using fake, paradigmatic cases, not unlike
synthetic common law, to guide judges in sentencing criminal defendants. See
Albert W. Alschuler, The Failure of Sentencing Guidelines: A Plea for Less
Aggregation, 58 U. CHI. L. REV. 901 (1991) (noting as the advantages of such a
system that “[n]o real-world case might fit any of the commission’s paradigms
exactly, and unusual cases might be far removed from any situation that the
commission had considered. But lawyers could use the commission’s paradigms at
sentencing hearings in much the same way that they now use judicial precedents at
other proceedings.”). However, Alschuler’s proposal – unlike synthetic common law
– would require both the involvement of federal judges and close judicial appellate
review. Moreover, because the entity creating the common law would be a regulatory
monopoly, the U.S. Sentencing Commission, there would be no assurance that the
“paradigmatic cases” would reflect societal practice. Of course, criminal sentencing
might not be an appropriate area to introduce competing providers of law, whether
synthetic or not. See infra notes 35-41 (assessing the regulatory competition
debate). I am grateful to Kevin Cole for bringing Alschuler’s proposal to my
attention.
13 Examples include the Uniform Commercial Code, the Model Penal Code, and
the various Restatements of Laws. See Steven Walt, Novelty and the Risks of Uniform
Sales Law, 39 VA. J. INT’L L. 671 (1999).
14 See generally OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES, THE COMMON LAW (1881).
15 See Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 474-
75 (1897). Holmes may have adapted this story from a passage in a letter to him
from Sir Frederick Pollock. In that letter, the first of a series of correspondence
between Holmes and Pollock from 1874 to 1932, Pollock described a “gem from
Viner’s Abridgment somewhere in title Pleader, which may be useful to you [and] is
not generally known. . . . A declaration in trover for bottles without naming how
many bottles is ill: but a declaration for twelve pair of boots and spurs without
naming how many spurs is well enough: for it shall be intended of the spurs that
belong to the boots.” MARK DEWOLFE HOWE, ED., I HOLMES-POLLOCK LETTERS: THE
CORRESPONDENCE OF MR. JUSTICE HOLMES AND SIR FREDERICK POLLOCK 1874-1932 5
(1942) (letter from Pollock to Holmes, dated July 3, 1874).
16 Melvin Eisenberg has made a similar point about the almost numberless rule
permutations that are possible based on fact differences in common law cases. For
example, he has noted that the “vehicle” of harm in a well-known British case in
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
5
fallible, judges. A common law judge might adhere stubbornly to the
view that if a statute (or perhaps a prior case) does not strictly cover
the terms of a transaction, then an injured party to that transaction
has no claim. Common law rules are fraught with contradictions and
ambiguity, and, because they depend upon a limited number of specific
cases, necessarily contain gaps.17
There has been vigorous academic debate about the merits and
flaws of common law. This Part critiques and updates some of the
most persuasive arguments for and against common law adjudication.
In some sense, this Part seeks to understand whether we should laugh
or cry in response to Holmes’s story. Is the story funny because of
its implausibility, the assumption being that the common law is fair
and efficient? Or is the story upsetting because it seems all too
plausible, the implication being that the common law is neither fair
nor efficient?
A. The Case for Common Law
In the modern regulatory state, dominated by federal statutes and
administrative rules, it is easy enough to relegate the common law to
the role of historical nicety. From the thirteenth century until
recently common law was the primary source of law in the United
States and England, and was revered by scholars and practitioners.18
In modern society, it assumes a lesser role. Notwithstanding the fact
that much of law school still involves the study of common law
topics, many legal commentators, scholars, and practitioners have
abandoned the common law in favor of statutes, including model
statutes, and private law, including model and uniform laws.19 In a
few areas of rapidly evolving technology, common law is
experiencing a renaissance, with some scholars advocating common
law adjudication as a higher-speed alternative to the often-sluggish
modern administrative state.20
Judge Learned Hand, drawing from Blackstone,21 described the
common law as “a monument slowly raised, like a coral reef, from the
which the plaintiff drank from a bottle containing a decomposed snail “could be
characterized as a opaque bottle of ginger beer, an opaque bottle of beverage, a bottle
of beverage, a container of chattels for human consumption, a chattel, or a thing.”
EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 54 (citing M’Alister (or Donoghue) v. Stevenson, [1932]
L.R. App. Cas. 562 (H.L. 1932)).
17 In his defense of common law regimes, Melvin Eisenberg has stated that an
application and extension of common law is justified when it is both socially
congruent and systemically consistent. See EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 68. These
justifications, to the extent one believes they are important, place additional
limitations on the power of common law.
18 Numerous commentators have described the history of common law
adjudication, a topic that is well beyond the scope of this article. See, e.g., I WILLIAM
HOLDSWORTH, A HISTORY OF ENGLISH LAW 194-350 (7th ed. 1956) (describing the early
system of common law jurisdiction).
19 See infra Part II.B. Moreover, self-interested judges, lawyers, and
commentators too often have supported the common law with assumptions and faith
more than argument or analysis, making it even easier for opponents to reject
arguments in favor of common law adjudication. Of course, the primary beneficiaries
of a common law-dominated legal system are lawyers and judges, so it is no surprise
that both groups historically supported the regime.
20 See infra notes 57-62 and accompanying text.
21 Blackstone stressed that the adherence to common law notions of stare
decisis required that courts adhere to precedent and make changes slowly over time:
“For it is an established rule to abide by former precedents, where the same points
6 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
minute accretions of past individuals, of whom each built upon the
relics which his predecessors left, and in his turn left a foundation
upon which his successors might work.”22 This romanticized notion
of the common law as coral reef is (or was, until recently) deeply
embedded in the psyche of lawyers and legal academics. The language
is loaded: Learned Hand’s metaphor of the coral reef implicitly
praises the role of judges in developing a “monument” (i.e., common
law) through an incremental, gradual, and fair process.
Why such lofty praise? As the argument goes, there are two chief
advantages to the common law. First, it provides a mechanism for
resolving disputes in a fair and efficient manner. Second, it generates
a supply of incremental and consistent legal rules that reflect social
practice.
1. Evolution and Efficiency
First, the superiority of a common law approach is rooted in the
notion that courts resolve disputes in a fair and efficient manner by
reasoning from existing standards, either of society generally or of
the legal system specifically.23 This function – dispute resolution –
depends on current and past practice. Disputes typically derive from
a claim of right by an individual or institution based on the
application, meaning, or implications of a particular society’s existing
standards.24
The process of common law dispute resolution is both
decentralized and passive. A decentralized approach ensures that
judges will hear disputes involving a large swath of experience in
society; common law rules then should reflect differences in standards
among various segments within society. Just as importantly, courts
play a largely passive role, responding only when parties set in
motion a particular legal dispute.
Ideally, a society’s method of dispute resolution should be
efficient and fair. Commentators have argued that the decentralized,
passive common law is both. The efficiency argument has an
evolutionary flair. In its most basic terms, the argument is that the
common law is an efficient dispute resolution system simply because
it is the system that has survived the test of time.25 The English
come again in litigation: as well as to keep the scale of justice even and steady, and
not liable to waiver with every new judge’s opinion; and also because the law in that
case being solemnly declared and determined, what before was uncertain, and
perhaps indifferent, is now become a permanent rule which is not in the breast of any
subsequent judge to alter or vary from according to his private sentiments: he being
not delegated to pronounce a new law, but to maintain and expound the old one.” I
SIR WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES 68 (1775). The synthetic common law
proposal offered embraces Blackstone’s appreciation of the utility of common law,
but takes issue with his respect for its “permanent rule” status.
22 Learned Hand, Judge Cardozo’s The Nature of the Judicial Process, 35 HARV.
L. REV. 479, 479 (1922).
23 See GORDON TULLOCK, THE CASE AGAINST THE COMMON LAW 2-3 (1997).
24 See id. at 1.
25 There may be a gap, of course, between the fact of evolution and the argument
that evolution is efficient. In evolutionary biology, for example, there is strong
evidence of evolutionary patterns that belie “survival of the fittest” arguments. The
fact that a particular practice survives during a periodic of selection and variation
does not necessarily mean it is the optimal current practice. For a discussion of
evolution as applied to legal theory, see Jody S. Kraus, Legal Design and the
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
7
common law system survived despite repeated threats, powerful
criticism, and almost insurmountable obstacles, including – some argue
– the emergence of Parliament as a power in the eighteenth
century.26 As the argument goes, if common law adjudication had not
been an efficient means of resolving disputes, given the state of
English society at the time, it likely would not have persisted over
time.
Moreover, the fact that common law rules survived while
legislatures were empowered to enact different rules is especially
strong evidence that a well-functioning27 democratic society could do
not better than those common law rules. Just as the common law was
threatened in England,28 the expansive reach of Congress has
threatened U.S. common law for many decades. Again, the argument
goes, if the common law were not an efficient system, elected
representatives would have substituted more efficient rules.29
In the 1970s, Judge Richard Posner and others attempted to
buttress the intuitive appeal of the argument for common law with
economic analysis. Their arguments also have an evolutionary
perspective. In general, the economic argument, first advanced by
Posner and William Landes, is that to the extent common law
adjudication involves private parties acting in their own self-interest
and judges deciding cases based on wealth-maximizing standards, only
efficient rules will survive.30 Accordingly, the common law is wealth
maximizing. Judges leave inefficient rules to the side, and over time
preserve and follow only efficient rules.
Other scholars then attempted to explain how the structure of
common law adjudication reinforces this efficiency-seeking process.
For example, George Priest argued that the process of litigation, and
how parties choose whether and when to litigate, pushes common law
Evolution of Commercial Norms, 26 J. LEGAL STUD. 377, 382 n.9 (1997) (citing
several articles).
26 See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 5-6; ARTHUR R. HOGUE, ORIGINS OF THE
COMMON LAW 241 (1986). Tullock has argued that the common law was threatened
several times during the Middle Ages, when the common law survived more in the
memories of individual judges and practitioners as oral histories than in formal
records. See, e.g., TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 8 (noting that the law was largely
judge-made and unwritten, although some “common law court decisions were
recorded, and occasionally the record would be consulted”).
27 This argument assumes the democracy is well-functioning one, an
assumption that may or may not be true.
28 See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 6 (quoting Justice William Blackstone as
saying in 1783 that the competence of Parliament was so great that Blackstone knew
“of no power in the ordinary forms of the constitution that is vested with authority
to control it”).
29 This argument ignores the fact that high transaction costs, especially the
collective action costs that dominate democratic voting, may prevent the legislature
from effectively amending poor common law rules, although there is evidence that at
least on occasion Congress can act to overturn or “amend” judicial decisions,
notwithstanding these transaction costs. See, e.g. 18 U.S.C. § 1346 (amending
definition of “property” in the mail fraud statute to include intangible rights, after
the Supreme Court held that such rights were not included); see generally MANCUR
OLSON, THE LOGIC OF COLLECTIVE ACTION: PUBLIC GOODS AND THE THEORY OF GROUPS
(1965).
30 See William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, Adjudication as a Private Good,
8 J. LEGAL STUD. 235 (1979).
8 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
rules in the direction of efficiency.31 Inefficient legal rules are
litigated more frequently, so judges can dedicate their efforts to
establishing efficient rules, which then lead parties to settle cases out
of court. Along different lines, but still advocating for the common
law, Guido Calabresi was one of the first scholars to use economic
analysis to demonstrate some of the disadvantages of a primarily
statutory regime in the U.S. as compared to a regime allowing
common law judicial “amendment” of statutes through
interpretation.32 These economic arguments added an element of
science and logic to the claim that the common law provides the best
method of dispute resolution.
The economic arguments supporting the common law can be
updated in the context of the ongoing debate about regulatory
competition.33 This debate considers the question of whether a single
monopolist regulator (e.g., the federal government) is superior or
inferior to a group of competing regulators (e.g., the state
governments). This argument, too, is evolutionary in tone: is the
regulatory system that survives over time superior, or is the surviving
system simply a result of a path-dependent movement from a set of
somewhat arbitrary initial conditions?34 The contours of the debate
vary, from corporate law35 to securities law36 to environmental
regulation.37
31 See George L. Priest, The Common Law Process and the Selection of Efficient
Rules, 6 J. LEGAL STUD. 65 (1977) (supporting efficiency conclusion with the
argument that inefficient rules are more likely to be litigated, and then changed). But
see Robert Cooter & Lewis Kornhauser, Can Litigation Improve the Law without the
Help of Judges?, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 139 (1980) (arguing efficiency conclusion
requires very strong assumptions); Gillian K. Hadfield, Bias in the Evolution of
Legal Rules, 80 GEO. L.J. 583 (1992) (arguing efficiency conclusion holds only on
average and cases are not a random sample); Eric Talley, Precedential Cascades: An
Appraisal, 73 S. CAL. L. REV. 87 (1999) (describing precedent in terms of rational
herding).
32 See GUIDO CALABRESI, A COMMON LAW FOR THE AGE OF STATUTES (1982).
Calabresi was prescient in arguing that such amendment was required, in part
because of barriers to formal legislative amendment, including interest-group
pressures; federal statutes in particular have multiplied many-fold in recent decades,
without much, if any, improvement in the clarity of legal rules. See, e.g., Stephen D.
Clymer, Unequal Justice: The Federalization of Criminal Law, 70 S. CAL. L. REV.
643 (1997) (describing recent expansion of federal criminal law).
33 See generally William W. Bratton & Joseph A. McCahery, Regulatory
Competition, Regulatory Capture, and Corporate Self-Regulation, 73 N.C. L. Rev.
1861 (1995); James D. Cox, Regulatory Duopoly in U.S. Securities Markets, 99
COLUM. L. REV. 1200 (1999).
34 See, e.g., Bernard Black & Reinier Kraakman, A Self-Enforcing Model of
Corporate Law, 109 HARV. L. REV. 1911, 1974-77 (1996) (suggesting path-
dependent evolution of corporate law); Ehud Kamar, A Regulatory Competition
Theory of Indeterminacy in Corporate Law, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 1908, 1927-28 (1998)
(suggesting that corporate law has developed based on vague, open-ended
standards); Lucian Arye Bebchuk & Mark Roe, A Theory of Path Dependence in
Corporate Ownership and Governance, 52 STAN. L. REV. 127 (1999) (extending path
dependence argument).
35 See, e.g., Roberta Romano, Empowering Investors: A Market Approach to
Securities Regulation, 107 YALE L.J. 2359, 2384 n.76 (1998) (offering race-to-the-
top interpretation); Ralph K. Winter, Jr., State Law, Shareholder Protection, and the
Theory of the Corporation, 6 J. LEGAL STUD. 251, 262-92 (1977) (same); James D.
Cox, Choice of Law Rules for International Securities, 66 U. CIN. L. REV. 1179
(1998) (discussing problems associated with privatizing securities regulation);
Lucian Arye Bebchuk, Federalism and the Corporation: The Desirable Limits on
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
9
The common law is a good candidate for the regulatory
competition debate because it originally depended on extensive
competition among courts and judges.38 For example, just as many
scholars argue that the competition among states for corporate
charters is a race-to-the-top, driving the development of (Delaware)
corporate law,39 one can argue that competition among courts and
judges generally was a race-to-the-top,40 driving the development of
English, and later American, common law. Over time, so the
argument goes, the system that survived is superior.41 If it had not
been superior, private parties would have opted to have their disputes
governed by another regime; alternatively, rational and well-informed
judges would have responded with different decisions. The viability of
this argument depends on empirical research, which has not yet been
done in the common law context.
For some scholars, it is enough to establish that the common law
is an efficient42 method of dispute resolution. Yet there remains the
State Competition in Corporate Law, 105 HARV. L. REV. 1435, 1448-50 (1992)
(offering race-to-the-bottom interpretation).
36 See, e.g, Roberta Romano, supra note 35 (arguing for regulatory competition
among state securities law regimes within the U.S.); Stephen J. Choi & Andrew T.
Guzman, Portable Reciprocity: Rethinking the International Reach of Securities
Regulation, 71 S. CAL. L. REV. 903 (1998) (arguing for regulatory competition
among national securities law regimes); Partnoy, Why Markets Crash, supra note 3,
at # (criticizing and suggesting amendments to proposals for competition among
international securities law regimes).
37 See, e.g., Richard L. Revesz, Rehabilitating Interstate Competition:
Rethinking the "Race-to-the-Bottom" Rationale for Federal Environmental
Regulation, 67 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 1210 (1992) (describing race-to-the-bottom versus
race-to-the-top arguments in the context of environmental regulation).
38 Randy Barnett has written about the evolution of common law from the
competitive law merchant: “Many of [common law’s] principles originated with the
competitive law merchant that preceded the growth of the common law. Many more
were determined in an era when common-law courts competed for legal business with
other legal systems and therefore had a far greater incentive than today to be
sensitive to the expectations of both parties. With this as its origin, I suggest that
the correspondence between common sense and common law is no coincidence.” See
Randy E. Barnett, The Sound of Silence: Default Rules and Contractual Consent, 78
VA. L. REV. 821, 910-11 (1992).
39 The argument in corporate law is that corporations choose to incorporate in
Delaware to benefit from that state’s value-enhancing corporate law rules. See, e.g.,
Romano, supra note 35, at 2384 n.76 (substantiating this claim with event studies).
40 There is a question about whether common law competition was a race to the
top or a race to the bottom. But it certainly was a race. See, e.g., Tom W. Bell, Public
Choice and Public Law: The Common Law in Cyberspace, 97 MICH. L. REV. 1746,
1769-70 (1999) (describing efficiency arguments). The specialized courts of the law
merchant often are cited as the predecessors to common law rules. See I. Trotter
Hardy, The Proper Legal Regime for “Cyberspace,” 55 U. PITT. L. REV. 993, 1019-21
(1994); David R. Johnson & David Post, Law and Borders – The Rise of Law in
Cyberspace, 48 STAN. L. REV. 1367, 1387-91 (1996); see also Lisa Bernstein,
Merchant Law in a Merchant Court: Rethinking the Code’s Search for Immanent
Business Norms, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 1765 (1996). The law merchant courts evolved
during the eleventh and twelfth centuries, when clients paid fees to courts. See
BRUCE L. BENSON, THE ENTERPRISE OF LAW 60-62 (1990).
41 An alternative view is that the competition in common law was a race-to-the-
bottom, i.e., has led to an inefficient and unfair regime. See infra Part II.B.1.
42 In the debate about common law, it frequently is unclear whether scholars are
arguing that common law is efficient in a Pareto sense (i.e., that no party can be made
better off without making another party worse off) or in a Kaldor-Hicks sense (i.e.,
that no party can be made better off by an amount greater than the amount other
parties are made worse off). In an environment of high transaction costs, the
10 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
additional question of fairness. To some extent, the above
evolutionary arguments support the notion that the common law is
fair. In a world with perfect information and zero transaction costs,
rational, fully-informed judges would resolve disputes in a manner that
both maximized not only the welfare of the parties to the dispute, but
that of society as a whole. If they did not, the argument goes, parties
in future disputes (or affected non-parties) would point out the ill
effects of a particular decision, and a rational, fully-informed judge
would alter the applicable common law legal rule. If some judges were
irrational or ill informed, parties would find other, better judges.43
Notwithstanding these weaknesses, there are strong arguments
that the common law is a fair method of dispute resolution because it
protects parties’ expectations. The credibility of common law
adjudication is based on the notion of replicability, i.e., that courts
employ consistent methodologies across cases.44 Numerous scholars
and commentators have focused on the preservation of expectations
through replicable decision-making as justifying the fairness of
common law. Melvin Eisenberg has noted that disputes in the U.S.
during the nineteenth century often relied on usages, and therefore by
definition depended on the behavior and expectations of private
parties.45 Justice Cardozo believed in the general rule of following
precedent to ensure that private parties’ rights and beliefs would be
protected in an evenhanded, consistent, and fair manner.46 Jeremy
Bentham – an opponent of common law generally – advocated a
predictable judicial framework to protect parties’ expectations, saying
that “[t]he business of the Judge is to keep the distribution of
valuables and of rewards and punishments in the course of
expectation.”47 Holmes, in his story about the judge in the churn
redistribution scenarios underlying the normative force of Kaldor-Hicks efficiency
may not occur.
43 The weaknesses of this argument are addressed in detail in Part II.B. For now,
it is sufficient to note that judges might be irrational and typically do not have
perfect information. See discussion infra at Part V.B. Moreover, private parties may
face transaction costs or other insurmountable obstacles in finding better judges.
44 See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 3.
45 See EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 38 (describing courts adopting miners’
usages as rules of law in mining claims, and whalers’ usages as rules of law in
disputes of the property rights of harpooned whales).
46 See Mark D. Hinderks & Steve A. Leben, Restoring the Common in the Law: A
Proposal for the Elimination of Rules Prohibiting the Citation of Unpublished
Decisions in Kansas and the Tenth Circuit, 31 WASHBURN L.J. 155, 171 n.96 (1992).
47 “The deference is that due to the determination of former judgments is due
not to their wisdom, but to their authority: not in compliment to dead men’s vanity,
but in concern for the welfare of the living. That men may be enabled to predict the
legal consequences of an act before they do it: that public expectation may know
what course it has to take: that he who has property may trust to have it still: that he
who meditates guilty may look for punishment, and in the self same guilty for the
same punishment. . . . Why should decisions be uniform? Why should succeeding
ones be such as to appear the natural and expected consequences of those preceding
them? Not because it ought to have been established, but because it is established. . .
. The business of the Judge is to keep the distribution of valuables and of rewards
and punishments in the course of expectation: conformable to what the expectation
of men concerning them is, or if apprised of the circumstances of each case, as he is,
he supposes would be.” Jeremy Bentham, A Comment on the Commentaries, in A
COMMENT ON THE COMMENTARIES AND A FRAGMENT ON GOVERNMENT 196-97 (J.H. Burns
& H.L.A. Hart eds., 1977).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
11
case,48 hinted that the result is apocryphal: any judge would resolve a
dispute about a damaged churn in a sensible way, in line with the
parties’ expectations.
Finally, recent empirical work in psychology supports a
conclusion that there are non-economic reasons to believe common
law adjudication is fair to the parties involved. Common law
adjudication gives parties the thing they seem to desire most: their
day in court. Recent studies in the psychology literature suggest that
disputants believe having a chance to describe their version of the
story to an impartial adjudicator is the most important factor
determining whether they perceive a particular process of dispute
resolution as “fair.” In fact, this “day in court” factor outweighs
every other variable tested, including the actual outcome of the
dispute.49 If these studies are correct, to the extent the common law
is perceived as fair, it generates greater happiness among disputants
than would a system that did not give parties the opportunity to air
their views. 50
2. The Supply of Legal Rules
A common law approach provides a second, equally valuable,
function. Courts add to and enrich the supply of legal rules in a way
that reflects the values of society.51 Thus, a key advantage to a
common law approach is that judicial rules evolve slowly as a flexible
response to the actions and preferences of individuals and institutions
involved in disputes.52 As such rules evolve, those parties, as well as
other non-parties who learn of the rules, can live and plan
accordingly. Then, other individuals and institutions are involved in
the next round of cases, which generates the next set of legal rules,
and so forth, all reflecting the behavior and values of society.
Several scholars have concluded that the common law upholds the
rule of law more effectively than civil law because of its flexibility,
coupled with the “stickiness” of precedent.53 Implicit in this
argument is a distrust of the democratic process: the notion is that
judges with life tenure are able to resolve disputes in an impartial
manner, and therefore are better at generating legal rules than
48 See supra note 15 and accompanying text.
49 See, e.g., Tom R. Tyler, et al., The Two Psychologies of Conflict Resolution:
Differing Antecedents of Pre-Experience Choices and Post-Experience Evaluations,
2(2) GROUP PROCESSES AND INTERGROUP RELATIONS 99 (1999) (describing these
studies).
50 However, the fact that disputants believe common law adjudication is fair
does not necessarily dispose of the fairness question: disputants might irrationally
overweight the benefits of being heard in an apparently fair process; in reality, the
process might be unfair.
51 See id.
52 Some scholars have argued that the behavior of parties in those relatively few
cases that involve a published decision are not representative of the behavior of
other parties. I consider these arguments infra at Part II.B.1.
53 See, e.g., F.A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION AND LIBERTY, LAW, LEGISLATION AND
LIBERTY: A NEW STATEMENT OF THE LIBERAL PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE AND POLITICAL
ECONOMY (1983) (arguing that common law is preferable to civil law because
legislative rules are both less flexible in form and more susceptible to sudden
change); EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 6 (arguing that common law courts should play
the role of developing the rule of law on a case-by-case basis).
12 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
legislators, who may be captured by particular individuals or
institutions.54
Also implicit in this argument is the notion that common law
legal rules evolve over time to reflect the values and practices of
society in a more current and accurate manner than statutes can.
Common law is passive and evolves in response to changes in the
behavior of disputants. Common law rules are more adaptable than
codified rules.55 As society changes judges can quickly56 alter the
relevant legal rules. Statutes, in contrast, are fixed and difficult to
change. The legislature would find it too costly and burdensome to
make similar, quick changes to reflect changes in society. Legislation
often cannot anticipate future controversies, especially in rapidly
changing areas of practice. Legislation necessarily is active, and
action requires time and is subject to the political process.
On the other hand, because common law rules are “sticky,” judges
may not change them simply based on a whim. Change must be
incremental, requires careful analysis, and is subject to review. In
contrast, the legislature, when it is moved to act, may act
immediately and on its own, with only that analysis individual
politicians facing reelection think necessary, even if the legislative
action directly reverses prior law.
Interestingly, several legal scholars recently have argued that in
the area of rapidly evolving technologies – particularly involving
telecommunications and the Internet – common law is uniquely able
to generate timely rules to govern the actions of sophisticated
parties.57 Melvin Eisenberg has argued that courts, not legislatures,
have a unique capacity to generate the large body of legal rules a
technologically advanced society needs to do its business.58 Bruce
54 See EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 4-5.
55 See M. Stuart Madden, The Vital Common Law: Its Role in a Statutory Age, 18
U. ARK. LITTLE ROCK L.J. 555 (1996) (arguing that an advantage of the common law is
its adaptability).
56 Many court systems have implemented so-called “fast track” or “rocket
docket” approaches, to speed the resolution of individual cases. See Chris A. Carr &
Michael R. Jencks, The Privatization of Business and Commercial Dispute
Resolution: A Misguided Policy Decision, 88 KY. L.J. 183, 197 n.34 (2000) (citing
several articles describing such systems). Other courts, such as those in the
Southern District of New York, resolve cases more slowly, and instead spend more
time writing a smaller number of careful, often lengthy, opinions.
57 See PETER HUBER, LAW AND DISORDER IN CYBERSPACE: ABOLISH THE FCC AND
LET COMMON RULE THE TELECOSM 8, 206 (1997); Frank H. Easterbrook, Cyberspace
and the Law of the Horse, 1996 U. CHI. LEGAL F. 207, 216 (1996); Lawrence Lessig,
The Path of Cyberlaw, 104 YALE L.J. 1743, 1752 (1995). I explicitly consider
arguments about the viability of common law as compared to statutory or civil law
infra at Part III.A.
58 “Our society has an enormous demand for legal rules that actors can live,
plan, and settle by. The legislature cannot adequately satisfy this demand. The
capacity of a legislature to generate legal rules is limited, and much of that capacity
must be allocated to the production of rules concerning governmental matters, such
as spending, taxes, and administration, rules that are regarded as beyond the court’s
competence, such as the definition of crimes; and rules that are best administered by
a bureaucratic machinery, such as the principles for setting the rates charged by
regulated industries. Furthermore, our legislatures are normally not staffed in a
manner that would enable them to perform comprehensively the function of
establishing law to govern action in the private sector. Finally, in many areas the
flexible form of a judicial rule is preferable to the canonical form of a legislative
rule. Accordingly, it is socially desirable that the courts should act to enrich that
supply of legal rules that govern . . . [business] conduct – not by taking on
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
13
Keller has pointed to the emergence of common law in intellectual
property disputes, where a statutory regime, especially given a
sluggish Congress, is much too slow.59 Peter Huber has advocated for
common law rules in the telecommunications industry.60 Lawrence
Lessig has discussed the benefits of common law related to the
Internet.61 Judges and litigants recently have attempted to apply
common law to disputes in the financial derivatives industry, where a
statutory regime may be irrelevant at best.62 The arguments in favor
of a common law system may be strongest in those areas involving
rapid technological change, where the advantages of adaptability are
more important, and where parties would benefit from a quick supply
of relevant legal rules.
One final advantage to the common law’s ability to supply legal
rules is that by reporting decisions, courts generate a public record of
what otherwise would be only unwritten law, customs, and oral legal
traditions. Especially in the business context, certainty generated by
a written record is essential; common law provides certainty by
enabling parties to rely on reported judicial decisions.63
The reporting of decisions also ensures that changes in legal rules
will be gradual and will need to be explained by reference to flaws in or
departures from prior reported judicial reasoning.64 As publicly
reported decisions increase in number and quality, the credibility of
the common law system improves. A common law system with a
sufficient number of well reasoned, publicly reported decisions can
both provide parties with guidance in their daily lives and assure
participants in the system that individual disputes will be resolved with
appropriate attention and care.65
lawmaking as a free-standing function, but by attaching much greater emphasis to
the establishment of legal rules than would be necessary if the courts’ sole function
was the resolution of disputes.” EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 4-5.
59 “[T]he common law has emerged as a source of protection for intellectual
property rights throughout this century whenever statutory protection for new forms
of media were still evolving.” Bruce P. Keller, Condemned to Repeat the Past: The
Reemergence of Misappropriation and Other Common Law Theories of Protection
for Intellectual Property Rights, 11 HARV. J. L. & TECH. 401, 403 (1998).
60 See Huber, supra note 57.
61 See Lessig, supra note 57; see also LAWRENCE LESSIG, CODE: AND OTHER LAWS
OF CYBERSPACE 218-23 (1999) (noting problems with legislators and need for
judicial action in regulating the Internet).
62 See infra Part V.B.2.
63 Several scholars have noted that private parties interacting repeatedly in
small groups may find ways of enforcing social practices without reported common
law or published statutes. See, e.g., ROBERT C. ELLICKSON, ORDER WITHOUT LAW: HOW
NEIGHBORS SETTLE DISPUTES (1991) (describing such private enforcement regimes);
Catherine Mansell-Carstens, Popular Financial Culture in Mexico: The Case of the
Tanda in CHANGING STRUCTURE OF MEXICO: POLITICAL, SOCIAL, AND ECONOMIC
PROSPECTS 77 (Laura Randall ed., 1996) (describing the “tanda” or “rosco,” an
informal mechanism used by members of many small Mexican villages to allocate
credit). However, in many instances – and particularly for parties transacting in a
global business environment, where the possibility of informal resolution may be
difficult – parties will need a formalized, specified system of dispute resolution.
Even in markets where parties risk suffering reputational costs from breaches of the
parties’ expectations, those reputational costs alone – without the possibility of
enforcement through a more formal dispute resolution system – may not be
sufficient to deter such breaches.
64 See Hinderks & Leben, supra note 46, at 170.
65 To the extent the common law is thought to be incomplete or vague it is not
unlike many other valuable social institutions, practices, and systems of ideas that
14 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
By publicly reporting decisions, courts also broadcast norms to
society so that parties and lawyers can resolve the vast majority of
disputes without burdening judicial resources.66 To the extent a
society relies on the norms of self-regulating private communities
transacting with each other in repeated interactions, public decisions
can reinforce those norms, while making it clear that although most
transactions will not lead to a dispute, clear rules will apply to those
that do.67
B. The Case Against the Common Law
Many legal scholars dispute the view of the common law as
attractive, efficient coral reef.68 As to the efficiency of common
law, there are arguments pointing to severe cracks in the reef’s
foundation, which cannot support the weight of costly, complex
dispute resolution. The core of these arguments is the economic
notion that a common law system is a tragedy of the commons:
overuse is rampant, court resources are rationed, and outcomes are
inefficient.
As to the common law’s ability to generate legal rules, there is a
preliminary theoretical question as to whether there is any reef at all
(i.e., whether common law can even be said to exist),69 and a more
pragmatic question about the value of published common law decisions
in modern society. For various reasons – fewer opinions written;
more opinions depublished, selectively published, or vacated; more
decisions subject to confidentiality orders or under seal; and increased
use of private adjudication – the common law is disappearing from
public view, and often is no longer useful to parties planning their
lives and business affairs.
1. Devolution and Inefficiency
First is the argument that any common law system that could
survive in a democracy necessarily is inefficient. The argument goes
like this: judicial resources, including published decisions, are a public
are, at their core, more art than science. See Brian Simpson, The Common Law and
Legal Theory, in LEGAL THEORY AND COMMON LAW 17 (William Twining ed., 1986)
(“In the sense used here a theory or general view of the common law represents an
attempt to provide an answer to the question whether the common law can be said to
exist at all – and this has been seriously doubted – and, if so, in what sense.”); see
also infra Part II.B.2.
66 See Marc Galanter, Real World Torts: An Antidote to Anecdote, 55 MD. L. REV.
1093, 1101-02 (1996) (noting that such norms “influence not only the disputes that
are brought to the courts, but also matters that never reach the courts”); see also
Howard Slavitt, Selling the Integrity of the System of Precedent: Selective
Publication, Depublication, and Vacatur, 30 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 109, 140
(1995) (noting that legal certainty enables parties to act in ways that avoid costly
litigation).
67 See, e.g., Robert D. Cooter, Decentralized Law for a Complex Economy, 23 SW.
U. L. REV. 443, 445-46 (1994) (labeling such norms as the “new law merchant”). For
a detailed description of the law merchant, see I. Trotter Hardy, supra note 40, at
1019-21.
68 See, e.g., Richard A. Epstein, Law and Economics: Its Glorious Past and
Cloudy Future, 64 U. CHI. L. REV. 1167, 1169-70 (1997) (criticizing early insistence
“on the efficiency of the common law, even as the legal system was moving
inexorably in the opposite direction”); TULLOCK, supra note 23 (similar criticism).
69 Simpson, supra note 65, at 9.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
15
good70 with no assigned ownership rights. Accordingly, if the
government establishes courts but does not charge a user fee to cover
costs, it encourages overuse of judicial resources, and therefore
inefficiencies. The only way to prevent such inefficiencies is for the
government to charge a high enough user fee to cover all of its costs.
But in a society where disputes are costly to resolve, such a fee would
be very high and necessarily would disadvantage a large segment of
society, who would not approve it. Therefore, any possible common
law system is inefficient.
Consider the following thought experiment: residents of a newly
established state have no system of dispute resolution. These
residents decide to establish a “judicial park” staffed with judges at the
center of the city. Any party with a dispute may enter the judicial
park, where a judge will resolve the dispute and issue a well-reasoned
written opinion.
What problems does this state face? If entrance to the judicial
park is free, any party with a dispute will enter the park to utilize
judicial resources. Judicial resources will be overused and a tragedy of
the commons will result.71 All parties will demand well-reasoned
opinions, which are very expensive to provide. The externality
benefits to such opinions are unlikely to outweigh these costs, because
non-parties and judges cannot exercise discretion about which cases
merit thorough review. The result will be a large number of
potentially useless judicial opinions.
The state may find itself unable to generate sufficient revenue,
through taxes or otherwise, to support the judicial park. If the state is
able to support the park, it will do so with resources that might be
more highly valued in another use. Judicial resources will not be
optimally used and judges will not be able to produce an efficient body
of common law.
The state could prevent this overuse by charging fees to enter the
park. To the extent the fees are less than the total costs of dispute
resolution, judicial resources still will be overused, albeit less so (i.e., a
partial tragedy of the commons). If the fees charged are high,
perhaps even high enough to cover the total costs of dispute
resolution, judicial resources will be conserved, but the system will be
regressive, favoring wealthy individuals and institutions. Residents of
the state may find such a system politically unacceptable.
As the costs of resolving disputes in the state increase,72 there are
only a handful of possible results. One is that the efficiency of the
common law system decreases because judicial resources are more
overused. Another is that the system becomes more regressive as the
state passes along the higher cost of using judicial resources by
70 A public good is a commodity or service which does not exhibit either
“depletability” (i.e., if an additional user consumes a public good, the benefits of
that good are not depleted) or “excludability” (i.e., it is difficult or impossible to
exclude consumers from the benefits of a public good). See WILLIAM J. BAUMOL &
ALAN S. BLINDER, ECONOMICS: PRINCIPLES AND POLICY 543 (1985).
71 See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 16 (describing the inefficiencies of common
law as a “tragedy of the commons”).
72 The costs of dispute resolution could increase for several reasons: the
complexity of transactions increases, the number and/or severity of uncertain events
(e.g., accidents or natural disasters) increases, or residents of the state demand fairer
process. In the U.S., all of these costs have increased in recent years.
16 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
charging higher fees. Still another is that the state decides to keep
fees constant, but to ration judicial resources, either by delaying the
resolution of disputes, by dismissing a portion of suits based on
specified standards, by punishing lawyers for filing frivolous suits, or
by permitting judges to decide which disputes merit complete
treatment in a written opinion. Public decisions about rationing are
difficult, and high transaction costs may prevent private parties
(including non-parties to disputes who seek externality benefits
associated with published judicial opinions) from acting collectively to
persuade legislators and judges to ration efficiently.
This thought experiment casts doubt on the argument that the
evolution of the common law has been efficient. In thirteenth
century England, when the costs of resolving disputes were relatively
low, it may have been possible to minimize the common law system’s
inefficiencies without charging high fees or rationing judicial
resources.73 However, in modern society, it is not possible. The cost
of resolving even average disputes is very high, and there are political
pressures preventing state and federal governments from charging
high fees for access to judicial resources. Judicial resources are
rationed through an implicit pricing system; this system favors
wealthy institutions and individuals, who can afford the costs of
delay.74
Empirical data also raise questions about the efficiency of
common law. The inner workings of an effective system depend on
rational, well-informed judges who move the common law along in
the right direction. However, judges too often fall short of the ideal
standard. The judiciary is politicized, with the results in many cases
depending on which judge is drawn to hear a dispute.75 Judges are paid
much less in real terms than they were fifty years ago,76 and they are
confronting more complex cases brought by more parties and lawyers
than ever before.77 Especially in areas of rapidly evolving
technology, it is very difficult for judges to keep pace.78 For
example, on average judges in the Ninth Circuit each write twenty
thorough opinions per year, an amount Judges Alex Kozinski and
Stephen Reinhardt have likened to “writing a law review article every
73 In fact, there is evidence that early British courts did both. In early common
law systems, courts did charge fees, see BENSON, supra note 40, at 60-62, although it
is difficult to assess how those fees compared to the courts’ costs. A reasonable
assumption is that those courts that survived without other resources (e.g., tax
revenue distributed by the crown) were charging fees high at least enough to cover
their costs.
74 Delay benefits wealthy individuals and institutions involved in disputes
with less wealthy individuals and institutions. See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 17.
Tullock notes that the tragedy of the commons aspects of U.S. courts could be
eliminated by introducing market-clearing prices for access to courts, but that
numerous interests – including lawyers – would oppose such an introduction. Id. at
17-18.
75 See Emerson H. Tiller & Frank B. Cross, A Modest Proposal for Improving
American Justice, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 215 (1999); Patricia M. Wald, A Response to
Tiller and Cross, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 235 (1999).
76 See RICHARD A. POSNER, THE FEDERAL COURTS: CRISIS AND REFORM 32 (1985).
77 The U.S. has 70 percent of the world’s supply of lawyers. See TULLOCK, supra
note 23, at 25.
78 For example, judges have performed especially poorly in cases involving
financial innovation. See infra Part V.B.2.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
17
two and a half weeks.”79 Moreover, the very presence of a common
law system – especially a low fee system coupled with liberal
procedural rules80 – creates incentives for parties to be litigious,
thereby increasing the costs of dispute resolution, in a kind of
litigation death spiral.81 This picture of the common law process is
far different from the incremental growth and beauty imagined in
Learned Hand’s coral reef.
2. The Shrinking Supply of Legal Rules
Even if the common law is inefficient, it might nevertheless be of
value if it adequately performed its second function: adding to and
enriching the supply of legal rules in a way that reflects the values of
society. There are two reasons to suspect that the U.S. common law
system does not perform this function very well. First, the U.S.
common law system arguably is incapable of generating legal rules at
all, at least not the kind of credible, articulated legal rules parties need
for use in daily life. Second, even if the common law system could
generate appropriate legal rules in particular cases, reported judicial
decisions in those cases are disappearing from public view, with the
most important decisions disappearing first and most frequently. This
disappearance of precedent is the result predicted by the judicial park
thought experiment described in Part II.B.1.
First, consider the argument that the common law system is
incapable of generating legal rules at all. Jeremy Bentham expressed
the opinion that the common law was “a fiction from beginning to
end,”82 referring to the term variously as “mock law,” “sham law,”
and “quasi law.”83 Many legal positivists adhere to this view.84
79 See Alex Kozinski & Stephen Reinhardt, Please Don’t Cite This!: Why We
Don’t Allow Citations to Unpublished Dispositions, CAL. LAWYER, June 2000, at 43.
I am grateful to Ed Ursin for pointing out this article, which is not available through
electronic databases. During 1999, the Ninth Circuit decided 4,500 cases on the
merits, 700 by opinion and 3,800 by memorandum disposition, known as
“memdispo,” for an average of 20 opinions and 130 memdispos per judge, plus
another 300 or so decisions for which the judge sits on a panel and comments on a
decision, but does not author it. See id. at 44. Judges write thorough opinions in
only 15 percent of cases overall (including cases not decided on the merits). See id.
Memdispos cannot be cited as precedent; if they could, judges would need to spend
much closer attention to drafting them. Id. (“Most [memdispos] are drafted by law
clerks with relatively few edits from the judges.”).
80 An example is the class action, which although of great potential value and
importance obviously leads to a greater quantity and cost of litigation.
81 At the same time, each state’s common law system competes for business, a
competition that thus could be characterized as a race-to-the-bottom. This
competition is especially heated among procedural rules, including choice of law
and venue. For example, consider the popularity of certain states’ courts among
plaintiffs’ lawyers. Such competition is in sharp contrast with the early competition
among courts during the law merchant era. See supra note 38 (describing correlation
between common law principles and expectations of both parties to a dispute).
82 IV JEREMY BENTHAM, COLLECTED WORKS 483 (1838-43). Bentham wrote of the
phrase common law: “In these two words you have a name pretended to be the name
of a really existent object: - look for any such existing object – look for it till
doomsday, no such object will you find.” Id. See also JEREMY BENTHAM, A COMMENT
ON THE COMMENTARIES 125 (1928) (“As a system of general rules, the common law is a
thing merely imaginary.”).
83 Id. at 460. For an analysis of Bentham’s argument and the question of
whether the common law is a “fiction,” see Simpson, supra note 65, at 16-18.
84 Brian Simpson has described this argument with a simple question, “How can
it be said that the common law exists as a system of general rules, when it is
18 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Legal positivism depends on two preconditions: (1) that all laws owe
their status as law to the fact that they have been laid down, i.e.,
posited,85 and (2) that all laws exist as sets of rules, where the rule
constitutes the law.86 For legal positivists, the epistemological
argument is the end of the story: they reject common law, which
satisfies neither of the two conditions.
Even those who reject the strict legal positivism argument may
nonetheless find there are other reasons to doubt the common law’s
ability to generate valuable legal rules. Instead of conceiving of the
common law as a system of legal rules, one can regard it as customary
law, namely, the body of practices and ideas received over time by a
specific group, predominantly lawyers, who have used these practices
and ideas in disputes and in advising clients.87 In this sense, the
common law does not exist as a freestanding entity; rather, it exists
only in the minds of lawyers acting based upon it.
Numerous legal philosophers have agreed that the value of
common law propositions depends upon the degree to which they are
accepted as accurate statements of received ideas or practice.88
Common law as customary law is valuable only if it preserves a
considerable measure of continuity and cohesion. Such continuity and
cohesion in turn require that the system reinforce strong pressures
against innovation. New entrants to the system must be
indoctrinated, to some extent, in the value of precedent and the
importance of the system’s “sticky” adherence to prior decisions.
Although these requirements may have been satisfied in the early
English royal courts, it is difficult to argue that they are satisfied
today. The barriers to entry in the legal profession are crumbling;
non-lawyers can access and understand legal opinions and jargon;
there are hundreds of law schools.89 Indoctrination into legal
principles works very poorly in the U.S., even when directed at first
year law students.
impossible to say what they are?” Id.; see also id. (“As a system of legal thought the
common law then is inherently incomplete, vague and fluid; it is a feature of the
system that uniquely authentic statements of the rules which, so positivists tell us,
comprise the common law cannot be made.”).
85 Hans Kelsen wrote, “Law is always positive law, and its positivity lies in the
fact that it is created and annulled by acts of human beings, thus being independent
of morality and other norm systems.” HANS KELSEN, GENERAL THEORY OF LAW AND
THE STATE 114 (1961). The synthetic common law system proposed here is
consistent with this notion: it envisions many versions of “law,” each of which is
simply made up, or created. But note how radically different the operation of
synthetic common law is from the traditional conception of common law. The status
of synthetic common law as authoritative is driven, not by the fact that it has been
created, but by the fact that private parties choose to have that “law” govern their
lives.
One obvious weakness in the first condition of the positivist view is that
custom, which cannot plausibly said to have been laid down, also is said be a
possible type of law; however, it is difficult to say that custom is “posited” in the
same way statutes are, simply because custom is composed of some underlying
human action. See Simpson, supra note 65, at 11. If that were the case, what notion
of law would not encompass some positive aspect?
86 See id. at 11.
87 See id. at 20.
88 See id. at 21 (citing agreement with Hale and Blackstone).
89 Of course, the causation may work the other way, i.e., these changes may be
the reason for the shift from common law to statutory law in the U.S.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
19
This breakdown in the system of customary law presents a serious
paradox for proponents of the common law. If lawyers agree as to its
meaning, it is not necessary, for common practice alone should be a
sufficient guide for resolving disputes. If lawyers do not agree as to its
meaning, rules alone are unlikely to provide the necessary authority
for choosing one practice over another, however those rules are
created.
A final argument supporting a conclusion that common law
cannot generate credible legal rules is that courts lack the respect and
authority necessary for the generation of such rules. Courts derive
authority, at least in part, from individuals’ perceptions that they are
objective and impartial. Yet many scholars question the objectivity
of judges.90 Because judges are arbitrary, the argument goes, decisions
cannot be replicated.91 And if decisions cannot be replicated, the
common law cannot generate credible legal rules. Gordon Tullock has
contended that during the second half of the twentieth century92
courts have “severely eroded, if not entirely destroyed, the support-
legitimacy of the common law.”93
There is a second, perhaps more important, reason that the
modern version of common law in the U.S. does not add to or enrich
the supply of legal rules: decisions in those cases are disappearing
from public view. More than 60 percent of federal circuit court
decisions are not published.94 Of those opinions, a large number
either disappear or are pushed out of the relevant body of common
law by a variety of processes, including depublication, confidentiality
arrangements, vacatur, selective publication, and publication subject
to no-citation rules. All of these processes are problematic, and they
erode95 the value of traditional common law. How can private parties
90 Gordon Tullock has been a prominent proponent of this view. See, e.g.,
TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 2 (arguing that late twentieth century U.S. courts have
failed to maintain objectivity on a consistent basis).
91 See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 3 (finding that “the U.S. common law system
has failed to preserve such replicability across major and growing areas of law”).
92 It may be that the common law would work in a less complex society, but is
ill-suited to modern disputes in the twentieth-century U.S. One reason may be the
expansion of tort law in the U.S. In the eighteenth century, the common law was
composed largely of the law of contract, not of torts. Torts were thought to be of
limited reach and achieved legal status only for relationships not covered by
contract. See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 11. Because synthetic common law
involves ex ante agreement by private parties, it would not substantially affect
problems generated by the recent expansion of tort law, although a synthetic
common law regime might be applicable to certain areas of tort law, where private
parties might be able to specify a probability distribution of accidents.
93 See TULLOCK, supra note 23, at 2-3.
94 See Hinderks & Leben, supra note 46, at 158. Much of the scholarship in this
area has focused on the California state courts, where the problem is especially acute.
Less than 15 percent of appellate decisions in California are certified for publication
and the California Supreme Court depublishes 10 percent of those decisions. See
Philip L. Dubois, The Negative Side of Judicial Decision Making: Depublication as
a Tool of Judicial Power and Administration on State Courts of a Last Resort, 33
VILL. L. REV. 469, 488 (1988).
95 One commentator has described this erosion in terms of the building of a
sculpture: “Our system of precedent has become subtractive as well as additive. Like
a sculpture, it is shaped as much by what is removed as by what is added.” Slavitt,
supra note 66, at 109. This erosion metaphor applies equally well to Learned Hand’s
coral reef.
20 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
plan their affairs based on judicial determinations that are private or
withdrawn or even do not exist?
The problem is serious. As early as 1985, Judge Richard Posner
noted that “[d]espite the vast number of published opinions . . . judges
will confess that a surprising fraction of appeals are difficult to decide,
not because there are too many precedents but because there are too
few on point.”96 This problem has been magnified many-fold during
the past fifteen years, as the number of disappearing precedents has
increased and as the probability has declined of finding an on-point
case, especially in areas subject to rapid technological change. In
1998, the federal appellate courts disposed of more than a thousand
cases on the merits without any comment at all,97 and district courts
frequently dispose of cases without a detailed opinion or even oral
argument. Anthony Kronman has decried the shortcut opinion judges
frequently issue in place of the type of “original composition”
opinion that he believes “disciplines the imagination”98 Yet such
short cut reasoning should not be surprising in a society where the
costs of dispute resolution are very high; it is merely an attempt to
ration precious judicial resources.
Many courts now depublish or selectively publish decisions.99
Reduced publication means fewer case precedents and greater
96 See POSNER, supra note 76, at 123.
97 See William C. Smith, Big Objections to Brief Decisions, A.B.A. J., Aug. 1999,
at 34, 36 (noting that "[l]ast year, the federal appeals courts disposed of 25,020
appeals on the merits. About six percent of the total were disposed of without
comment, meaning the court did not expound the law as applied in the case, or did
not explain the reasons for the ruling"); Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 219.
98 “[O]pinion-writing disciplines the imagination. It is one thing to reach a
tentative conclusion in a case, but something very different to write an opinion
defending it. The search for the right words to support a judgment one has
provisionally formed often stirs up new objections and compels the reexamination
of earlier beliefs. A judge may feel that he has decided a case and is finished with it.
But when he attempts to justify his decision in writing, he will be forced to reenact
the drama of the original conflict in his imagination, taking first one side and then
the other in an effort to anticipate the strongest arguments that might be made
against his own earlier position and the best responses to them. Writing judicial
opinions imposes on the writer a duty of responsiveness that can be met only by
giving each side to a dispute its due, by entertaining every claim in its most
attractive light, and that in turn demands a special effort of imagination. The
discipline of opinion-writing is thus a goad to the imagination, and the greater the
distance of the writer from the original conflict in a case, the more valuable this
discipline becomes as a guard against the relaxation of his imaginative powers:
which is why it is especially needed at the appellate level. In many appellate courts,
however, this discipline is weaker today than it has been in the past. In part this is
due to procedural changes in court practice that permit more cases to be decided with
no opinion or only an unpublished one-changes intended to increase the number of
disputes that a court can decide in a given period of time. But a more important
cause of the weakening of this discipline has been the growing tendency of appellate
judges to work by editing draft opinions prepared for them by their clerks instead of
writing opinions themselves . . . [E]diting does not in general make as strong a
demand on the imagination as original composition.” ANTHONY T. KRONMAN, THE
LOST LAWYER: FAILING IDEALS OF THE LEGAL PROFESSION 330-31 (1995).
99 For example, the California Supreme Court depublishes more appellate
opinions each year than it publishes of its own. See Gerald F. Uelman, Losing Steam,
CAL. LAW., June 1990, at 33, 43. Depublication and selective publication have been
popular topics among legal commentators. See Slavitt, supra note 66; William L.
Reynolds & William M. Richman, The Non-Precedential Precedent-Limited
Publication and No-Citation Rules in the United States Court of Appeals, 78
COLUM. L. REV. 1167 (1978); Gerald F. Uelman, Publication and Depublication of
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
21
uncertainty, especially in business disputes. The purported
justification for selective publication and no-citations rules is to
allocate scarce judicial resources away from the writing of less
consequential opinions to the writing of a smaller number of well-
crafted, more important opinions.100 Judges spend almost one-third
of their time writing opinions,101 and simply do not have the time
and resources necessary to write opinions that will be suitable
additions to the body of common law.102
The effect of limiting publication is not merely a reduction in
published decisions. Selective publication and no-citation rules also
create moral hazard problems by giving judges a form of insurance
against reversal. Armed with the knowledge that an opinion will not
be published or cannot be cited, a judge is unlikely to devote sufficient
care to crafting an opinion.103 As a result, both the quantity and
quality of judicial decisions is reduced, perhaps so much that the
limiting rules are unconstitutional. On August 22, 2000, Judge Arnold
of the Eighth Circuit found unconstitutional a rule limiting the
precedential effort of certain decisions within that Circuit, finding
that the rule expanded the judicial power beyond the limits of Article
III by allowing judges the discretion to determine which judicial
decisions are binding and which are not.104
Another phenomenon chipping away at the common law occurs
when parties to litigation reach a private settlement following a
district court’s judgment with the condition that the appellate court
vacate the lower court’s judgment. This process – known as
“vacatur”105 – changes the shape of judicial precedent in a perverse
California Court of Appeal Opinions: Is the Eraser Mightier than the Pencil?, 26
LOY. L.A. L. REV. 1007 (1993); Stephen R. Barnett, Making Decisions Disappear:
Depublication and Stipulated Reversal in the California Supreme Court, 26 LOY.
L.A. L. REV. 1033 (1993); Dubois, supra note 94, at 488; Joseph R. Grodin, The
Depublication Practice of the California Supreme Court, 72 CAL. L. REV. 514
(1984).
100 See Carpenter, Jr., supra note 103, at 251 (arguing that the “real reason” for
these rules is the overload on the appellate courts).
101 See Reynolds & Richman, supra note 99, at 1183 n.95.
102 See Slavitt, supra note 66, at 123.
103 “When a judge knows ahead of time that an opinion will not be published,
she can save time. First, the judge does not need to recite carefully the facts of the
case because the parties are already familiar with them. Second, it is unnecessary to
rehearse all of the arguments; the judge is able to focus the opinion on the
dispositive issues. Third, the judge need not spend as much time eliminating vague
language that other litigants may attempt to expand in later cases. Because
unpublished opinions serve no future purpose, judges need only provide a minimal
indication of the reasoning that a fully explicated opinion would have followed.”
Slavitt, supra note 66, at 123-24; see also Charles E. Carpenter, Jr., The No-Citation
Rule for Unpublished Opinions: Do the Ends of Expediency for Overloaded
Appellate Courts Justify the Means of Secrecy?, 50 S.C. L. REV. 235, 251 (1998).
104 See Anastasoff v. U.S., 2000 U.S. App. LEXIS 21179 (8th Cir. 2000). For a
discussion of some of the policy implications raised by the Anastasoff case, as well
as a detailed study of the Third Circuit’s practice of disposing of cases without
comment, see Mitu Gulati & C.M.A. McCauliff, 61 LAW & CONTEMP. PROB. 157
(1998).
105 Vacatur also has been a popular topic among legal commentators. See
Stephen R. Barnett, supra note 99; Judith Resnik, Whose Judgment? Vacating
Judgments, Preferences for Settlement, and the Role of Adjudication at the Close of
the Twentieth Century, 41 UCLA L. REV. 1471 (1994); Slavitt, supra note 66; Henry
E. Klingeman, Settlement Pending Appeal: An Argument for Vacatur, 58 FORDHAM L.
REV. 233 (1989).
22 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
way by eliminating a particular class of cases, typically those in which
one party decides that the cost of the decision (including the cost of
its precedential value in future cases106) is greater than the cost of
settlement.
For example, suppose Natasha sues her insurance company for its
bad faith refusal to pay her claim. Natasha and her attorney refuse to
settle the case for less than $100,000. The insurer is unwilling to pay
that much and files a motion for summary judgment. The judge
decides against the insurer in a decision that will cost the insurer
millions of dollars in future cases. The insurer then offers to settle
with Natasha for $100,000. Natasha and her attorney believe she will
win if the insurer appeals, but that the appeals process will be costly.
Therefore, Natasha is willing to settle. In this example, the insurer
might even sweeten its offer to persuade Natasha to settle. The result
would be a settlement for some amount between $100,000 and the
insurer’s perceived cost (in present value terms) of future cases if it
does not settle.
Both of the individual parties to the litigation are better off.
Who is worse off? If the judicial decision being vacated was correct in
terms of assessing the overall costs and benefits, vacating that
decision will transfer wealth from future claimants/insureds to the
insurance company,107 enabling the insurance company to benefit
from externalizing its future costs.108 Those future non-parties
harmed by vacatur face very high transaction costs in acting
collectively, and even if they were able to agree in time to pay for the
benefits of the judicial decision, it is unclear how they would do so.
Bribing the judge is illegal, and cases are vacated shortly after the
judge issues the opinion. Moreover, the insurer and the non-parties
might not agree about how much the decision would increase the
insurer’s costs of resolving future cases, and there would be very little
time to contract and bargain with the insurer.
Not surprisingly, vacating large numbers of decisions erodes
respect for courts, in part because vacated decisions likely attempted
to assess the overall costs and benefits in a particular case, and likely
favored future litigants more than they harmed the losing party. One
judge, writing in dissent in a California state case, noted that “[p]ublic
respect for the courts is eroded when this court decides that a party
who has litigated and lost in the trial court can, by paying a sum of
money sufficient to secure settlement conditioned on reversal,
purchase the nullification of the adverse judgment.”109
Published judicial decisions also are disappearing because of the
large number of decisions issued subject to confidentiality orders or
under seal. Much litigation takes place under confidential stipulation,
with documents and testimony sealed away from non-parties. Judges
often conduct the pretrial phase of a case outside public view and
without articulating their reasoning in writing or on the record. At
pretrial conferences, after the judge calls a case, the parties’ counsel
106 In addition, a vacated judgment cannot be used for collateral estoppel
purposes. See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 216.
107 If the decision did not correctly assess overall costs and benefits, this
settlement might be the optimal solution for both the private parties and for society.
108 See Resnik, Whose Judgment?, supra note 105, at 1500.
109 Neary v. Regents of Univ. of Cal., 834 P.2d 119, 127 (Cal. 1992) (Kennard, J.
dissenting).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
23
often are led to the judge’s private chambers or a conference room to
discuss the case with no court reporter present.110 These private
aspects of the judicial process undercut judicial obligations and may
even induce judges prematurely to favor one side of a dispute.111 Like
vacatur, confidentiality benefits parties to the dispute at the expense
of future non-parties who might have benefited from a public decision
and opinion.
Moreover, under current law, non-parties to the litigation have no
basis for complaint. Courts generally have interpreted the public’s
right of access to civil judicial proceedings to apply only to pleadings,
motions, exhibits, and court transcripts.112 Other materials are off
limits.113 Even those materials presumptively open to the public may
be closed to the public by agreement of the court and the parties; even
pleadings may be sealed.114
Confidentiality in disputes creates private benefits and imposes
societal costs. It is unclear which weighs heavier. The private
benefits include protecting the parties’ reputations and intellectual
property. The societal costs include the loss of value associated with
the information. Some of these benefits and costs are offsetting: for
example, information about a case involving the manufacture of a
product may harm the manufacturer (by making it subject to future
litigation costs) in the same way it benefits consumers (by giving
them the information necessary to litigate). On the other hand,
private benefits are likely to be localized, in most cases involving
only the parties to the litigation, whereas societal benefits are likely
to be diffuse, depending on the nature of the underlying activity.
Absent transaction costs, one would expect those harmed by the
nondisclosure of information to bargain for the information;
however, transaction costs in these instances are likely to be high, due
both to collective action problems and the difficulty of valuing the
external costs.
The disappearance of common law may be a symptom of a more
troubling problem: in the U.S. today, a “true” judicial common law
may simply be too costly. Specifically, it may be too costly to have
judges spell out their reasoning in complex business disputes. It is
extraordinarily expensive for judges to hear every case publicly,
decide all important issues in those cases on the record, and write
detailed well-reasoned opinions supporting these decisions. These
costs are especially high for business disputes in areas of rapidly
evolving technology where judges lack expertise.115 Nearly half of
federal district court judges come from a prosecutorial background,
experience that is important for any judge who will be deciding
110 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 212 (describing the authors’ experience
in California courts).
111 See generally Judith Resnik, Managerial Judges, 96 HARV. L. REV. 376
(1982).
112 See Resnik, Whose Judgment?, supra note 105, at 1493 n.84.
113 See Arthur R. Miller, Confidentiality, Protective Orders, and Public Access
to the Courts, 105 HARV. L. REV. 427 (1991).
114 See Nault’s Auto Sales, Inc. v. American Honda Motor Co., 148 F.R.D. 25
(D.N.H. 1993).
115 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 205-07 (describing perceived lack of
expertise in judges presiding over business disputes).
24 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
criminal cases,116 but many fewer have sophisticated business
backgrounds.117 Moreover, in an environment of disappearing
precedent, litigation becomes much more expensive, as parties are
forced to litigate issues another court might have decided already but
not have published an opinion describing the decision. Thereby,
litigants find themselves forced to reinvent the wheel over and over
again.
At the same time the costs of judicial decisions are increasing, the
benefits of decisions are decreasing. Who gains from a reported
judicial decision? The parties gain something – a description of the
basis for decision – although at least one party (the losing one) likely
would prefer not to suffer public scrutiny based on the decision.118
Future litigants gain from the certainty associated with the
precedential value of the opinion, but only if the opinion is clear, well
reasoned, and relevant to future disputes. Often, decisions are too
limited in scope to issues that are unlikely to arise in future litigation,
or are too unclear, poorly reasoned, or irrelevant to be of value to
future litigants.
For all of these reasons, there are limits to the common law.
Commentators and practitioners should understand how these
arguments are relevant, especially in costly business disputes. In the
U.S. today, a common law system may not be able to satisfy the
efficiency and fairness goals of society, even if there are persuasive
arguments that common law has done so historically.
III. ALTERNATIVES TO COMMON LAW
There are alternatives to common law, including statutory law,
private law, and private adjudication. Alternatives can be classified119
116 Of recent appointees to federal district court, the percentages coming from a
prosecutorial background were 40.7% under President Clinton, 39.2% under
President Bush, 44.1% under President Reagan, and 38.1% under President Carter.
See Sheldon Goldman & Elliot Slotnick, Clinton’s Second Term Judiciary: Picking
Judges Under Fire, 82 JUDICATURE 264, 275 (May-June 1999).
117 Much of this is for economic reasons. For attorneys, private practice pays
more than judging, which discourages entry; for judges, private practice and private
judging (e.g., serving as an arbitrator or mediator) pays more than judging, which
encourages exit. See William C. Smith, Bailing From the Bench, A.B.A. J., May 1999,
at 22 (noting that this drain from the bench especially is true for the best business
judges). These comments are not in any way directed at the Honorable Michael B.
Mukasey (for whom I clerked) of the Southern District of New York, who remains the
best business judge I know. Unfortunately, Judge Mukasey has not yet had the
opportunity to decide a major derivatives case. When and if he does, his opinion in
that case may resolve some of the problems presented infra at Part V.B.2.
118 Especially in costly business disputes, one party may lose a great deal in
reputational costs from an unfavorable decision, and therefore may be willing to
settle prior to decision, even if the terms of the settlement are less favorable than the
party believes is warranted in the particular case.
119 Thomas Barton has described the structure of decisional institutions in four
parts: (1) the method of problem identification (active vs. reactive), (2) the degree of
deliberation involving in reaching a decision (spontaneous vs. deliberative), (3) the
level of participation and control by the disputants (disputants control vs. third-
party control), and (4) the substantive justification for decisions (rigid vs. flexible).
The classification here is similar to the first part of Barton’s structure, except that ex
ante is substituted for active and ex post is substituted for reactive, and the
public/private distinction is added. See Thomas D. Barton, Common Law and Its
Substitutes: The Allocation of Social Problems to Alternative Decisional
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
25
based on two variables. First, is the system’s source of legal rules
public or private? Second, does the system specify legal rules to
resolve disputes ex ante or does it adjudicate disputes based on an ex
post specification?
The following schematic diagram illustrates the different
approaches:
Institutions, 63 N.C.L. REV. 519 (1985). My classification obviously is stylized, and
many regulatory approaches will not fit neatly within the confines of a particular
quadrant in Figure 1 infra.
26 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
The left half of the diagram depicts methods of dispute resolution
involving ex ante specification of applicable legal rules; the right half
depicts methods involving ex post specification. The top half of the
diagram depicts methods of dispute resolution where the source of the
applicable legal rules is a public (i.e., governmental) entity; the
bottom half of the diagram depicts methods where the source is a
private entity.
Part II analyzed the upper right quadrant, common law,120 the
most important dispute resolution system for the purposes of this
article. This Part briefly analyzes the alternatives in the remaining
quadrants. Part III.A. considers the top left quadrant, statutory law,
including codes in civil law regimes. Part III.B. considers the bottom
left quadrant, private law, including model acts and model default
terms for contracts. Part III.C. considers the bottom right quadrant,
private adjudication. There are serious problems associated with each
alternative.
A. The Viability of Statutory Law
A complete discussion of statutory law regimes is beyond the
scope of this article. The purpose of this section is to sketch briefly
some of the arguments for and against such regimes, to assess when
statutory regimes are more (or less) likely to be efficient and fair, and
to provide a benchmark for comparing synthetic common law.
The dominant alternative to common law is statutory law. The
vast majority of jurisdictions are civil law jurisdictions, in that their
legal regimes consist largely of legal codes and statutes instead of
common law. Moreover, the modern U.S. system is largely based on
statutes and administrative law rules and regulations.
The primary purported advantage of statutes is clarity. Ideally, a
private party planning future action can read a statute and understand
what class of conduct is prohibited, what class is permitted, and the
120 Common law adjudication frequently involves the specification of legal
rules ex post, particularly in cases of first impression. To the extent common law
legal rules are used in future cases, an argument can be made that common law
adjudication also involves the specification of legal rules ex ante. In other words,
not every common law specification of legal rules will fit neatly within the upper
right quadrant of Figure 1.
Private
Public
Ex PostEx Ante
Statutory Law Common Law
Private Adjudication Private Law
Figure 1
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
27
costs of undertaking prohibited conduct. Statutes can spell out details
about how particular behavior will be governed. In doing so, statutes
can attempt to regulate anticipated behavior. Accordingly, statutes
are most highly valued when all contingencies can be specified clearly
in advance.
Moreover, in democratic regimes statutes are thought to reflect
popular will. Unlike most common law judges, who are largely
unaccountable to the public, legislators face reelection and must
satisfy the concerns of their constituents – or lose their jobs.
Another strength of statutes (and a weakness of common law) is
that “the process of judicial development of law is of necessity
gradual and may prove too slow to bring about the desirable rapid
adaptation of the law to wholly new circumstances.”121 Thus, statutes
are most likely to be effective when the democratic process is
working to ensure protection of the reasonable expectations of
parties.
Unfortunately, statutes often are far from clear. Language may
be ambiguous, and resort to legislative history may be unhelpful.
Statutes require interpretation by human judges, who in turn require a
theory of legislation.122 Interpretation is an elastic concept,
composed of more than logic.123 Justice Cardozo believed judges were
capable of enormous creativity when confronted with a wide range of
statutes.124 Max Radin has emphasized the parity of statutes and
common law in the hands of judges.125 In other words, although
judges are not free to change the words of a statute (as they are with
the common law) through the workings of judicial interpretation,
judges have as much freedom in deciding difficult statutory cases as
they have in deciding difficult common law cases. Judge Richard
Posner has agreed with this point.126 Again, statutes are most valued
when contingencies can be specified clearly.
121 HAYEK, supra note 53, at 88. Hayek has noted that it is undesirable for
judicial decisions to reverse a development, because the judge “is not performing
his function if he disappoints reasonable expectation created by earlier decisions.”
Id.
122 See RONALD DWORKIN, LAW’S EMPIRE 17 (1986).
123 Judge Richard Posner is a proponent of this view: “The current bastion of
legal formalism is not the common law; it is statutory and constitutional
interpretation. It is here that we find the most influential modern attempts to derive
legal outcomes by methods superficially akin to deduction. The attempts will fail.
The interpretations of texts is not a logical exercise, and the bounds of
‘interpretation’ are so elastic (considering that among the verbal and other objects
that are interpreted are dreams, texts in foreign languages, and … musical
compositions) as to cast the utility of the concept into doubt.” RICHARD A. POSNER,
OVERCOMING LAW 400 (1995).
124 Cardozo included the U.S. Constitution, noting that John Marshall “gave to
the constitution of the United States the impress of his own mind; and the form of
our constitutional law is what it is, because he moulded it while it was still plastic
and malleable in the fire of his own intense convictions.” BENJAMIN N. CARDOZO, THE
NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL PROCESS 169-170 (1921).
125 See generally Max Radin, Statutory Interpretation, 43 HARV. L. REV. 863,
881 (1930); Max Radin, A Short Way with Statutes, 56 HARV. L. REV. 388 (1942).
James Landis argued, quite reasonably, that Radin’s approach should be limited to
exclude “easy” cases, when the statute’s meaning is clear on its face or can be
clarified by legislative history. See James M. Landis, A Note on “Statutory
Interpretation”, 43 HARV. L. REV. 886 (1930).
126 POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 392.
28 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
In addition, statutes are primary directed at regulating and limiting
government; they perform less well in regulating and limiting private
conduct.127 The legislative process is buffeted by greater interest-
group pressures than the judicial process and therefore may be less
likely to reflect sound policy judgments.128 As Hayek has argued,
there is nothing magical about the legislative process that causes it to
“uncover” efficient legal rules.129
Public choice and interest group theories have demonstrated that
the legislative process often works to redistribute wealth to narrow
coalitions, not in the public interest.130 Under pressure from these
theories, it “becomes unclear where to locate statutory meaning,
problematic to speak of judges discerning legislative intent, and
uncertain why judges should seek to perfect through interpretation the
decrees of the special-interest state.”131
At best, statutes reflect the popular will of a prior electorate, not
the current one, and in areas where technologies are rapidly changing
may not reflect the interests and expectations of the relevant parties.
Therefore, in an imperfectly functioning democracy, statutes – even
to the extent they accurately reflect constituent interests – may
reflect only a portion of society’s interests.
Next, consider how information becomes reflected in legal rules.
In a common law system, the judge articulates the relevant legal rules
after one or more private parties involved in a dispute have chosen to
have the judge adjudicate that dispute. The judge decides the dispute
with reference to statutory rules, prior cases, commentary, and
societal practice. The information reflected in the judge’s decision
includes the preferences of the parties to the transaction, as well as
the body of existing law. This information is described in narrative
form.
In a statutory system, the legislature articulates the relevant legal
rules after particular legislators (lobbied by supporters and constrained
by voters) have chosen to have the legislature consider the rules. The
legislature decides to adopt or reject the rules with reference to public
debate, commentary, and societal practice. The information reflected
in the legislature’s decision includes the preferences of society
generally, or of the legislators’ supporters specifically. This
information is described in non-narrative form.
Thus, the information “forced” to be reflected in the relevant
legal rules differs under common law and statutory law. The objective
of fair and efficient legal rules is to reflect the interests of society.
127 See, e.g., HAYEK, supra note 53, at 127 (noting that for the past several
centuries the overwhelming majority of statutes have been concerned with
administrative law and direct measures of government); see also id. at 133.
128 POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 393.
129 See, e.g., HAYEK, supra note 53, at 72 (noting that “[u]nlike law itself, which
has never been ‘invented’ in the same sense, the invention of legislation came
relatively late in the history of mankind”); see also id. at 73 (“Yet there can be no
doubt that law existed for ages before it occurred to man that he could make or alter
it.”).
130 As Judge Posner put it, “A further complication for the theory of statutory
interpretation is that we no longer think of statutes as typically, let alone invariably,
the product of well-meaning efforts to promote the public interest by legislators who
are devoted to that interest and who are the faithful representatives of constituents
who share the same devotion.” POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 400.
131 Id. at 400.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
29
This information is the vehicle for doing so, and therefore the utility
of one system over the other depends largely on the value of such
information. Consequently, one should expect common law and
statutory law to achieve different benefits in different areas of
practice. One regime or the other is not inherently preferable. In
some areas of practice, where the democratic process works
effectively, statutory rules will best reflect overall societal
preferences. In other areas, where a small number of private parties
assisted by a judge can “outperform” the legislature, common law rules
will best reflect such preferences.
It is difficult to offer a general analysis of when a particular
societal practice will be more susceptible to the information-forcing
mechanisms of statutory versus common law. Common law is likely
to deliver superior information when the legislative process is not
working effectively or in a timely manner, and when the nature of the
practice is best served by narrative, as opposed to statutory rules.132
Private parties interacting in the “traditional” areas of common law
(e.g., contract, property, tort) may find legal rules expressed through
narrative clearer and easier to understand than statutory
specifications. In contrast, private parties interacting in the
“traditional” areas of statutory law (e.g., utilities, transportation,
commercial) may prefer clear articulation of general rules and abhor
the ambiguity of legal narrative.
Judge Posner has argued that reasoning by analogy is valuable in
fixing the boundaries of a legal rule when language is vague and
therefore is not a reliable guide to the rule’s actual scope; in such
instances an adjudicator should determine that scope through
reference to hypothetical cases (i.e., stories).133 In contrast,
analogical reasoning is unnecessary when a legal rule is clear, even in
translation (e.g., as in the instructions for assembling a table, or in the
provision of the U.S. Constitution that the President must be at least
35 years old).134
The issue is complex, but there are reasons to believe individuals
may benefit from common law over statutory rules simply because of
the former’s narrative structure. People rarely read statutes or
regulations, and when they do they rarely find them useful.135
Statutes often include narrative examples or cases to clarify any
perceived ambiguities, or to draw the attention or interested parties.
The various Restatements of the Laws are obvious examples.
Finally, even if one rejects the above analysis of the benefits of
analogical reasoning, it is more difficult to reject a series of recent
studies by several economists attempting to determine whether
statutory regimes or common law regimes generate superior economic
results. These studies found common law systems to be superior in
132 See POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 471-97.
133 See id. at 520.
134 See id. at 493. Numerous scholars have set forth the arguments for and
against analogical reasoning. See, e.g, Emily Sherwin, A Defense of Analogical
Reasoning in Law, 66 U. CHI. L. REV. 1179 (1999) (arguments for); Larry Alexander,
Bad Beginnings, 145 U. PA. L. REV. 57 (1996) (arguments against). One need not
accept either of the arguments to recognize that in certain areas of practice,
analogical reasoning and narrative may have greater utility than statute-like rules.
135 See Eisenberg, Text Anxiety, supra note 4.
30 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
nearly every economic aspect.136 Economic performance speaks
louder than philosophical argument.
B. Private Law
Legal scholars have been unsatisfied with the development of
statutory law for many decades, and have made private efforts to
improve these statutes. These efforts include model acts and uniform
private laws, including the various Restatements of the Laws, the
Model Penal Code, and the Uniform Commercial Code.
For example, the UCC provides that every contract imposes an
obligation of good faith in its performance or enforcement.137
Similarly, the Restatement (Second) of Contracts states as a general
principle that every contract imposes upon each party a duty of good
faith and fair dealing in its performance and enforcement.138
Commentators draft these model acts and uniform laws outside the
context of the legislative process, in the hope that legislatures will
adopt them and thereby rationalize or improve statutory law.
In addition, lawyers and other parties also have created private
default terms or standard form contracts, many of which are widely
used. Much of agency, partnership, and corporate law consists of such
default rules.139 Numerous services provide standard form contracts
for parties to use in various areas of law.140 Private default terms and
standard form contracts are analytically equivalent to model acts and
uniform private laws, the primary difference being the intended
audience. While the former is directed to private parties engaging in
contracting, the latter is directed more generally to legislators. All
such private law offers the benefits of the considered judgment of
non-governmental actors.
As with statutes, the primary purported advantage to private law
is clarity. Model acts are drafted by commentators knowledgeable in
the field, who attempt to delineate every possible anticipated result.
Private parties using standard contract default terms are able to tailor
such terms to reflect their best understanding of how future disputes
should be resolved.
The argument in favor of a private law system is that it is more
likely to reflect societal practice than a system instituted by
legislators or judges far removed from practice. Legal rules percolate
up through private parties to practitioners to commentators and,
finally, to legislators or judges. Legal rules need not be debated or
litigated in a legislative or judicial setting; they can simply be written
down.
There is no general agreement as to the line of distinction
between private and public law.141 The UCC, sections of the various
Restatements, and many model acts all are now public law. Much
private law consists simply of proposals aspiring to be public law. If
136 See supra note 3.
137 See U.C.C. § 1-203.
138 See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 205.
139 Many of these default rules are embodied in state statutes; other simply
become part of private contracts.
140 See, e.g., Standard Forms (2000) <http://findlaw.com>. Most large law firms
have developed standard forms that attorneys can tailor to a individual party’s
needs..
141 See HAYEK, supra note 53, at 132.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
31
the legislative process is working properly, the legislature will adopt
all private law proposals that make society better off; non-adopted
proposals by definition are those that would not make society better
off. However, if the legislative process is not working properly,
advocates of private law that would make society better will face
difficulties in persuading legislators to adopt their proposals. Note
that these arguments relate to the workings of the democratic
process, not to the comparative advantage or disadvantage of private
law. To the extent private law consists of proposals to be made
statutory law, all of the arguments in Part III.A. apply equally to
private law, and need not be restated here.
However, much of private law is not directed at legislators. To
the extent private law consists of default terms and standard form
agreements intended for use by private parties, it is not aspiring to be
public law at all. In fact, the rationale for such terms and agreements
is that private parties are best able to establish legal rules to govern
their daily conduct, and that legislatures and courts should respect
those decisions and not interfere.
Unfortunately, there are limitations to the ability of private
parties to establish such terms and agreements. Private law – like
judicial opinions – has the characteristics of a public good, and
therefore will tend to be underprovided unless subsidized. There are
mechanisms for distributing private law to parties in a more efficient
manner than a series of individual negotiations (i.e., reinventing the
wheel), although these mechanisms are not tailored to, and often do
not satisfy, the needs of particular parties, including confidentiality.
Moreover, although private law may serve to guide practice
absent a dispute, parties relying on private law provisions nevertheless
will need to specify a means of resolving disputes. A major limitation
to private law is that private ex ante alternatives do not provide a
mechanism for resolving disputes. Consequently, even parties
choosing private law must use either the courts or some means of
private adjudication, both of which have drawbacks.142
Another problem with private law is that private parties
attempting to specify all of the details associated with future dispute
resolution will find it very costly to specify all contingencies. More
importantly, they will not necessarily accrue any of the benefits of
other parties’ similar efforts. As with statutes, the argument here is
not a general indictment of private law; it simply indicates when
private law is most likely to be useful: when parties can specify all or
most contingencies.143
Finally, private law relies on a statute-like, non-narrative method
of describing legal rules. For parties who understand and can assess
narrative better than boilerplate, private law may not serve its
intended purpose.144 For such parties, private law may create or
leverage inequities. One party may use its advantageous position in
information or sophistication to obtain agreement to lengthy or
142 See supra Part II.B. and infra Part III.C.
143 Contingencies can be thought of as options, and to the extent option rights
are not allocated or specified ex ante, disputes based on private law agreements are
very difficult to adjudicate.
144 See supra note 4.
32 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
complex terms the other party would not agreed to if such terms were
understood.
Private law may be of great utility, both to the extent it becomes
public law and to the extent it specifies methods of dispute resolution.
Ultimately, however, the utility of private law will turn on the
efficiency and fairness of the means of dispute resolution, and on the
ability of the parties to specify contingencies ex ante in non-narrative
form.
C. Opting Out through Private Adjudication
As an alternative, parties may choose not to be subject to either
common law or statute-based regimes. They may simply opt out of
such regimes by choosing to have any dispute governed by a private
dispute resolution mechanism.145
Subject to limited judicial review,146 parties to a private contract
can decide in advance to adjudicate any disputes in a private regime,
generally referred to as Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADR).
Parties do so frequently.147 For example, private parties often
choose to handle private arbitrations through the American
Arbitration Association (“AAA”), which has been an especially
popular venue for parties contracting in areas of rapidly evolving
technologies, including computer, patent, trademark, and copyright
law.148 The Federal Mediation and Conciliation Service (FMCS) and
AAA each assist in the selection of arbitrators and provide some
additional services, all for a nominal fee.149 As an alternative to
ADR, parties often agree to mediation.
Private adjudication is touted as offering certain advantages,
especially lower cost, as compared to the other dispute resolution
regimes. From an economic perspective, private adjudication is said
to avoid the tragedy of the commons problem associated with
common law, because all of the costs are internalized to the parties.
Courts are publicly funded, but taxpayers do not subsidize alternative
forums. Arbitration must create perceived economic efficiencies in
some cases; otherwise, it could not compete against subsidized
145 For a general discussion of private dispute resolution and the dominating
role played by Professor Lon Fuller, see Robert G. Bone, Lon Fuller’s Theory of
Adjudication and the False Dichotomy Between Dispute Resolution and Public Law
Models of Litigation, 75 B.U.L. REV. 1273 (1995).
146 The standards for judicial review of arbitration determinations are highly
restrictive, based on standards such as “arbitrary and capricious,” “manifest
disregard for the law,” and “completely irrational.” See Harold Brown, Alternative
Dispute Resolution Realities and Remedies, 30 SUFFOLK U. L. REV. 743, 762 (1997);
see also Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 208 n.67 (noting that in California “it has
become virtually impossible to set aside an arbitrator’s award because the state
legislature amended the state arbitration act to provide that an arbitrator’s award
stands even where an error exists on the face of the award”).
147 The Center for Public Resources has established an Institute for Dispute
Resolution, which has obtained more than 4,000 corporate and 1,500 law firm
signatures. See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 200, n.43; see also
<http://www.cpradr.org/>.
148 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 200 n.43.
149 As of 2000, FMCS charged $30 per request; AAA charged $150 per case. See
LAURA J. COOPER, DENNIS R. NOLAN & RICHARD A. BALES, ADR IN THE WORKPLACE 20
(2000). Of course, the arbitrator(s) selected will then charge their hourly or daily
rate.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
33
judges.150 This phenomenon is not unusual. Profit and non-profit
firms coexist within other industries, notwithstanding the tax
advantages to non-profit firms.151
In addition to economic benefits, there may be psychological
benefits to private adjudication. Recent empirical research in
psychology shows that once people are persuaded to participate in
private dispute resolution, they tend to prefer such regimes to
court.152 Accordingly, many view private adjudication as both
efficient and as a kinder, gentler way to resolve disputes.153
However, there are numerous problems associated with these
alternatives. First, private adjudication actually may be very costly
relative to its benefits. It is difficult to compare directly the costs and
benefits of private adjudication and courts, because courts are publicly
subsidized and judicial costs and benefits are difficult to specify.
However, there are reasons to believe arbitration is quite costly
compared to court, especially given that claims of the recent
“litigation explosion” and increase in judicial costs in U.S. courts may
be exaggerated, if not false.154
Moreover, private adjudication fails to generate the public
benefits (e.g., maintaining credibility of a particular legal system, such
as patent law) associated with judicial dispute resolution.155
Arbitration cannot provide the range of services a judge provides.156
Nor will arbitration always occur; for example, if the parties cannot
agree on the selection of an arbitrator, they will resort to court. Also,
judges must enforce arbitral awards. Even if the value of additional
judicial services not available in arbitration cannot be measured
precisely, it is clear that they are non-trivial. Accordingly, any cost
reductions achieved through private adjudication may be at the
150 See, e.g, POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 115 (“The incentive
effect of conditioning the private judge’s compensation on satisfying a market
demand may therefore enable the slack associated with the counterpart nonprofit
service to be avoided at reasonable cost, so that in some areas of dispute resolution
private judging can compete effectively with public judging even though the latter
is subsidized.”); see also William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, Adjudication as a
Private Good, 8 J.LEG. STUDIES 235 (1979) (assessing the economics of arbitration
and private judging generally); Robert D. Cooter, The Objectives of Private and
Public Judges, 41 PUBLIC CHOICE 107 (1983); Jeffrey N. Gordon, Corporations,
Markets, and Courts, 91 COL. L. REV. 1931, 1967-71 (1991).
151 See BURTON A. WEISBROD, THE NONPROFIT ECONOMY, Ch. 8 (1988).
152 Several studies have show that “it is difficult to induce conflicting parties to
choose mediation, a procedure that lessens third party control and that makes the
sure attainment of any given outcome problematic, but that also engenders feelings
of social engagement and involvement. However, once experienced, mediation
procedures tend to be evaluated quite positively by the disputing parties, and to
produce decisions that the parties are likely to find satisfactory and voluntarily
accept." Tyler, supra note 49 at 102.
153 See Tyler et al., supra note 49, at 102.
154 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 201.
155 See Brown, supra note 146, at 760-61.
156 Judge Posner has described these services as follows: “There is, it is true, a
good deal of private judging. But an arbitrator or other private judge is hired by the
parties to a dispute to resolve that dispute, not to produce the full range of judicial
services. The full range includes rulemaking through the issuance of opinions that
interpret statutes, common law principles, rules and regulations, and constitutional
provisions; the provision of a stand-by dispute-resolution service for people who
can’t agree on a neutral arbiter; the interposition of a neutral body between the state
and the citizen – and the enforcement of arbitration awards, making the public judge
a backstop to the private one.” POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 114.
34 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
expense of one or more of the parties. For example, one of the
greatest potential benefits of private adjudication is that it avoids the
prospect of a jury trial, an event many business executives have little
confidence in and seek to avoid. However, the absence of a jury trial
may prejudice one or more parties, depending on the panel or
arbitrator chosen to adjudicate the dispute.157
Although arbitration is not a common law system, both parties
and arbitrators often attempt to behave as is they were in a common
law system, citing precedents and decisions to support their
positions.158 However, arbitrators owe little regard to the decisions of
other arbitrators, and only a small number of such decisions are
published. Those few published arbitration decisions are not
representative of other decisions, and are difficult for parties to
access.159 Common law reasoning in arbitration yields poor results
because of the wide variation in arbitration agreements and factual
contexts, variation that is not described in detail in individual
arbitrations yet may account for different results.160 Of course, there
is variation in fact patterns in common law cases, too, but to the
extent judges describe this variation in published opinions, parties are
able to distinguish among cases.
The selection of an arbitrator is very much ad hoc.161 Typically,
the parties do not select the arbitrator until after it is apparent they
will not be able to resolve the dispute without recourse to
157 See id. at 204. Business people also seem to find judges inexperienced in
commercial matters. Judge typically come to the bench as generalists. See Jack B.
Weinstein, Limits on Judges Learning, Speaking and Acting – Part I – Tentative
First Thoughts: How May Judges Learn?, 36 ARIZ. L. REV. 539, 540-41 (1994); see
also supra notes 115-117 and accompanying text. Of judges with business
experience, few have knowledge of a wide range of complex commercial practices. In
one recent study, more than two-thirds of business executives and in-house counsel
disagreed with the following statement: “the legal system generally considers the
needs and practices of particular business communities.” John Lande, Failing Faith
in Litigation? A Survey of Business Lawyers’ and Executives’ Opinions, 3 HARV.
NEG. L. REV. 1, 34-35 (1998). This study quoted one utility company executive as
saying, “Judges are trained in the law, not necessarily in the fundamentals of a
particular industry or avenue of commerce. They’re coached on fairness and
precedent and things like that. . . . For example, we have a number of disputes with
people who we transact with in a transmission grid. Well, that’s a very complex
engineering-econometric type of consideration where we use those mechanisms. It’s
just not the type of thing you want to bring to the courts.” Id. at 32. Private
adjudication can ameliorate these concerns by using industry specialists as
adjudicators.
158 See COOPER ET AL., supra note 149, at 232 (“For good or ill, however, parties
and arbitrators alike frequently refer to previous decisions. Parties usually do so in
the hope that previous awards will persuade the arbitrator of the merits of their
positions, not because they regard the awards as binding. Arbitrators usually do so
to justify their decisions.”).
159 “Each arbitrator there owes no more than ‘due regard’ to the decisions of
other arbitrators. Nor is there complete publication of awards. Those published form
only a small, and not necessarily representative, portion of the whole. Many parties
have no convenient access to the publishing services, and many parties forego the
use of lawyers who could discover and argue the pertinent precedents.” Id. at 233.
160 “Contractual language, evidence of the drafters’ intentions, and the parties’
past practices differ widely. The same words may mean different things in different
bargaining relationships. Factual contexts are usually unique.” Id.
161 The parties may select one arbitrator or select a tripartite panel with one or
two arbitrators selected by each party.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
35
arbitration.162 Late selection of an arbitrator may be advantageous,
because the parties can pick an arbitrator with current and particular
expertise related to the dispute. However, late selection inevitably
causes delay.163
The purported confidentiality benefits of private adjudication
may be offset by reductions in fairness and efficiency. Parties
involved in private adjudication generally relinquish the right of
appeal. There generally is no public record of private proceedings; in
fact, many commercial parties prefer private adjudication precisely
because it is a way of protecting themselves from negative
publicity.164 This protection may suit both parties, even the winner,
who otherwise might have been forced to disclose trade secrets or
negative information about its products or services during the
proceedings.165 Moreover, businesses involved in repeated judicial
determinations over time risk establishing negative precedents for
future cases; because private proceedings are not reported, even an
extremely negative result is unlikely to harm future litigation.166
When cases settle or are adjudicated through a private forum, there is
no body of reported cases.167 To the extent there is public disclosure
of private proceedings, such information is unlikely to be tracked,
memorialized, and stored.168
Both the courts and Congress seem to have made a decision to
divert business cases into arbitration to conserve judicial resources for
162 See id. at 18.
163 In a synthetic common law regime, the parties could both select and
constrain an appropriate arbitrator without creating delay.
164 See Judith Resnik, Failing Faith: Adjudicatory Procedure in Decline, 53 U.
CHI. L. REV. 494, 538 (1986).
165 In contrast, legal proceedings in courts are highly publicized, and even
relatively low-level proceedings are reported in specialty journals. Important events
during the proceedings are reflected quickly in the stock prices of publicly-traded
participants. In fact, there now exist sophisticated financial instruments allowing
private parties not involved in the litigation to bet on the outcome of particular
cases. For example, after the Supreme Court held that savings and loan institutions
could sue the U.S. government for breach of contract arising out of a governmental
change in the accounting treatment of goodwill for regulatory capital purposes, see
U.S. v. Winstar Corp., 518 U.S. 839 (1996), several plaintiffs, including Glendale
Federal and California Federal issued securities, known as Litigation Tracking
Warrants, whose return was based on the amount recovered in the suits against the
government. See Frank Partnoy, Betting on Suing (1999)
<http://www.lawnewsnetwork.com/opencourt/> (copy on file with the author).
166 The securities industry is an appropriate example. This industry created a
system of specialist arbitration for both investors and employees, in which
arbitrators are required to put their decisions in writing, but are not required to give
any reasons. See Bird v. Shearson Lehman/Am. Express, Inc., 926 F.2d 116, 124 (2d
Cir. 1991) (Kearse, J., dissenting). Securities arbitration is a hotly disputed topic.
The securities industry asserts that the move to arbitration makes everyone better off
because of reduced transaction costs. Numerous commentators counter that the
securities industry, with its expertise in repeat litigation and vast resources, is
taking advantage of individual employees and investors. See, e.g., Margaret A.
Jacobs & Michael Siconolfi, Losing Battles: Investors Fare Poorly Fighting Wall
Street – And May Do Worse, WALL ST. J., Feb. 8, 1995, at A1 (quoting one observer as
saying, “Christians had a better chance against the lions than many investors and
employees will have in the climate being created now.”).
167 See Owen M. Fiss, Against Settlement, 93 YALE L.J. 1073 (1984).
168 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 228 (citing Borzou Daragahi,
Environmental ADR: Demand for Arbitration Raises Practical Concerns, N.Y. L.J.,
Sept. 8, 1994, at 5).
36 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
other types of cases, particularly criminal, family law, and civil rights
cases.169 What is the consequence of having primarily only these
non-business cases left in the judicial system? They could be quite
serious. Many commentators are concerned that such a practice
would split dispute resolution into private courts for the “haves” and
public courts for the “have-nots,” in the same way many argue public
and private schools have been split.170
Mediation171 purports to provide benefits not available in a
confrontational proceeding, including both court and arbitration.172
On the other hand, the more mediation is used, the more it erodes
whatever precedential value exists in dispute resolution by judges or
arbitrators. If a large number of “normal” cases are resolved in
mediation, then those cases resolved in judicial and arbitral fora may
not reflect societal practice.173 Disputes resolved in mediation
typically are resolved confidentially, and therefore other parties are
denied all of the benefits associated with public resolution of decisions,
including a body of decisions to guide future practice.174 In this way,
mediation poses a more serious and specific version of the general
problem posed by the settlement of large numbers of cases.175
169 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 213-15 (detailing judicial and
legislative efforts to move business cases out of courts into ADR). For example, the
Supreme Court has permitted arbitration of federal securities law claims based on
contractual choice. See Rodriguez de Quijas v. Shearson/American Express, Inc., 490
U.S. 477 (1989); Shearson/American Express, Inc., v. McMahon, 482 U.S. 220 (1987).
170 See Carr & Jencks, supra note 56, at 231-33 (citing numerous
commentators). It certainly is the case that the direct cost of judging in private ADR
is greater than the cost of judging in a heavily-subsidized public judicial system;
for example, JAMS rent-a-judges charge fees ranging from $350 to $500 per hour.
See Richard C. Reuben, The Dark Side of ADR, CAL. LAW., Feb. 1994, at 55. Lisa
Bernstein has argued that compulsory ADR reduces the frequency of settlements and
increases costs to less wealthy parties. See Lisa Bernstein, Understanding the Limits
of Court-Connected ADR: ADR: A Critique of Federal Court-Annexed Arbitration
Programs, 141 U. PA. L. REV. 2169, 2216-30 (1993).
171 See J.B. Ruhl, Thinking of Mediation as a Complex Adaptive System, 1997
B.Y.U.L. REV. 777, 784 n.22 (1997) (discussion definition of mediation).
172 See, e.g., Jonathan R. Harkavy, Privatizing Workplace Justice: The Advent of
Mediation in Resolving Sexual Harassment Disputes, 34 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 135,
156 (“Mediation provides a comfortable forum for all parties and thus is more likely
to facilitate a workable resolution to a dispute than a more adversarial process
involving rights adjudicated in a formal setting under a fixed set of rules.”).
173 Jonathan Harkavy has made this point in the context of sexual harassment
dispute resolution: “Mediation may impair the orderly development of a coherent
sexual harassment jurisprudence. To the extent that it is successful in resolving
large numbers of disputes, the cases left for adjudication may involve such unique
factual situations that the resultant body of case law will be shaped – and possibly
warped – by mediation’s leftovers.” Harkavy, supra note 172, at 160.
174 For example, most mediated settlements of sexual harassment cases are
confidential. This confidentiality deprives the public of valuable information need
to answer important questions necessary to parties planning behavior, including:
what is the law, who is violating the law, and what are the costs of illegal conduct?
See Harkavy, supra note 172, at 163. Some scholars have argued that private interest
should at least sometimes prevail over the public interests in clarifying legal rules
through litigation. See Carrie Menkel-Meadow, Whose Dispute is it Anyway?: A
Philosophical and Democratic Defense of Settlement (in Some Cases), 83 GEO. L.J.
2663 (1995) (arguing that private interests in settling a case should be respected,
even when they are outweighed by the public interest in litigating the case).
175 The classic article posing these problems in the context of settlement is Fiss,
Against Settlement, supra note 167. In that article, Owen Fiss stated that
“[s]ettlement is for me the civil analogue of plea bargaining: Consent is often
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
37
As an example of how the current system of private adjudication
generates enormous uncertainty, consider the arbitration of securities
employment contracts. Securities firms generally require employees
to sign arbitration agreements, in order to opt into what the firms
regard as a lower-cost option to judicial resolution of employment
disputes. In fact, the arbitration of employment claims by securities
employees has not always worked out as the employers planned. In
several recent cases, New York Stock Exchange arbitration panels
have awarded employees multi-million-dollar bonuses, even though
the employees making the claims had been terminated for cause, and
notwithstanding the fact that prior practice in the industry was that
management awarded such bonuses at its discretion.176 These
arbitrations were not adjudicated based on rules known to either party
at the time of contracting; in fact, the rules by definition were
contrary to the expectations of at least one of the parties.
Because these arbitration decisions are unpublished and do not bind
future arbitrators, there is great uncertainty surrounding the
arbitration of securities employees’ bonus disputes. The result almost
certainly will be an increase in the filing of bonus-related claims, some
of which no doubt will succeed, many of which will be inconsistent,
and all of which will require the additional expenses of lawyer and
arbitration fees.
This evidence in the securities firm employee bonus context is
anecdotal, but there are general arguments indicating that similar
problems will persist in other areas of arbitration. Consider the
following hypothetical: First, suppose a judicial regime governs a
particular dispute. Every year for ten years there is a contract dispute
related to a particular type of contract. In each dispute, $1 million is
at stake. Suppose it costs each side $50,000 in legal fees to adjudicate
the dispute and it costs another $50,000 for the judge to hear the
case. If the facts of each case, each year, are precisely the same, once
the first case is decided, then all of the later cases will settle based on
the terms of the first case. For example, the judicial decision in the
coerced; the bargain may be struck by someone without authority; the absence of a
trial and judgment renders subsequent judicial involvement troublesome; and
although dockets are trimmed, justice may not be done.” Id. at 1075. Fiss argued
that certain types of disputes are especially inappropriate for arbitration, including:
(1) disputes where one party has disproportionate bargaining power or resources, (2)
disputes where settlement is difficult, (3) disputes where parties must be supervised
post-judgment, and (4) disputes where parties (and society) need an authoritative
interpretation of the law. Fiss’s argument has some relevance to the discussion of
derivatives disputes in Part V infra. Derivatives disputes arguably satisfy the first
and fourth criteria – often one party has an information or sophistication advantage
over the other party, and parties desperately need authoritative interpretation – but
may not satisfy the other criteria. In particular, settlement seems to be relatively
easy, at least compared to the prospects of costly and continued litigation, and
parties typically do not need to be supervised post-judgment. Therefore, some
derivatives disputes may be appropriate for arbitration, while others clearly would
not be.
176 See Randall Smith, Traders, Bankers Who Lost Jobs Amid Charges of
Wrongdoing Still Get Bonuses, WALL ST. J., July 19, 2000, at C1, C4 (describing
awards of $2 million, $2 million, $1.5 million, and $1.44 million). The securities
firms involved in these arbitrations were described as “taken aback” and one firm,
UBS Securities, sought to vacate an award in New York state court, although New
York Supreme Court Justice Carol E. Huff upheld the arbitrator’s award. See id. at
C4.
38 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
first case might be to split the $1 million equally. Such a decision
would mean it would cost a total of $150,000 (the costs of legal and
judicial fees in the first case) to resolve ten years of annual contract
disputes.
However, if the facts or legal arguments in later cases differ from
those in the first case, the cases may not settle. Assume that in each
later case the facts differ in such a way that each party believes it is
entitled to $600,000, or $100,000 more than was awarded in the first
case. Then it is in each party’s economic interest to litigate. That
means a judge will need to decide all 10 cases, at a total cost of
$150,000 per case, or $1.5 million. The efficiency of judicial dispute
resolution thus turns on the accuracy of the expectations of the
parties.
Now, suppose an arbitration regime governs the dispute. Note
that arbitration actually increases society’s overall costs. If the first
case is decided in arbitration, there is no guidance at all for future
cases, which would need to be adjudicated, even if the later cases were
factually similar. In other words, the total cost will be $1.5 million,
regardless of the accuracy of the expectations of the parties, because
the parties will not be able to rely on a published opinion.
Accordingly, even if the cost of arbitration were substantially less
than the cost of judicial review, arbitration might not be preferable.
The use of arbitration may be even more problematic when two
commercial parties contract ex ante for its use in a wide range of
potential future disputes involving other non-parties. For example,
Robert Kenagy has written about an agreement between Whirlpool
Corporation and State Farm Fire and Casualty Company to remove
subrogation177 disputes about damage to State Farm insureds caused by
Whirlpool products from court to arbitration.178 The agreement
committed any injured insureds to confidential arbitration with
streamlined discovery.179
Of course, Whirlpool and State Farm benefit from the agreement.
But at whose expense? Future claimants lose the ability to pursue a
judicial subrogation remedy if one of Whirlpool’s products harms
them (which, as the parties must have known, almost certainly would
occur; otherwise, there was no reason for the agreement). These are
parties who by definition cannot bargain because it is unknown in
advance who, if anyone, will suffer the harms. Nor is the extent of
the harms known. This is a classic externality example.
177 Subrogation has been defined as: “the equitable remedy by which, where the
property of one person is used to discharge a duty of another or a lien upon the
property of another, under such circumstances that the other will be unjustly
enriched by the retention of the benefit thus conferred, the former is placed in the
position of the obligee or lienholder.” RESTATEMENT OF SECURITY § 141, comment a,
at 383 (1941). In the insurance claims context, subrogation disputes typically occur
when an insured seeks recovery from a third party or third-party insurer after the
insured’s (first-party) insurer already has paid some compensation to the insured;
the first-party insurer then has a subrogation interest in the insured’s recover against
the third party or third-party insurer in the amount paid. See, e.g, Texas Farmers Ins.
Co. v. Seals, 948 S.W.2d 532 (2d Dist. Tex. 1997) (describing such a subrogation
dispute).
178 See Robert T. Kenagy, Whirlpool’s Search for Efficient and Effective Dispute
Resolutions, 59 ALB. L. REV. 895, 897-98 (1995).
179 Id. at 898. Importantly, the plaintiffs’ bar would be not privy to the
arbitration proceedings.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
39
Absent transaction costs, State Farm insureds might bargain for an
arbitration agreement, if that agreement would result in a lower cost
of insurance. Or Whirlpool might be willing to pay insureds enough
to compensate for any losses associated with committing to
arbitration. In other words, arbitration might, in aggregate, be
cheaper and fairer than judicial resolution. But is likely that such
payments would occur (i.e., that agreement would have been reached)
when transaction costs are very high? There is no evidence that the
value of the Whirlpool-State Farm agreement was included in the
price of the insurance contract offered to insureds.180
Private adjudication is used in business cases, but often for reasons
unrelated to the fairness or efficiency of the alternative systems. It is
increasingly costly and uncertain, and may not serve the public
interest because of the external costs to non-parties. Often, it does
not even satisfy the businesses opting in without recourse to appeal.
Private adjudication is perhaps the worst of several evils.
IV. A PROPOSAL: SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
The current systems of public and private adjudication of disputes
are not the only alternatives. A synthetic common law system is a
blend of the other systems, and resolves many of the problems in
each. In Learned Hand’s terms, synthetic common law enables
parties to build their own coral reefs. This Part describes the
synthetic common law system in greater detail, and explains when and
why it likely would obtain advantages over the other systems.
Here, in greater detail, is how a synthetic common law regime
would work. Private synthetic law associations would be
established,181 consisting of experts in individual fields of law, perhaps
including law professors.182 Those associations would publish menus
of cases. The cases would involve simplified facts in particular areas
of practice and would focus on the issues that, in the judgment of the
association (and of parties who would choose that association), most
likely would arise in future disputes. The cases could include published
state and federal cases, or examples based on such cases, or even
stylized versions of such cases with certain facts changed or omitted.
Numerous associations would compete for a particular contract.
Private parties might simply list, or check a box for, cases they
selected to govern disputes under the contract.
The association would then commit to resolve disputes based on
those cases. The association might describe, or even commit to, its
anticipated mode or process of reasoning in any future dispute.183
The reputation of the association over time would be based on the
extent to which it was able to keep its commitments. The association
could incorporate information gleaned from actual cases it adjudicated
into new synthetic common law for future parties to choose.
180 See id.
181 These would be for-profit associations, established with a view to earning
income both by providing synthetic common law cases ex ante and by adjudicating
disputes ex post.
182 Writing synthetic cases would be similar to writing comments on proposed
legislation or even final examination questions, areas in which law professors have
expertise.
183 Parties might also specify ex ante the cost or rate structure for adjudication,
and might list acceptable adjudicators.
40 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Associations would compete for business over time. As with
arbitration, courts would have limited review of association
judgments.184
From the perspective of private parties, synthetic common law
would be no more complex ex ante than arbitration. Parties would
simply select an association to adjudicate their disputes, and then
select from that association’s menu of cases a particular set of cases
to govern their contract. The association would adjudicate any
disputes based on the selected menu of cases, and the selected mode of
legal reasoning, if applicable.
A schematic diagram is illustrative:
184 See supra note 146.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
41
Note that synthetic common law is a hybrid of common law and
the alternatives to common law.185 It contains some of the public
aspects of common law and statutory law (e.g., limited judicial review,
real common law cases forming the basis for synthetic cases included
on a particular menu), as well as non-governmental aspects of private
law and private adjudication (e.g., synthetic common law associations
are private entities). Synthetic common law also involves both ex
ante and ex post specification of legal rules: the governing legal rules
(e.g., cases) are specified ex ante, as they are in statutory and private
law, whereas the results in particular cases are decided ex post, as in
common law or private adjudication. Synthetic common law draws
advantages from each, as described below.
Common Law
In certain areas, a synthetic common regime might better
accomplish both of the goals of common law. It could enable a
private adjudicator to resolve parties’ disputes in a fair and efficient
manner, while generating at lower cost a supply of legal rules that
reflect social practice.
First, unlike common law, synthetic common law cases need not
evolve over time in order to reflect social practice. Advocates of
common law laud the case or controversy requirement, and the
purported efficiencies derived from having judges adjudicate only real
cases involving real parties with real disputes. It is undeniably true
that some filter works to limit those disputes percolating from real
disagreements among private actors up to real judicial opinions. But a
filter works to limit synthetic cases, too, and that filter does not
depend on the potentially abnormal behavior of parties other than
the contracting parties. Real cases and controversies are often based
on disputes in which parties are behaving in an economically
irrational manner. Numerous real cases are litigated because one or
more parties misperceive either the probability of recovery, the
likelihood of victory, or both. Most importantly, the case or
185 Figure 2 is simply Figure 1 plus synthetic common law.
Private
Public
Ex PostEx Ante
Statutory Law Common Law
Private Adjudication Private Law
Figure 2
Synthetic
Common Law
42 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
controversy filter is incredibly costly. The synthetic common law
filter costs very little.186
Synthetic common law likely would be fairer than common law,
because it would avoid judicial temptation to create new law.187 The
value of common law rules depends on their consistency (i.e., cases
that are consistent with each other) and stability over time (i.e., the
“stickiness” of precedent).188 Synthetic common law, because it is
created all at once, is far more likely than common law to be
consistent. Moreover, because synthetic common law cases will not
change, absent agreement of the parties, during the life of the
contract, they are guaranteed to be stable over time.
Thus, synthetic common law could achieve one of the primary
aims of the common law: “enabling private actors, within limits, to
determine before they enter into a transaction the legal rules –
including the ‘new’ legal rules – that will govern the transaction if a
dispute should arise.”189 Private actors need a replicable process so
they will not be insecure in planning future actions.190 To the extent
common law is not replicable, as it often is not, it cannot achieve this
aim. In contrast, synthetic common law by definition is replicable
because the rules selected by the parties cannot change during the life
of the contract, regardless of the views of particular judges. Synthetic
common law eliminates the possibility that prospective overrulings191
or transformative192 rulings by judges will change the law relevant to
any dispute between the parties. It avoids the difficulty of overruling
or overturning a decision, which in a common law regime requires a
judge to construct an elaborate justification.193 In contrast, under
synthetic common law, private parties can avoid a bad case simply by
not checking that particular box.
Melvin Eisenberg, one of the leading scholars of common law, has
summed up his view of the common law as follows: “What then does
the common law consist of? It consists of the rules that would be
generated at the present moment by application of the institutional
principles of adjudication.”194 By this definition, synthetic common
law arguably is superior to common law. Synthetic common law cases
always are created “at the present moment” – the moment when the
contract is executed, when the parties are determining what rights
should govern any future disputes – whereas common law cases may
not reflect the expectations of the parties at that crucial time.
186 In a competitive market for synthetic common law organizations, one
organization is unlikely to have market power. The marginal cost of synthetic
common law is likely to be low; it involves only a few people spending a relatively
small amount of time writing cases.
187 See EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 35 (discussing problem of judges creating
new legal rights after the event relevant to the dispute).
188 See id. at 44, 46.
189 Id at 11.
190 See id. at 48.
191 See id. at 127-32 (describing judicial decisions affecting transactions
comparable to the one being adjudicated that occurred before the decision but
remain open to legal challenge).
192 See id. at 132 (describing judicial process of transforming cases, including
the example of Justice Cardozo’s radical reconstruction of precedents to reach a
particular result).
193 See id. Ch. 7.
194 Id. at 154.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
43
Synthetic common law avoids the tragedy of the commons
critique of common law, because the (very low) costs are internalized
by the parties. To the extent there is a public goods problem in a
synthetic common law regime, it is likely to be far less serious than
the problem under common law. It would cost drafters creating
synthetic cases only a fraction of the costs of litigating similar cases.
Scholars who advocate regulatory competition should prefer
synthetic common law, because it adds competing options to parties
who currently can only choose which state (or federal) law to have
govern their contract. The number of competing synthetic common
law regimes is virtually unlimited. Competition among synthetic
common law associations would eliminate problems associated with
the common law mode of legal reasoning.195 Successful associations
would develop reputations for deciding cases using a particular mode
of reasoning; they might even advertise a particular type of legal
reasoning methodology (e.g., reason like Holmes would have, err on
the side of stability and consistency, decide our case like Dworkin
believes judges decide cases). Alternatively, private parties could
request particular modes of reasoning, and only associations agreeing
in advance to provide such modes would obtain their business.
Scholars who abhor regulatory competition nevertheless need to
recognize the possibility of synthetic common law regimes, and
explain why parties should not adopt them. Even if choice of law is a
race-to-the-bottom, choice of synthetic law might not be, because to
the extent there is information asymmetry or other market failure
leading to unfair bargains in choice of law, synthetic common law
levels the playing field by laying bare in narrative form the effects of
particular contractual provisions.
To the extent the justification for common law is its evolutionary
process, synthetic common law better takes advantage of that
process. Synthetic cases can evolve over time; the major difference is
a certain amount of “genetic engineering” taking place while the first
regime is created.
Synthetic common law also could generate a superior body of
legal rules. Although ardent legal positivists may not agree that
synthetic common law is composed of actual legal rules, the argument
that synthetic common law is based on such rules is much stronger
than the corresponding argument for common law.196 Common law-
style rules (including synthetic common law rules) enjoy their status
as “law,” not because they are posited sets of rules, but because parties
continue to accept them. Such acceptance is more likely in a
synthetic common law regime, which necessarily requires that parties
approve of applicable legal rules, than it is in a traditional common
law regime, which limits choices to existing regimes and does not
require that parties make an explicit choice about particular cases that
will govern a dispute. Although the common law is said to “lack[] an
authoritative authentic text”197 and “to develop and apply principles
that have never been committed to any authentic form of words,”198
synthetic common law carries greater weight as text because the
195 See EDWARD LEVI, AN INTRODUCTION TO LEGAL REASONING (1948).
196 See supra Part II.B.
197 Simpson, supra note 65, at 16.
198 F. POLLOCK, A FIRST BOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE 249 (3d ed. 1911).
44 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
parties explicitly agree to the words contained in the cases specified in
advance; under common law, the legal rules in the cases are specified
ex post.
To the extent common law is flexible, synthetic law is at least as
flexible. The parties could choose whatever cases they would like to
include in a particular contract, including existing common law cases.
The parties could specify the process of adjudication, including
“sticky” adherence to precedent, and could even indicate how they
would like a judge to reason.
Whereas common law in the U.S. now performs poorly in
generating a public record of legal rules, for the various reasons
analyzed in Part II.B.2., synthetic common law guarantees an
adequate number of on-point cases. If the parties do not believe the
cases cover a specific point, they can change or add a case. Many of
the arguments offered in favor of common law adjudication depend on
the assumption that a large number and wide variety of opinions will
be published.199 Synthetic common law achieves this assumed
objective better than common law does.
Similarly, common law may be uncertain if parties are able to
construct large numbers of plausible rules from a given precedent.200
Precedents often follow unstable, “jagged” paths, zigging and zagging
until a judge or commentator is able to synthesize the results in
existing cases. This synthesis typically requires explaining the cases
while recognizing the prior legal rule.201 A synthetic common law
regime would simply clarify the cases to eliminate such ambiguity.
In difficult areas of commercial law, where some cases may seem
irreconcilable even after years of legal commentary,202 parties using
synthetic common law could reconcile such difficult cases simply by
deleting problematic sections. Hard cases may be useful, even fun for
law professors and students, but private parties likely will not find the
intellectual challenge of such precedents, as originally written, to be
worth their commercial while. In common law cases, a party often
must show that the rule of a precedent is not in conflict with a
particular decision.203 In a synthetic common law regime, there is no
such need, and consequently synthetic common law regimes can avoid
costs related to such showings. If a particular passage in a case seems
troubling or confusing, the parties could simply delete it.
The key point is that synthetic common law provides
information that both (1) is not reflected in current precedent, and
may contradict precedent; and (2) would not with certainty lead every
judge to the principle articulated by the parties. Synthetic common
law would not require parties to specify all contingencies, or to list the
199 Many pro-common law arguments depend upon the publication of opinions.
See id. at 42.
200 See EISENBERG, supra note 2, at 63.
201 Examples of such synthesis have involved major figures in law. For
example, the reliance principle in contract law was first explicitly formulated in
Section 90 of the Restatement (First) of Contracts, authored principally by Samuel
Williston; the modern principle of unconscionability was first formulated in Article
2 of the UCC, authored principally by Karl Llewellyn; and the principle of strict
product liability was first explicitly formulated in Section 401A of the Restatement
(Second) of Torts, authored principally by William Prosser. See id. at 78-79
(describing justifications for each example).
202 See id. at 61, 64, 97.
203 See id. at 62.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
45
many possible iterations of changes in a variable. Rather, synthetic
common law would ask the parties to articulate the cases they would
want a future adjudicator to use in a future dispute about some, but not
all, facts that the parties anticipated.204 Of course, judges in common
law judges today can reason based on hypothetical facts or cases, but
synthetic common law is preferable to common law reasoning from
hypotheticals, because the parties can specify the relevant
hypotheticals ex ante, and need not attempt to anticipate a future
judge’s reasoning.205
I am not saying that synthetic common law always will be
superior to common law. In fact, it might be superior only in
particular areas of law. In the vast majority of cases, both synthetic
common law and common law are largely irrelevant, because most
parties do not know the law and instead make plans implicitly, not
explicitly (i.e., they do not consider specific legal consequences).206
Synthetic common law, to the extent it is more specific than
common law, may alarm one of the parties and thereby “queer the
deal.” Many aspects of contracting are uncertain ex ante and
therefore cannot be specified in words, whether those words are
contract terms or fake cases.207 Synthetic common law may not
carry the authority of the “rule of law,”208 not only because it would
be privately administered, but because it assumes there is not a fixed
rule of law ex ante. Notwithstanding these flaws, my argument is that
for some parties synthetic common law could be fairer and more
efficient than common law.
Statutory Law
Second, a synthetic common law regime could be superior to a
statutory regime. To the extent statutory law is inferior to common
law, as a number of recent studies have indicated, synthetic common
law should provide the same types of economic benefits as common
law. Societies with a history of common law (e.g., the United States
and England) would find it relatively easy to shift to synthetic
common law in certain areas without a loss of economic benefits.209
In at least some cases, a synthetic common law system would
achieve the primary purported advantage of statutes: clarity. If the
applicable statute is clear, there would be no need for synthetic
common law, and the parties would not choose to use it. However,
the reality is that many statutes are unclear or limited, and require
interpretation through hypotheticals or some other form of
adjudication. If a statute is not clear, private parties could specify in
fake cases how the judges of their imagination would resolve the
ambiguities. Cases could include excerpts of the relevant statutes,
existing or proposed, if such inclusion would make the cases clearer.
204 See id. at 86.
205 See id. at 99.
206 See id. at 157.
207 See id. at 158 (asserting, without justification, that “the greater part of the
common law, although not certain, is nevertheless sufficiently determinate for
planning purposes”).
208 See F.A. HAYEK, THE ROAD TO SERFDOM 72 (1944) (describing importance of
government “being bound by rules fixed and announced beforehand”).
209 See supra note 3.
46 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Consequently, synthetic cases could achieve, at minimum, that level
of clarity already achieved by a statute.
In addition, synthetic common law could achieve some of the
benefits of democratically selected statutes. The information
impounded in a set of synthetic common law cases is more likely to
reflect the expectations of the parties than any statute. None of the
noise associated with the legislative process pollutes the legal rules in
synthetic common law. Because the cases more likely reflect the
parties’ expectations, they are more likely to be fair and efficient.
Synthetic common law also avoids the problem of statutes
reflecting the popular will of a prior electorate, not the current one.
In areas where technologies are rapidly changing, synthetic common
law can change, too. Alternatively, parties can anticipate change and
build it into cases.
In at least some instances, private parties will be able to assess
contingencies relevant to future disputes in individual cases better
than legislators will. Although legislators are democratically elected,
they may have been elected by parties with different interests and
preferences than the contracting parties. Synthetic common law
avoids the public choice and interest group pressures of legislation.
Cases are influenced only by the choices of the parties and the
availability of synthetic common law regimes.
Synthetic common law may not be superior to statutes, in every
area, or even in very many areas. In some areas of practice, the
democratic process works effectively, and statutory rules will best
reflect overall societal preferences. In relatively simple contracts,
statutes may be reasonably clear, and developing synthetic common
law may be too costly.
Finally, to the extent narrative is important to assist parties in
understanding the legal rules governing their contract, synthetic
common law has obvious advantages. Statutes may enable parties
with superior information to obtain an advantage in bargaining. The
narrative aspects of synthetic common law might help to level the
playing field for disadvantaged parties. For evenly-matched parties,
explaining the legal rules governing their contract in narrative form
may improve their ability to specify contingencies ex ante, a wealth-
improving result.
Private Law
Third, a synthetic common law regime also may be superior to a
regime of model acts and private law. Model acts suffer from the
same weaknesses as statutes. The only true difference between a
model act and a statute is that a model act front-loads most of the
work onto commentators who consider various proposals carefully
before the legislative process begins. Model acts take force only when
adopted as statutes.
Private law avoids some of these problems, because it derives its
authority from the fact that the parties agree to include it in their
contracts. Private law has expanded greatly in recent years, due in
part to the recent arguments of law and economics scholars that
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
47
private law is efficient. To some extent, existing private law regimes
offer the same advantages of synthetic common law.210
There are, however, several differences between private law and
synthetic common law, and these differences highlight the reasons
why synthetic common law would be superior in particular cases.
Private law is essentially private statutory law, and therefore suffers
from a lack of clarity and completeness. It is very difficult to specify
in advance the variety of factors relevant to any future dispute.
Clarity is just as elusive in complex contracts as it is in complex
statutes. Private law does not obtain any benefits of analogical
reasoning.
Why can’t lawyers and other parties create private default terms
with sufficient specificity? As noted above, private default terms and
standard form contracts are analytically equivalent to model acts and
uniform private laws, the primary difference being the intended
audience. While the former is directed to private parties engaging in
contracting, the latter is directed more generally to legislators. All
such private law offers the benefits of considered judgment of non-
governmental actors.
Moreover, although private law may serve to guide practice
absent a dispute, the parties will need to specify the means of
resolving a dispute. The choices are courts or private adjudication,
each based on the language in the private law. Therefore, even if
private parties can draft an ideal private contract, they are subject to
the interpretation of a judge or arbitrator in a future case. More
likely, the parties will not be able to, or even attempt to, specify all
contingencies. Even the various Restatements of the Laws include
short case examples explaining how particular statutory provisions
would work in practice.
For parties who prefer narrative to contract terms, private law
may be inferior to synthetic common law. Synthetic common law is
more likely to level the playing field between parties, especially for
consumers and purchasers who do not read contracts because the costs
of reading them exceed the benefits. Synthetic cases are less costly
(i.e., painful) to read, and may generate additional benefits if parties
are able to understand and intuit their implications more easily than
they would be able to formulate hypotheticals based on contract
language, even if a contract were clear. If contracts were written in
terms of synthetic cases, the bargain over contract terms might be
more party-to-party than lawyer-to-lawyer.
As a result, lawyers may have a vested interest in supporting
private law over synthetic common law. Contract lawyers have been
trained in, and have acquired, a particular skill: drafting complex
contracts that specify many often-related contingencies. This is
difficult work. Many non-lawyers find such contracts difficult to read,
and would find them impossible to draft. However, few contract
lawyers have developed the skill of writing or interpreting synthetic
cases. Even if synthetic common law were superior to private law,
lawyers might oppose the synthetic regime for self-interested reasons.
210 One difference between the regimes is that private contract terms typically do
not refer to an adjudication association, although there is no principled reason why
they could not be enforced by private associations in the same way synthetic
common law would be.
48 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Private Adjudication
Fourth, a synthetic common law regime could capture many of
the benefits of private dispute resolution while avoiding many of its
costs. First, a synthetic common law regime is essentially a form of
private adjudication. The major differences are increased competition
among regimes, and the addition of synthetic cases. Therefore,
synthetic common law would achieve many of the benefits of existing
forms of private adjudication.
Synthetic common law could avoid some of the problems
associated with the private nature of ADR and mediation. All of the
synthetic cases would be known to the parties. To the extent parties
valued additional decisions, they could pressure associations to include
those real decisions in future menus of cases. Nevertheless, there
would be some externality costs to non-parties, although those costs
might not be as high to the extent non-parties learn of the
contractual arrangement and read the synthetic cases.
Most importantly, synthetic common law would avoid the
arbitrary nature of private adjudication. There are few constraints on
private adjudicators, and they are notoriously difficult to predict. In
some areas, arbitration has not reflected the ex ante understandings of
the contracting parties.211
Finally, to the extent parties prefer private adjudication to court
because of the psychological benefits, as some studies have
indicated,212 synthetic common law also could achieve those results.
In fact, parties might even achieve some satisfaction ex ante from
expressing in narrative form their expectations regarding future
disputes. Moreover, private adjudication creates an adverse selection
problem for judicial opinions, because as normal cases are resolved in
arbitration or mediation, the body of disputes available to judges
writing published opinions is not representative. Because parties
involved in a synthetic common law regime have expressed their
views about future cases ex ante, they may be less likely to perceive
that a court would adjudicate their case differently, thereby avoiding
the adverse selection problem. To the extent the problem continues,
because parties contracting in a synthetic common law regime rely on
synthetic cases, not judicial opinions, the problem will not be
relevant.
V. USING SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW IN DERIVATIVES DISPUTES
This Part analyzes how synthetic common law would work in a
particular context: the resolution of disputes involving financial
derivatives.213 If Oliver Wendell Holmes were alive today, he surely
211 See supra note 176 and accompanying text (discussing securities arbitration
bonus awards that conflicted with expectations).
212 See, e.g., Tyler, supra note 49, at 102.
213 Disputes in the derivatives market provide an excellent opportunity to
compare the viability of common law and the various alternatives to common law.
As shown in the previous subpart, ex ante attempts to cure the uncertainty in the
derivatives market, through detailed statutes and extensive private law, have failed.
This section considers the problems associated with common law attempts to resolve
the disputes ex post and thereby create certainty. By and large, the common law, too,
has failed.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
49
would want to decide – or at least to write about – disputes involving
the multi-trillion market for over-the-counter (OTC) financial
derivatives.214 Holmes was interested in the major conflicts of his
day, in the influences of technology and scientific progress, and – as
he often is quoted – in experience over logic.215 To a judge such as
Holmes, the temptations of derivatives disputes would be
overwhelming: hard-fought, novel claims involving leaders of industry
and billions of dollars; breathtaking innovation and complexity
underlying the relationships of the parties; and, above all, the kind of
logic-defying real-world experience that Holmes believed defined the
substance of the law.216 Most importantly, the jurisprudence of
derivatives disputes is a tabula rasa, available for a bold, intelligent
jurist to make his or her mark.
Unfortunately, the judges thus far presented with OTC derivatives
claims have, to put it charitably, not been of Holmes’s statute. Judges
have shied from deciding any core issues in these cases, either because
they fear the effects of an off-the-mark precedent or because they are
overwhelmed by the detail and complexity of the cases. Although the
OTC derivatives market is among the largest markets in the world and
is chock full of disputes, judges only rarely have decided even narrow
issues in derivatives disputes, and they almost never write detailed
opinions.217 The vast majority of cases settle before trial in most
areas of law, but the derivatives area is striking for the near total
absence of judicial opinions and decided cases on important issues.
Only one derivatives claim ever has been tried,218 and that trial was a
decade ago, well before the recent waves of derivatives disputes. Only
a handful of disputes have led to judicial opinions on dispositive
motions.
The trepidation of a judge facing a derivatives dispute is
understandable. The financial instruments underlying the disputes are
complex and the relationships among parties and transactions are
In an earlier article, I suggested that society would be better served by ex post
rules in the derivatives industry that ex ante rules, which parties would contract
around through regulatory arbitrage transactions. See Partnoy, Regulatory
Arbitrage, supra note 5, at #. This article extends that argument by supplying the
means (synthetic common law) by which ex post evaluation of cases could generate
efficient and fair legal rules.
214 Financial derivatives are financial instruments whose value is based on, or
derived from, some other underlying instrument or index. See id. at 216-26
(describing classes and uses of derivatives). As of year-end 1999, the size of the
derivatives market was estimated at more than $100 trillion. See supra note 5. Over-
the-counter financial derivatives are those not traded on any exchange.
215 HOLMES, THE COMMON LAW, supra note 14, at 5.
216 Holmes’s attempt to present “a general view of the Common Law” recognized
the importance of both history and current practice: “The substance of the law at any
given time pretty nearly corresponds, so far as it goes, with what is then understood
to be convenient; but its form and machinery, and the degree to which it is able to
work out desired results, depend very much upon its past.” Id.
217 A rare exception is the opinion by Judge Feikens in Procter & Gamble Co. v.
Banker Trust Co., 925 F. Supp. 1270 (S.D. Ohio 1996), which considered multiple
claims in detail. Ironically, Judge Feikens, in Ohio, was interpreting New York state
law, and the New York state courts subsequently have rejected a portion of his
opinion with little analytical support or explanation. See infra at notes 353-356
and accompanying text.
218 To my knowledge, the only trial in a derivatives case was the one reviewed in
BankAtlantic v. PaineWebber, Inc., 955 F.2d 1467 (11th Cir. 1992); see discussion
infra at notes 444-445 and accompanying text.
50 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
difficult to understand.219 Some judges might find unraveling such a
case to be impossible. Moreover, any decision likely would have vast
repercussions, potentially affecting trillions of dollars of transactions.
No judge wants to be accused of bringing down a market, especially in
New York, where many derivatives disputes are filed.
Eventually, one or more emboldened judges may write definitive
opinions in the area; meanwhile, there is little or no judicial guidance.
The situation is dire. Private parties continue to contract (or not) in
a regime of enormous legal uncertainty.
This Part argues that a synthetic common law system could
eliminate much of that uncertainty. I begin by explaining briefly the
challenges associated with deciding derivatives disputes: the
complexity of the instruments themselves, the difficulties associated
with regulatory arbitrage, and the problems associated with attempting
to regulate only a subset of an economically equivalent class of
financial instruments. Then, I assess how the four regulatory
alternatives described in Parts II and III have fared in the derivatives
area. The short answer: not well. Historically, statutes have played
the most prominent role, so I begin there. Because participants in the
OTC derivatives market have opted out of most of these statutory
schemes, most securities and commodities statutes are of little
relevance to OTC derivatives disputes. Next, I assess the relative
small number of derivatives disputes that have been litigated in court.
Interestingly, because statutory claims are not relevant to the OTC
derivatives market, state common law claims are at the core of these
disputes. Finally, I consider the bounds of private law and arbitration,
which play a limited role in the area.
In Part V.C., I explain how a synthetic common law regime could
be a superior method of dispute resolution. I also suggest a specific
menu of synthetic common law cases that could eliminate some of
the uncertainty in these markets. In Part V.D., I analyze some
institutional barriers to adopting synthetic common law.
A. Line-Drawing in the Derivatives Market
Derivatives are notoriously difficult to categorize. Part of the
problem is the ambiguous meaning of the term “derivative.” The
definition typically220 given by legal academics and commentators in
the area is not particularly helpful: a derivative is a financial
instrument whose value is based on (or “derived” from) some
underlying instrument or index.221 According to this definition,
nearly all financial instruments are derivatives.222
In more precise economic terms, derivatives include two basic
classes of instruments: options and forwards. Both are financial
219 Because parties often use Special Purpose Vehicles, subsidiaries, off-shore
partnerships and corporations, and other intermediaries, it often is difficult to
discern the true counterparties to a particular transaction, a fact some derivatives
sellers have attempted to use to distance themselves from purchasers.
220 The popular definition is not used by regulators, who define derivatives in
increasingly obtuse and nonsensical ways. See infra Part V.B.
221 See, e.g., Partnoy, Regulatory Arbitrage, supra note 5, at 211, 216.
222 Even stocks and bonds can be thought of as derivatives. See Fisher Black &
Myron S. Scholes, The Pricing of Options and Corporate Liabilities, 8 J. POL. ECON.
(1973) (first describing equity as a call option).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
51
contracts, the primary difference being that options are “rights,”
whereas forwards also include “obligations.”223
For example, a call option is the right to buy some underlying
instrument at a specified time and price.224 An investor might
purchase a call option on IBM stock with an exercise price of $100
and an exercise date of one year from today. Such an investor would
have the right, but not the obligation, to buy IBM stock during the
next year for $100. If the price of IBM increased, the value of the
call option also would increase. If after one year, the price of IBM
were below $100, the option would expire worthless.
In contrast, a forward is the right and the obligation to buy or sell
some underlying instrument at a specified time and price. A baker
might buy a forward contract on a bushel of wheat with a forward
price of $100 and a delivery date of one year from today. In this
case, if the value of the wheat increased, the baker would make money
on the forward contract, and these gains would offset the increase in
the cost of the higher-priced wheat. Conversely, if the value of the
wheat decreased, the baker would lose money on the forward contract,
but these losses would be offset by gains associated with buying lower-
priced wheat.
There are additional complexities to derivatives.225 The
purchaser of the call option in the previous example could purchase
the option either through an exchange or from another private
party.226 Similarly, the baker could purchase a forward contract
either though an exchange (in which case it would be called a future)
or from another private party. In addition, the simple examples of
options and forwards can be combined in all sorts of complicated and
fantastic ways.227 Many derivatives are off-balance sheet, and thus
escape scrutiny.228
223 See Frank Partnoy, Adding Derivatives to the Corporate Law Mix, 34 GA. L.
REV. # (2000).
224 Whereas a call option is the right to buy, a put option is the right to sell. For
a detailed and colorful description of the various option payouts, including
diagrams, see Peter H. Huang, Teaching Corporate Law from an Options Perspective,
34 GA. L. REV. 571 (2000).
225 The existence of derivatives means that traditional financial market labels –
such as “equity” and “debt” – are now meaningless. For example, suppose a
particular legal rule applies only to the “equity” of a firm. Examples include the
duties of care and loyalty, which the managers of a firm generally owe to the firm’s
shareholders (e.g., equity), but not to the firm’s other stakeholders (e.g., debt).
However, what constitutes “equity” may vary from firm to firm in ways that make the
legal rules inconsistent. See Partnoy, Corporate Law Mix, supra note 223, at #.
226 The private transaction is classified as over-the-counter (OTC).
227 For examples of exotic derivatives, and the complexities of the valuation
issues associated with them, see PAUL WILMOTT, FINANCIAL DERIVATIVES 34-41 (2000).
Even complex combinations of options and forwards may not create “complete”
markets. See Peter H. Huang, A Normative Analysis of New Financially Engineered
Derivatives, 73 S. CAL. L. REV. 471, 498-500 (2000). More complex derivatives
generally are more profitable for the derivatives dealers who sell them. See, e.g.,
STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 160 (“More complicated products are more profitable and
therefore more attractive to dealers.”).
Financier George Soros has expressed unease about the dangers in complex
aspects of the derivatives market: “The explosive growth in derivative instruments
holds other dangers. There are so many of them, and some of them are so esoteric,
that the risks involved may not be properly understood even by the most
sophisticated of investors. Some of these instruments appear to be specifically
designed to enable institutional investors to take gambles which they would
52 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
In the option example, the investor was using derivatives to
speculate on the price of IBM stock. In the forward example, the
baker was using derivatives to hedge the risk of an increase in the cost
of wheat. Speculating and hedging are two of the primary uses of
derivatives.229
A third use of derivatives – arbitrage, including regulatory
arbitrage – presents additional difficulties. True arbitrage is the
simultaneous, riskless purchase and sale of economically equivalent
instruments for profit. True arbitrage rarely exists, but derivatives
frequently are used to make arbitrage-like bets that economically
similar instruments will converge in price. These bets are variously
known as risk arbitrage, convergence trades, or relative value trades.
A particular type of arbitrage, regulatory arbitrage, involves the
use of derivatives to avoid costly regulation. Regulatory arbitrage
involves purchases and sales of financial instruments designed to
capture the difference in regulatory costs applicable to two
economically equivalent assets.230 Private parties often use
derivatives for regulatory arbitrage, a fact that makes the job of
defining derivatives more difficult, especially for regulators, because
to the extent a regulatory cost is imposed on a class of instruments,
there is an incentive for market participants to create economically
equivalent derivative assets that avoid the regulatory cost.
Disputes in the financial market have involved all three uses of
derivatives. The disputes have occurred in waves, typically after
some major economic dislocation (e.g., an increase in interest rates or
dramatic change in foreign exchange rates) causes market participants
to sustain losses large enough to lead them to sue. Not all derivatives
losses are relevant here. 231 An early round of derivatives losses,
which led to the first major wave of derivatives cases, followed soon
after when the Federal Reserve increased interest rates six times in
early 1994.232 Another wave followed the Asia crisis of 1997, when
several Asian currency collapsed.233
otherwise not be permitted to take. . . . And some other instruments offer exceptional
returns because they carry the seeds of a total wipeout.” GEORGE SOROS, SOROS ON
SOROS 313 (1995).
228 See STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 159 (describing off-balance sheet treatment
and noting that for major commercial banks, including Chase Manhattan and
Morgan Guaranty, the notional value of off-balance sheet derivatives represents 40
to 50 times the value of their balance sheet assets).
229 See, e.g., Kimberly D. Krawiec, Derivatives, Corporate Hedging, and
Shareholder Wealth: Modigliani-Miller Forty Years Later, 1998 U. ILL. L. REV. 1039
(1998) (hedging); Lynn A. Stout, Betting the Bank: How Derivatives Trading Under
Conditions of Uncertainty Can Increase Risks and Erode Returns in Financial
Markets, 21 J. CORP. L. 53 (1995) (speculating).
230 See generally Partnoy, Regulatory Arbitrage, supra note 5. For example, a
simple regulatory arbitrage transaction would be buying an untaxed asset and
selling an economically equivalent taxed asset.
231 For example, although one publicized case, involving billion-dollar losses
by Nicholas Leeson of Barings Bank, has raised numerous regulatory and policy
issues about derivatives, but because the Barings losses did not involve a dispute
between the purchaser and seller of the financial contracts, the Barings losses are not
relevant here. It is worth noting, however, that in December 1995 a Singapore court
sentenced Nick Leeson to six and a half years in prison, for fraud and for falsifying
certain reports sent to SIMEX, the relevant exchange in Singapore. See Bennett &
Marin, supra note 305, at 5.
232 These increases followed an extended period during which short-term U.S.
interest rates had remained very low. During that period, many market participants
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
53
Before 1994, numerous companies throughout the world had
purchased derivatives contracts, including swap transactions, that
essentially were bets that short-term rates would remain low. There
were numerous ways to place this bet using derivatives. The most
straightforward way would have been either to enter into a simple
interest rate option or forward contract,234 betting that rates would
not increase. Another would have been to enter into a simple U.S.
dollar interest rate swap, pursuant to which the company would agree
to pay a short-term floating interest rate and to receive a fixed
interest rate, each as a percentage of some fixed, notional amount.
For example, if in 1993 Procter & Gamble had believed interest
rates would remain low (or if it had wanted to convert fixed rate
liabilities into floating rate liabilities), it could have entered into an
interest rate swap transaction with Bankers Trust, agreeing to pay
every three months a short-term floating interest rate (e.g., LIBOR,
the London Inter-Bank Offered Rate) times $100 million and to
receive, say, 5 percent times $100 million, or $5 million. Then, if
interest rates remained low, P&G would make money every quarter on
its swap; if interest rates increased, it might lose money.
Such swaps, known as “plain vanilla” interest rate swaps are very
common, are relatively low risk, and are transacted in a competitive,
transparent market. Unfortunately for the banks brokering such
swaps, the large size and competitive nature of that market means
that such swaps are a relatively unattractive low-margin business. The
greatest growth in derivatives has been in swaps and other OTC
derivatives, where “plain vanilla” trades have become less profitable
in recent years.235
However, derivatives disputes, especially those involving large
well-publicized losses, typically do not involve these simple financial
contracts. Instead, they more often involve more complex swaps and
structured transactions, which are neither liquid nor transparent, and
which generate very large profits for dealers.
In sum, although derivatives are difficult to categorize, derivatives
disputes typically have involved transactions that were both more
complex on average for the purchaser and more profitable on average
to the seller. Frequently, these transactions were composed of
several, simpler parts, which could have been sold separately in a
small number of more straightforward transactions. “Plain vanilla”
transactions are rarely disputed.
B. A Critique of the Four Approaches
Thus far, I have described only the economic complexities of
financial derivatives, without mentioning the applicable regulatory
made short-sighted bets that these rates would remain low, based on historical
performance.
233 These collapses followed an extended period during which Asian foreign
exchange rates were very stable. During that period, many market participants made
short-sighted bets that these rates would remain stable, based on historical
performance.
234 Interest rate option and forward contracts are traded on exchanges, whereas
many of the transactions underlying the derivatives disputes during this period were
based on similar, over-the-counter transactions.
235 See STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 161 (noting increase in use of OTC
derivatives by non-financial institutions from $7.5 trillion in 1995 to $11 trillion
in 1998).
54 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
regimes. Unfortunately, those regimes do not track the economic
attributes of derivatives, and often seriously contradict them.236
The result is that the derivatives market is fraught with
uncertainty.237 Frank Knight has distinguished between risk (which
has an observable probability distribution) and uncertainty (which does
not).238 Markets deal well with risk, but not with uncertainty. Some
investors (in some instances including sophisticated derivatives
market participants) face uncertainty in valuing complex
derivatives.239 Others understand derivatives well enough to evaluate
their market risks, but face uncertainty in assessing other aspects of
the transactions, including potential liability in a future dispute. Much
of the uncertainty in derivatives market stems from regulation and
the OTC markets are the least certain.240 Most jurisdictions permit
OTC derivatives transactions, although some limit or prohibit them
when retail investors or unsophisticated counterparties are
involved.241 Not surprisingly, a recent survey of derivatives
regulators concluded “there is little uniformity in regulatory approach
to OTC derivatives.”242
This section assesses how the four regulatory alternatives have
addressed derivatives disputes (or have failed to do so). Statutory
coverage is piecemeal and byzantine, and has led market participants
to opt out of the statutory framework when dealing in the OTC
markets. The common law, then, has been left to resolve these
disputes, and it has performed abysmally. Private law has worked to
insulate market participants from regulatory coverage and,
potentially, from liability in disputes, but has failed to clarify
transaction terms relevant to disputes. Arbitration has played only a
limited role, and has provided even less certainty.
1. Piecemeal Regulation of Derivatives by Statute
The greatest source of uncertainty in the derivatives market is the
complex web of statutory regimes that govern (or do not govern)
derivatives purchases and sales. Derivatives are regulated by multiple
236 This regulatory tension creates additional incentives for regulatory arbitrage
transactions.
237 See, e.g., Michael Schroeder, Lugar in Senate Charges CFTC, SEC Impede
Bill to Deregulate Derivatives, WALL ST. J., June 22, 2000, at C26 (describing current
legal and regulatory uncertainty and legislation proposed to reduce it); Kathleen
Day, The Derivatives Dilemma; Oversight Dispute Leaves Contracts in Perilous
Limbo, WASH. POST, June 2, 2000, at E1 (describing the legal status of derivatives as
“murky”); see generally Thomas A. Russo & Marlisa Vinciguerra, Financial
Innovation and Uncertain Regulation: Selected Issues Regarding New Product
Development, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1431 (1991).
238 See FRANK H. KNIGHT, RISK, UNCERTAINTY AND PROFIT (1921).
239 See STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 191-92 (“There are significant difficulties in
understanding, pricing and managing inherently complex derivative instruments,
particularly longer-date instruments, for example currency options. The statistical
and mathematical techniques that underlie pricing and trading strategies are based
on the assumption that historical distributions of price changes are good guides to
future volatility. Uncertainty about the value of derivative positions may lead to
liquidation sales in declining markets.”).
240 In response to a recent survey, regulators in sixteen countries240 listed “the
types of OTC derivatives transactions permitted” as the primary area of concern. See
id.
241 See id
242 Id.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
55
laws under multiple regulatory jurisdictions.243 Many classes of
derivatives are not regulated at all. Many pockets of the derivatives
market exist precisely because of the range of nonsensical and costly
statutory applications. This section is an attempt to explain some of
the differential aspects of those statutory regimes.
There are two primary244 sets of federal statutes and agencies
regulating derivatives.245 First, the Securities and Exchange
Commission (SEC) regulates “securities”246 (which include stocks,
243 See, e.g., HAMILTON, ET AL., A GUIDE TO FEDERAL DERIVATIVES REGULATION 9
(1998).
244 Not all derivatives disputes with federal statutory claims involve either of
these two statutes (the securities and commodities statutes). Plaintiffs in recent
derivatives disputes have alleged other novel theories, even including violations of
the Racketeer Influenced and Corrupt Organizations Act (RICO), allegations that
were made together with allegations of common law fraud. See Sumitomo Copper
Swaps Complaint Seeks $1.5B from Chase Manhattan, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Jan.
24, 2000, at 6 (noting the including of a RICO claim). One leading derivatives cases
was decided under the Employee Retirement Income Security Act (ERISA). In that
case, Laborers Nat’l Pension Fund v. American Nat’l Bank & Trust Co. of Chicago,
173 F.3d 313 (5th Cir.), cert. denied, 120 S. Ct. 406 (1999), the Fifth Circuit ruled
that a pension fund’s investment in Interest Only (IO) strips did not violate the
prudent investment standards contained in ERISA. See also Trying to Recoup
Losses, Fund Fails to Win Sup. Ct. Review, SECURITIES LITIG. & REG. REPTR., Jan. 12,
2000, at 6. In that case, Laborers National Pension Fund (LNPF) lost $4.2 million on
IOs it bought from American National Bank. LNPF sued in the Northern District of
Texas, and the district court found the investments violated ERISA and awarded
damages of $7.1 million. However, the Fifth Circuit reversed, holding that although
IOs are volatile, they were only 6.5 percent of the fund’s portfolio and served to
hedge other portions of the fund. See id.
245 Other federal agencies, including the Federal Reserve Board, also play a role
in the regulation of derivatives. Most prominently, the Fed plays an active role in
system-wide concerns about risk, as it did in the recent near-collapse of Long-Term
Capital Management. See Peter H. Huang, Kimberly D. Krawiec & Frank Partnoy ,
Derivatives on TV: A Tale of Two Derivatives Debacles in Prime-Time,
<http://www.greenbag.org> (2000) (copy on file with the author). The U.S.
Department of Treasury also plays an important, although often informal, role. The
“Treasury Amendment” – though not explicitly directed at the U.S. Treasury –
expressly excludes certain financial instruments from the scope of federal
commodities regulation. The Treasury Amendment provides that “[n]othing in this
Act shall be deemed to govern or in any way be applicable to transactions in foreign
currency, security warrants, security rights, resales of installment loan contracts,
repurchase options, government securities, or mortgages and mortgage purchase
commitments, unless such transactions involve the sale thereof for future delivery
conducted on a board of trade.” 7 U.S.C. § 2; see also 50 Fed. Reg. 42963 (Oct. 23,
1985) (CFTC interpretation of Treasury Amendment). The Treasury Amendment
arguably exempts from regulation certain types of derivatives, including swaps.
246 There is substantial uncertainty surrounding the definition of “security.”
The question of whether a particular financial contact is a “security” (and therefore
falls within the ambit of federal securities law) typically turns on judicial
interpretation of the relevant federal statutes. In the 1933 Securities Act, Congress
defined the term “security” as
any note, stock, treasury stock, bond, debenture, evidence of indebtedness,
certificate of interest or participation in any profit-sharing agreement,
collateral-trust certificate, preorganization certificate or subscription,
transferable share, investment contract, voting-trust certificate, certificate of
deposit for a security, fractional undivided interest in oil, gas, or other mineral
rights, any put, call, straddle, option, or privilege on any security, certificate of
deposit, or group or index of securities (including any interest therein or based
on the value thereof), or any put, call, straddle, option, or privilege entered into
on a national securities exchange relating to foreign currency, or, in general, any
interest or instrument commonly known as a “security”, or a certificate of
56 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
bonds, and options), pursuant to the 1993 Securities Act247 and 1934
Securities Exchange Act.248 Second, the Commodity Futures Trading
Commission (CFTC) regulates “futures”249 (which include exchange-
traded futures on various commodities, instruments, and indices),250
pursuant to the Commodity Exchange Act.251 Many of the conflicts
in derivatives regulation stem from the turf battle between the SEC
and CFTC created by these two statutory regimes.252
Such a bifurcated regime is in general problematic. It is
increasingly difficult to determine whether, under the applicable tests,
a particular instrument is a “security” or “future” or neither.253
Regulated derivatives may be economically equivalent, but fit under
different statutory regimes.254 Competition between these two
interest or participation in, temporary or interim certificate for, receipt for,
guarantee of, or warrant or right to subscribe to or purchase, any of the
foregoing.
15 U.S.C. § 77b(1). The definition in the 1934 Securities Exchange Act is
virtually identical to the definition in the 1933 Act and courts have held that the
1933 and 1934 Acts cover the same instruments. See 15 U.S.C. § 78c(a)(10); see also
Reves v. Ernst & Young, 494 U.S. 56 (1989).
247 15 U.S.C. § 77.
248 15 U.S.C. § 78c.
249 An additional wrinkle is added by the fact that the CFTC also has exclusive
jurisdiction over option transactions involving commodities. See 7 U.S.C. §
2(a)(1)(A) (granting the CFTC exclusive jurisdiction over “accounts, agreements
(including any transaction which is of the character of . . . an ‘option’ . . .), and
transactions involving contracts of sale of a commodity for future delivery traded or
executed on a contract market . . . or any other board of trade, exchange, or market . . .
.”).
250 Congress passed the Commodity Exchange Act, and amended it to establish
the CFTC in 1974, in response to widespread abuses in commodity futures trading
and to protect investors amid “the volatile and esoteric futures trading complex.”
CFTC v. Schor, 478 U.S. 833, 836 (1986) (quoting H.R. Rep. No. 93-975, p. 1 (1974)).
251 7 U.S.C. §§ 2 et seq.
252 The lines between regulatory areas in the U.S. often are less than clear. For
example, a “futures contract” may only be traded on a designated exchange, but a
“forward contract” – even if it is economically equivalent – may be traded off-
exchange, or over-the-counter (OTC). See Willa E. Gibson, Are Swap Transactions
Securities or Futures?: The Inadequacies of Applying Traditional Regulatory
Approach to OTC Derivatives Transactions, 24 J. CORP. L. 379 (1999).
253 Consider, for example, an unusual type of derivative instrument called a
“viatical settlement.” The purchaser of a viatical settlement pays cash upfront for an
interest in the life insurance policy of a terminally ill person, typically a victim of
AIDS. The price of the viatical settlement is discounted depending on the life
expectancy of the insured. When the insured dies, the investor receives a share of the
insurance proceeds. The courts have struggled with the question of whether viatical
settlements are “securities,” ultimately relying on the Howey test, which holds that
an investment contract is a security if investors purchase with an expectation of
profits arising from a common enterprise that depends upon the efforts of others.
See SEC v. W.J. Howey Co., 328 U.S. 293, 298-99 (1946). In 1996, the D.C. Circuit
held, over a vigorous dissent by Judge Wald, that viatical settlements were not
securities, because although they are purchased with an expectation of profits
arising from a common enterprise, those profits did not depend upon the “efforts of
others,” because the intermediaries selling the contracts performed only ministerial
services and, instead, it is the length of the insured’s life that is of overwhelming
importance to the value of the viatical settlements. See SEC v. Life Partners, 87 F.3d
536, 542-48 (D.C. Cir. 1996).
254 Even relatively straightforward regulatory regimes present complex and
intractable questions. For example, the task of matching purchase and sale
transactions for the purpose of calculating liability under Section 16(b) of the
Securities Exchange Act, 15 U.S.C. § 78p(b), becomes enormously complicated once
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
57
regimes has not led to the efficiencies predicted by scholars who
advocate expanded regulatory competition.255 To the contrary,
competition has led to a nasty and inefficient turf battle, and costly
uncertainty.
Consider, for example, the regulation of forward contracts on
individual stocks or bonds. The SEC and CFTC have disagreed about
this issue for decades. The SEC claimed it should have jurisdiction
because such contracts behave like the underlying individual stocks
and bonds; the CFTC claimed it should have jurisdiction because such
contracts behave like futures.256 For such contracts, it was unclear
which regulatory regime applied, if any, and competition between the
two relevant jurisdictions had only increased uncertainty and
paralyzed the markets for those instruments.257 In fact, the only
resolution to the dispute was a Congressional ban on futures contracts
on individual stocks and bonds; now, such contracts are illegal and
unenforceable.258 In other words, options on single securities are
allowed; futures on single securities are not.259 Recent efforts to
remove the ban have provoked heated debate.260 In this area,
regulatory competition did not lead to efficient results; it forced a
stalemate.
Over time, exceptions have been carved out of this ban against
futures trading of individual stocks and bonds. There are exceptions
for futures on government securities, including U.S. Treasury bonds,
and for futures on broad-based equity indices, including the Standard &
Poor’s 500 Index.261 Other “illegal” futures still can be, and are,
traded in the OTC market.262 In other words, regulation banning the
trading of these instruments has created a gray market in
economically equivalent OTC derivatives transactions. This gray
market is not trivial. By 2000, the market for equity swaps was
several trillion dollars.263
derivatives are added to the mix. See Magma Power Co. v. Dow Chemical Co., 136
F.3d 316 (2d Cir. 1998) (finding that Dow Chemical’s delivery of Magma Power
stock was not eligible for 16(b) purposes where the stock was delivered pursuant to
the exercise of subordinated exchangeable notes Dow Chemical previously had
issued; the notes gave the noteholder the option to exchange the notes at any time
prior to maturity for a fixed number of Magma Power Co. shares).
255 See supra notes 35-36.
256 See, e.g., Day, supra note 237, at E1 (describing turf battle between the SEC
and CFTC since 1982).
257 See Day, supra note 237, at E1
258 Section 4(a) of the Commodity Exchange Act provides that it is unlawful to
enter into a commodity futures contract that is not made “on or subject to the rules
of a board of trade which has been designated by the Commission as a ‘contract
market’ for such commodity.” 7 U.S.C. § 6(a).
259 See Board of Trade of the City of Chicago v. SEC, 187 F.3d 713, 716 (7th Cir.
1999) (noting that “[t]his allocation appears to be a political compromise; no one
has suggested an economic rationale for the distinction.”).
260 See SEC’s Levitt Sees “Gaping Loophole” in Senate Bill 2697, 6 DERIVATIVES
LITIG. REPTR., July 3, 2000, at 9.
261 See Day, supra note 237, at E1.
262 The creation of such instruments is another example of regulatory arbitrage.
See Partnoy, Regulatory Arbitrage, supra note 5.
263 In an equity swap, one counterparty agrees to receive (and the other agrees to
pay) the increase in value of a particular stock or stocks and, in exchange, that
counterparty agrees to pay (and the other agrees to receive) a specific periodic
payment, typically based on some fixed or floating interest rate.
58 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
In the same way, market participants created large classes of OTC
derivatives to fill gaps in other CFTC regulation. The CFTC requires
that any CFTC-regulated financial contracts be traded on a CFTC-
regulated exchange,264 and Congress allows the CFTC to create a list
of forward contracts that could be excluded entirely from CFTC
regulation (and that therefore were not required to be traded on a
CFTC-regulated exchange). Today, such forward contracts are traded
in the OTC market, and include some of the largest markets in the
world, including the market for interest rate and currency swaps.
Derivatives traded in these OTC markets remain legal so long as
the CFTC keeps those trades on its list of exempt contracts.
However, there is the possibility, albeit unlikely, that the CFTC would
remove one or more contracts from its list. If it did so, such
contracts would become illegal and unenforceable, because they would
not be traded on a CFTC-regulated exchange.265 This remote
possibility has contributed to the uncertainty among derivatives
market participants.
The statutory uncertainty of OTC derivatives regulation has a
complex history. During the 1980s, as derivatives were
developing,266 regulators struggled with possible responses to the
differential jurisdictional treatment of derivatives.267 In 1984, the
CFTC and the SEC issued a Joint Policy Statement spelling out the
types of financial derivatives the agencies believed were suitable for
trading.268 Following that statement, the CFTC issued several releases
addressing the issue, and responded on a case-by-case basis to inquiries
about regulation of particular instruments through its no-action letter
process.269 The primary focus of the releases and responses was on
the market for swaps,270 which had been growing dramatically in the
264 See 7 U.S.C. § 6(a), 6c(b), 6c(c).
265 In the example of equity swaps, which were created to sidestep the ban of
forward contracts on individual stocks and bonds, the legal uncertainty is especially
great. See, e.g., Day, supra note 237, at E1 (“If equity swaps were deemed by a court
to be futures contracts, they would become instantly illegal, on or off a regulated
exchange, because of the ban on futures contracts based on individual corporate
securities.”).
266 Even by 1989, there was a mere $7.1 trillion worth of outstanding notional
amount of derivative financial instruments. JAMES HAMILTON, ET AL., supra note 243,
at 9. By June 1999, the estimated global notional amount was $81.5 trillion. See
Bank for International Settlements Releases Global Derivatives Statistics,
DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Dec. 20, 1999, at 6.
267 Courts struggled, too. For example, in 1984, the Seventh Circuit held that a
forward contract to purchase a Government National Mortgage Associate security
was properly regulated by the antifraud provisions of the securities laws, even
though the forward contract itself is not a security as defined by the securities laws.
See Abrams v. Oppenheimer Gov’t Securities, Inc., 737 F.2d 582 (7th Cir. 1984).
268 See Joint Policy Statement, 49 Fed. Reg. 2884 (Jan. 24, 1984). Although this
statement was simply a statement, not a regulation, and therefore lacked legal force,
market participants observed its limits for many years when proposing new
contracts. See Board of Trade, supra note 259, at 716.
269 See CFTC Policy Statement Concerning Swap Transactions, 54 Fed. Reg.
30694, at 2 n.2 (July 21, 1989) (describing relevant proposed rules, requests for
comments, and notices of proposed rulemaking from 1985 through 1989); see also
id. at 2 n.3 (describing several no-action letters addressing proposed offerings of
derivative transactions by the CFTC Task Force on Off-Exchange Instruments).
270 A swap is simply a contract pursuant to which two counterparties agree to
exchange cash flows. In an interest rate swap, the counterparties exchange cash flows
based on changes in some interest rate or interest rate index; in a currency swap, they
exchange cash flows based on changes in some foreign exchange rate or index.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
59
late 1980s. In response to a perceived need for clarification, the
CFTC issued a detailed policy statement on swaps on July 21,
1989.271
The 1989 CFTC policy statement took the position that most
swap transactions were not appropriately regulated by the CFTC and
recognized a “non-exclusive safe harbor for transactions satisfying
the requirements set forth herein.”272 The CFTC relied on multiple
rationales for exempting swaps from regulation,273 but recognized the
argument that swaps are economically equivalent to futures.274
The CFTC policy statement listed five specific criteria relevant
to determining whether the safe harbor applied. The CFTC’s stated
objective in issuing the policy statement was to generate “a greater
degree of clarity”275 for swap market participants. These criteria –
(1) (1) individually tailored terms, (2) absence of exchange-style
offset, (3) absence of clearing organization or margin system, (4) the
transaction is undertaken in conjunction with a line of business, and
(5) prohibition against marketing to the public276 – are examined in
detail below.
From 1989 until early 1993, the derivatives industry lobbied the
CFTC to adopt regulations embodying the principles and objectives in
the 1989 policy statement.277 At the eleventh hour, one-week before
the end of her term, CFTC Chair Wendy Gramm – wife of Senator
Phil Gramm – finally persuaded the CFTC to adopt the exemption (in
what was described as Gramm’s “farewell gift” to the swaps
industry278) in 17 C.F.R. § 35, known as Part 35. Part 35 is a
framework for exempting particular OTC swaps from the CEA’s
exchange trading requirements. Part 35 exempts swaps that meet
particular categories279 and authorizes the CFTC to grant additional
exemptions on a case-by-case basis.280
271 See id. at 1.
272 See CFTC Policy Statement, supra note 269, at 4.
273 “Commentators have described the swap market as one in which the
customary large transaction size effectively limits the market to institutional
participants rather than the retail public. Market participants also have noted that
swaps typically involve long-term contracts, with maturities ranging up to twelve
years. In addition to these characteristics, many comparisons between swaps and
futures contracts have stressed the tailored, non-standardized nature of swap terms;
the necessity for particularized credit determinations in connection with each swap
transaction (or series of transactions between the same counterparties); the lack of
public participation in the swap markets; and the predominantly institutional and
commercial nature of swap participants.” Id. at 5 (citations omitted).
274 “Other commentators have stressed that despite these distinctions in the
manner of trading of swaps and exchange products, the economic reality of swaps
nevertheless resembles that of futures contracts.” Id. at 5. Economically, swaps can
be described as a series of forward contracts.
275 See CFTC Policy Statement, supra note 269, at 7.
276 Id. at 7-10.
277 See Matt Rees, Swap Market: Farewell Gift from CFTC’s Gramm for Swap
Traders, BLOOMBERG BUSINESS NEWS, Jan. 14, 1993, at 1 (copy on file with the
author).
278 See id.
279 These categories include minimum financial thresholds for various
institutions. See 17 C.F.R. § 35.1(b)(2).
280 See 17 C.F.R. § 35.2(d).
60 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Part 35 does not provide nearly the certainty it could.281 Part
35.1(b)(1) explicitly exempts certain swap agreements, including any
agreement which is “a rate swap agreement, basis swap, forward rate
agreement, commodity swap, interest rate option, forward foreign
exchange agreement, rate cap agreement, rate floor agreement, rate
collar agreement, currency swap agreement, cross-currency rate swap
agreement, currency option, any other similar agreement (including
any option to enter into any of the foregoing) . . . [or] Any
combination of the foregoing .”282 However, these particular terms
are not defined, and it is unclear what tests should be applied to
determine if a particular instruments fits within the list. Part
35.1(b)(2) limits eligible swap participants to (1) financial
institutions, including banks, trust companies, savings associations,
credit unions, insurance companies, investment companies,
commodity pools, broker-dealers, and futures commission merchants
(including floor brokers or floor traders);283 (2) large corporations,
including business entities with total assets of $10 million, or a net
worth of $1 million if it is entering into the swap in connection with
its business or if the swap obligations are secured;284 (3) employee
benefit plans, including both certain employee benefit plans subject to
the Employee Retirement Income Security Act of 1974 and certain
foreign persons performing similar functions;285 and (4)
governmental entities, including the United States, states, foreign
governments, multinational entities, and their political
subdivisions.286 These provisions are clear, but static, and are neither
indexed to inflation nor flexible enough to allow additions or
subtractions from the list based on changes over time. In the seven
years since Part 35 was enacted, it has not changed at all; during the
same time, the derivatives industry has experienced revolutionary
change.
Although derivatives industry participants have relied on the safe
harbor of the CFTC policy statement since 1989, and Part 35 since
1993, they do not appear to have considered in detail the application
of the factors in either case. Indeed, because Part 35 is ambiguous in
several respects,287 it is useful to consider the factors in the 1989
CFTC policy statement in greater detail. For many swaps at least one
of the criteria – often several – are not satisfied. Moreover, the 1989
CFTC policy statement is a very useful statement of the intended
coverage of any swaps exemption; to the extent the regulatory
exemption as implemented has exceeded the scope of this coverage
(and perhaps of its own language), this expansion may need to be
reconsidered. The 1989 criteria are now among the most important,
yet least discussed, aspects of U.S. derivatives regulation. Legal
281 See Rees, supra note 277, at 2 (quoting a prominent derivatives attorney as
saying “it’s not a completely clean exemption”).
282 17 C.F.R. Part 35.1(b)(1)(i), (ii).
283 See 17 C.F.R. Part 35.1(b)(2)(i)- (v), (ix), (x).
284 See 17 C.F.R. Part 35.1(b)(2)(vi).
285 See 17 C.F.R. Part 35.1(b)(2)(vii).
286 See 17 C.F.R. Part 35.1(b)(2)(viii).
287 For example, Part 35 does not include as exempt any swaps that are part of a
“fungible class of agreements that are standardized as to their material economic
terms.” 17 C.F.R. § 35.2(b) (1993). This language, while ambiguous, draws heavily
from all five criteria in the 1989 CFTC policy statement. See CFTC Policy Statement,
supra note 269, at 1-10.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
61
commentators have largely ignored them. Therefore, it is worth
considering these criteria in greater detail.
The first criterion is individually tailored terms, which relatively
few swaps have. The CFTC stated, “[s]uch tailoring and counterparty
credit assessment distinguish swap transactions from exchange
transactions, where the contract terms are standardized and the
counterparty is unknown.”288 The assumption that swaps were
individually tailored may have been true in 1989; it certainly no
longer holds today. Most swap agreements are fully standardized.
The International Swap Dealers Association (ISDA) has established a
detailed standardized contract that is used for the vast majority of
swap contracts. Interest rate swaps and currency swaps in particular
are highly standardized. In the 1989 policy statement, the CFTC
recognized that swap counterparties entering into several swap
transactions might find it beneficial to enter into a “master
agreement” covering all of the transactions, although it warned that it
nevertheless required that “material terms of the master agreement
and transaction specifications are individually tailored by the
parties.”289 The market has moved away from the CFTC’s expressed
understanding in 1989. According to the CFTC, “[t]o qualify for safe
harbor treatment, swaps must be negotiated by the parties as to their
material terms, based upon individualized credit determinations, and
documented by the parties in an agreement or series of agreements
that is not fully standardized.”290 By this standard, many swaps –
including many disputed swaps – would not qualify.
Second, in order to qualify for a safe harbor, the CFTC required
that a swap not have an “exchange-style offset.” This term refers to
the ability of a party to liquidate a futures position by acquiring an
opposite, or off-setting, position.291 For exchange traded futures,
because the counterparty to any trade is the exchange and there is a
single clearing organization for any trade, there is no need to obtain
the consent of the clearing organization in order to offset futures
transactions. The CFTC seemed to believe in 1989 that there was a
substantive difference between futures and swap transactions because
the counterparty to a swap is another party whose consent was
required in order to offset the swap.292 The purpose of this
requirement, as articulated by the CFTC, was to exempt only
transactions that “are not readily used as trading vehicles, that are
entered into with the expectation of performance and that are
terminated as well as entered into based upon private negotiation.”293
This is a distinction without a difference. Parties enter into
offsetting swaps quite commonly. Counterparties routinely net swaps,
and it may be possible – though frequently it is very costly – to find
several counterparties (other than the original counterparty to a
swap) to enter into a mirror to the original swap. Legal rules,
including tax and net capital requirements, explicitly recognize
netting, and private parties net swaps in assessing credit exposure to
various counterparties. Moreover, some swaps are quite liquid and
288 Id. at 7.
289 Id. at 7.
290 Id. at 7.
291 Id. at 8.
292 Id. at 8.
293 Id. at 9.
62 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
fungible and are traded using broker screens in a way that is virtually
indistinguishable from exchange trades. There have been proposals to
trade swaps on exchanges, and one commentator believes exchange
trading is a natural solution to some of the problems posed by OTC
derivatives.294 At least one website has proposed acting as an
intermediary for swap transactions.295 Thus, since 1989, the swaps
market has changed in ways that conflict with the CFTC’s
understanding of this second criterion.
The third safe harbor criterion is that swaps should not have a
clearing organization or margin system. The CFTC clearly did not
intend to exempt swaps for which there was a clearing organization or
some similar system used to minimize credit risk. According to the
CFTC, “this safe harbor is applicable only to swap transactions that
are not supported by the credit of a clearing organization and that are
not primarily or routinely supported by a mark-to-market margin and
variation settlement system designed to eliminate individualized credit
risk.”296
As noted above, private parties act in ways (e.g., netting) that
make the swaps market very similar in economic substance to the
futures market. Banks use daily mark-to-market, and often monitor
positions more frequently. There are a few banks with large numbers
of counterparties that are at least as sophisticated as the futures
exchanges in reducing credit risk. There are various risk management
systems available, including well known approaches such as
CreditMetrics and Value-at-Risk. There even have been efforts to
securitize or insure derivatives exposure, to offload credit risk.297 In
short, the swaps market has developed private risk management
systems that resemble the credit, clearing, and margin systems of
exchange markets.
Fourth, to qualify for the safe harbor, swap transactions should be
undertaken in conjunction with a line of business. It is unclear how
far the CFTC originally envisioned the “line of business” test would
extend, but it noted that “[s]wap transactions entered into with
respect to exchange rate, interest rate, or other price exposure arising
from a participant’s line of business or the financing of its business
would be consistent with this standard.”298
This statement appears to draw a distinction between dealer
transactions and transactions by non-dealer or non-financial parties.
Transactions between banks in the OTC market – the vast majority
of OTC derivatives – may be related to “line of business” exposure,
although frequently they will involve speculation or arbitrage instead.
But more importantly, transactions involving non-bank parties,
294 See STEINHERR, supra note 5, at xiv.
295 See http://www.MyCFO.com.
296 See CFTC Policy Statement, supra note 269, at 9.
297 For example, the London Clearing House, the clearing house for London’s
main derivatives exchanges, bought from a subsidiary of American International
Group £150 million in credit insurance. See Sophie Belcher, London Clearing
House Buys GBP100 Million in Credit Protection, DERIVATIVES WK., Feb. 10, 1997, at
1, 11. This insurance protects the clearing house from credit losses of more than this
amount during a three-year period. Other exchanges have purchased similar forms of
default insurance.
298 See CFTC Policy Statement, supra note 269, at 9.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
63
which are more frequently disputed than bank-to-bank transactions,
often will not relate to a line of business at all.299
Fifth, swap transactions may not be marketed to the public.300
This criteria merits only a short paragraph in the CFTC policy
statement, although that paragraph makes it clear that the CFTC
assumed swaps would not be part of a banks’ core sales function. This
assumption also proved incorrect. Swaps dealers aggressively market
their transactions to clients outside the financial sector, and the
greatest profits from swaps involve sales to public investors
(individuals and institutions) who may lack the sophistication and
information necessary to evaluate the transactions.
This movement away from the CFTC’s original understanding of
swaps generates great uncertainty about the regulation of OTC
derivatives. Obviously, swap dealers understand the implications of
this uncertainty, and therefore are lobbying for clearer exemptions.301
Regulators have resisted this lobbying, in part because they understand
OTC dealers lobbied previously for the 1993 exemptions in Part 35,
and then expanded it to support a multi-trillion dollar unregulated
industry.
For all these reasons, the legal rights of the parties to any dispute
stemming from losses on OTC derivatives are mired in uncertainty.
As of August 2000,302 both industry executives and federal regulators
were publicly expressing concern that a counterparty might walk away
from its obligations under an OTC derivatives contract, and
successfully argue that the contract was illegal and therefore
unenforceable.303 In late 1998, such uncertainty had generated fear
among regulators that the collapse of Long-Term Capital
Management, which had relied heavily on OTC derivatives contracts,
would cause securities markets to unravel.304 More recently, this
uncertainty has stifled innovation and contracting in the derivatives
markets.
In a recent article, Michael Bennett and Michael Marlin argue
that the regulators use legal uncertainty and ambiguity to enhance and
maintain their control over derivatives market participants.305
Regulators in Asia often overlook or ignore questionable market
299 Consider, for example, the payments Gibson Greetings was to owe on a swap
transaction it entered into with Bankers Trust in October 1992: Gibson’s payments
would equal 5.5 percent minus LIBOR-squared divided by 6 percent. This swap,
known as a “ratio swap,” could not possibly be related to any Gibson line of
business. Arguably, a swap with a squared term cannot be related to any entity’s line
of business, at least on this planet. The CFTC policy statement should not cover
transactions like ratio swaps, which are unrelated to a line of business.
300 See CFTC Policy Statement, supra note 269, at 10.
301 See sources cited supra at note 237.
302 Congress was required to reauthorize the CFTC by end of September 2000.
303 See, e.g., Day, supra note 237, at E1 (“The legal status of OTC derivatives is
murky. The enforceability of these contracts has never been tested in court.
Regulators and industry executives hope it stays that way until Congress clears up
the laws governing these complex, increasingly essential financial products.”).
304 See Day, supra note 237, at E1.
305 See Michael S. Bennett & Michael J. Marin, The Casablanca Paradigm:
Regulatory Risk in the Asian Financial Derivatives Markets, 5 STAN. J.L. BUS. & FIN.
1, 9 (1999) (describing the regulatory model for such legal uncertainty as the
“Casablanca Paradigm,” named for the 1942 Warner Bros. movie).
64 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
practices until political pressures force them to act.306 This approach
creates uncertainty for market participants, “because it limits the
importance of regulatory precedent.”307 In Asia, regulators provide
guidance to market participants on an informal basis, through the
administrative approach known as gyousei shidou, creating burdens
for firms that do not comply with the regulators, and awarding
benefits to firms that do.308
This informal process has benefits. However, market participants
do not have advance warning of a change in position. If the market
participants have a close relationship with the regulators, it may lead
to greater flexibility and perhaps greater certainty in the short term.
It is difficult to obtain reliable information about derivatives losses, so
it is difficult to say how such losses result in disputes.309
The regulators’ positions with respect to statutory coverage of
derivatives are in constant flux. In derivatives markets outside the
U.S., there is even greater uncertainty, because market participants
believe regulators might change their approach to derivatives at any
time.310 But even in the U.S., there is no consistent regulatory
position. For example, on November 9, 1999, the President’s
Working Group on Financial Markets311 issued a report
recommending additional deregulation and exemptions for OTC
derivatives.312 At approximately the same time, two members of
Congress cosponsored a bill making equity swaps – a commonly-used
type of OTC derivative – subject to regulation.313 A recent proposal
to allow trading of futures or swaps on individual securities faces
intense opposition.314 As of September 2000, bills were pending in
both the Senate and House of Representatives to reauthorize and
306 See CHARLES ADAMS ET AL., INTERNATIONAL MONETARY FUND, INTERNATIONAL
CAPITAL MARKETS (1998); Antony Currie, Asian Derivatives: Waiting for the Big
One, EUROMONEY, Feb. 1997.
307 Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 10.
308 See Curtis J. Milhaupt, Managing the Market: The Ministry of Finance and
Securities Regulation in Japan, 30 STAN. J. INT’L L. 423 (1994); see also Bennett &
Marin, supra note 305, at 11 n.43 (citing numerous sources).
309 See Robert W. McSherry, Experts Worry Over the Potential for Derivatives
Defaults by Asian Companies, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Feb. 5, 1998, at 3 (“Insider
reports, however, are hard to verify because of a culture of reticence that permeates
the derivatives business.”).
310 “The fact that regulators have tolerated a practice in the past does not
necessarily mean that the practice will continue to be tolerated in the future or that
market participants will be given any warning before the regulators change their
position.” Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 11.
311 The President’s Working Group on Financial Markets consists of the
Secretary of the Treasury, and the chairpersons of the Securities and Exchange
Commission, the Commodity Futures Trading Commission, and the Federal Reserve
Board. See Conrad G. Bahlke, A Brief Review of the President’s Working Group
Issues Report on OTC Derivatives, SECURITIES LITIG. & REG. REPTR., Dec. 22, 1999, at
10.
312 The President’s Working Group Report warned that the uncertain status of
some derivatives could, if not addressed, discourage innovation and growth in
derivatives markets, and recommended, among other things, an exclusion from the
Commodity Exchange Act for sophisticated counterparties to OTC transactions. See
id.
313 In early November 1999, Rep. Edward J. Markey and Senator Byron L. Dorgan
cosponsored the Derivatives Market Reform Act, which would have made equity
swaps subject to regulation under the Securities Exchange Act. See Bahlke, supra
note 311, at 10.
314 See Senate Bill 2697, supra note 260, at 9.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
65
amend the Commodity Exchange Act; included in the bills are
provisions exempting numerous additional derivatives transactions
and entities from federal regulation.315
Finally, the statutory uncertainty about derivatives is not limited
to federal laws. Certain state laws, too, have generated uncertainty.
In particular, there is uncertainty surrounding state laws prohibiting
certain forms of gambling. There are such statutes in most U.S.
states316 and foreign jurisdictions,317 and although there are few, if
any, recent cases decided under those statutes, their language is broad
enough to encompass literally billions of dollars of derivatives
transactions.318 Not surprisingly, derivatives purchasers have seized
on this broad language, claiming that the applicable transactions were
illegal under the anti-gambling laws of various jurisdictions.319 To the
extent particular OTC derivatives are not covered by the swaps
exemption, this argument is a serious one.
Several legal scholars have argued that many financial derivatives
can be considered as gambling, and that the line between legitimate
transactions and gambling is less than clear.320 New rules promulgated
315 See 106 S. 2697 (2000); 106 H.R. 4541 (2000).
316 For example, under New York law a transaction is illegal gambling if it is a
“wager, bet or stake made to depend upon . . . any . . . chance, casualty or unknown or
contingent event or whatever.” N.Y. Gen. Obl. Law § 5-401 (McKinney 1989).
Similarly, New York’s criminal states that “[a] person engages in gambling when he
stakes or risks something of value upon . . . a future contingent event not under his
control or influence, upon an agreement or understanding that he will receive
something of value in the even of a certain outcome.” N.Y. Penal Law § 225.00
(McKinney 1989).
317 For example, most Asian countries have anti-gambling statutes. In Asia, a
cash settled transaction (as opposed to a physically settled transaction) is more
likely to be deemed an illegal gambling contract. For example, courts in Taiwan
have found cash settled derivatives transactions constitute gambling. See Bennett &
Marin, supra note 305, at 41 (basing such a conclusion on advice received from the
Taipei law firm of Lee and Li), and under the Philippine Civil Code cash-settled over-
the-counter equity option and forward contracts are likely to be held null and void
as illegal gaming contracts. See id. (basing such a conclusion on advice received
from the Manila law firm of SyCip, Salazar, Hernandez & Gatmaitan). In a cash
settled transaction, the underlying asset never changes hands; the parties simply
exchange cash at the end of the contract. For example, if a party contracts to buy
gold on a forward basis, at the expiration of a physically settled contract, she would
pay cash and receive the gold; at the expiration of a cash settled contract, she would
pay or receive the difference between the value of the gold and the value of the cash.
See ZVI BODIE & ROBERT C. MERTON, FINANCE 366-68 (2000). Cash settled
transactions are less costly and more convenient, especially for parties who do not
actually require delivery of physical assets.
318 Many such statutes are both vague and broad, especially outside the U.S. For
example, the Indonesian Civil Code provides simply that all claims arising from
games or betting are unenforceable; Hong Kong’s Gambling Ordinance prohibits
gaming, betting, and bookmaking, and defines gaming as the playing of any game
for winnings in money or other property. See Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at
39-40; see also Gilliam Tett, Traders Gamble on an Anomaly, FIN. TIMES, July 17,
1988, at 6 (discussing applicability of Japanese anti-gambling laws to financial
derivatives).
319 See Korea Life Files 2nd Amended Complaint Against Morgan Guaranty, 6
DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR. 3 (noting claims raised under New York gambling statute).
320 See Thomas Lee Hazen, Public Policy: Rational Investments, Speculation or
Gambling? – Derivative Securities and Financial Futures and Their Effect on
Underlying Capital Markets, 86 NW. U. L. REV. 987 (1992); Lynn Stout, Why the Law
Hates Speculators: Regulation and Private Ordering in the Market for OTC
Derivatives, 48 DUKE L.J. 701 (1999). Legislators also have made this point. See
66 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
by the Financial Accounting Standards Board attempt to draw the line
between hedging and speculation in the derivatives context, with
results that are both complex and often counterintuitive.321 Many
recently issued securities easily could be categorized as illegal gambling
contracts including, for example, a bond linked to the number of
victories by the Utah Jazz, a professional basketball team;322 a
derivative security based on an interest rate index multiplied by itself
three times;323 or so-called Asian options, whose payoff can depend
on a continuously-sampled geometric average.324
Several states also have so-called “bucket shop” laws,325 which
present a similar problem to those posed by the anti-gambling
statutes. “Bucket shop” laws prohibit wagering on changes in the
market prices of securities by means of “fictitious transactions in such
securities.”326 One court has held that an interest rate swap was not
subject to California’s bucket shop law.327 However, it is questionable
whether the analysis in that case would prevent most derivatives from
falling under the law.328
In sum, statutes regulating derivatives are all over the financial
map. They provide little clarity or certainty to market participants,
who have attempted to opt out of these statutes by structuring
transactions outside their reach. For parties involved in derivatives
disputes, it is unclear if the statutes apply at all.
2. Judicial Treatment of Derivatives Disputes
I began Part IV.B. with a discussion of the statutory coverage of
derivatives in order to demonstrate upfront how difficult it is to
determine whether a particular derivative is a regulated security, a
STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 151 (citing Rep. Henry Gonzalez as saying, “You can call
it [the use of derivatives] whatever you want, but in my book it’s gambling.”).
321 See FINANCIAL ACCOUNTING STANDARDS BOARD STATEMENT OF FINANCIAL
CONCEPTS NO. 113; see also Michael S. Lesak, FASB’s Folly: A Look at the Misguided
New Rules on Derivatives Valuation and Disclosure, 29 LOY. U. CHI. L.J. 649 (1998).
322 See JOHN EATABLE & LANCE TAYLOR, GLOBAL FINANCE AT RISK: THE CASE FOR
INTERNATIONAL REGULATION 101 (2000). I am grateful to Peter Huang for pointing out
this example.
323 See FRANK PARTNOY, FIASCO: THE INSIDE STORY OF A WALL STREET TRADER
139-40 (1999).
324 See WILMOTT, supra note 227, at 215-26.
325 See, e.g., Cal. Corp. Code §§ 29000-29201 (West 1997).
326 See In re Thrifty Oil Co., 212 B.R. 147, 153 (Bankr. S.D. Cal. 1997) (citing
California statutes).
327 See id.
328 First, that court noted that the interest rate swap did not involve a security or
commodity, as California’s law requires. See Cal. Corp. Code § 29004 (West 1997)
(defining security as “all shares in any corporation or association . . . and other
evidences of debt or property and options for the purchase or sale thereof or any
right entitling the holder thereof to participate in profits or a division of assets”);
Cal. Corp. Code § 29005 (West 1997) (defining commodity as “anything movable
that is bought and sold”). Even if it were the case that the payments on a fixed-for-
floating interest rate swap did not involve a security or commodity according to the
statutory definition, many other derivatives would involve a security or commodity.
Second, the court noted that the bucket shop statute only covers agreements where
neither party intends to deliver the security or commodity. See Cal. Corp. Code §
29004 (West 1997). The court apparently misunderstood the meaning of this section
of the statute as requiring that one or both of the parties not intend to fulfill its part
of the contract: “[The parties] fully intended to perform their payment obligations
under the swaps – there was no fictitious transaction.” In re Thrifty Oil Co., supra
note 326, at 154.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
67
regulated commodity, or is unregulated.329 This determination is
crucial in a dispute about losses stemming from an investment in
derivatives: if a judge determines that the derivatives subject to
dispute were securities or commodities, then a federal regulatory
regime would apply to the resolution of the dispute;330 if not, the
judge would dismiss the federal claims and any state law claims would
remain.
In some cases, judges and regulators have strained to argue that
particular OTC derivatives were governed by securities or
commodities laws.331 However, in most of the relevant cases, the
derivatives are governed by neither, as the parties intended, and the
judges are left to resolve state law claims, predominantly under
common law.332 The problem presented here thus relates to the
resolution of disputes when there is no applicable federal statutory
law. In these cases, the parties are seeking to resolve disputes based
on common law and analogical reasoning. Derivatives complaints in
such cases have alleged breach of fiduciary duty, common law fraud
and negligent misrepresentation, lack of authority, and various
contract-based claims.333
This subpart analyzes how courts in some representative cases
have treated these various state common law claims. The drawbacks
of common law in this area are enormous. It is extraordinarily
expensive to resolve these disputes, and there are few published
329 For example, a court would resolve a dispute concerning an investment in a
“security,” see supra note 246 (defining “security” in the 1933 and 1934 Acts),
under the applicable federal securities laws (most likely under Rule 10b-5),329
regardless of whether the economic qualities of the instrument make it a
“derivative.” Similarly, a court would resolve a dispute concerning a commodity
under the relevant federal law. Such disputes involving “regulated” derivatives do
not present the same serious difficulties posed in disputes involving OTC
derivatives.
330 In disputes about derivative securities or commodities, a court will rule that
a particular statute applies and then the parties will go about litigating under the
terms of that statute. The parties may be uncertain whether the statutory regime
applies to their contract, but that is the problem addressed in Part IV.B.1., and is not
of any additional concern for purposes of this section.
331 See, e.g., In the Matter of BT Securities Corp., Exchange Act Release No.
35,136, [1994-95 Transfer Binder] Fed. Sec. L. Rep. (CCH) P 85,477, at 86114 (Dec.
22, 1994) (assuming that Bankers Trust violated the securities and commodities
laws without finding explicitly that the interest rate swaps Bankers Trust sold were
securities or commodities).
332 These claims also may include state statute-based claims. See supra notes
316-324 and accompanying text (describing New York anti-gambling statutes and
relevant derivatives). For a description of some of the common law arguments by
practitioners in derivatives cases through 1997, see Aaron Rubinstein, Derivatives
and Risk Management: Common Law Theories of Liability in Derivatives Litigation,
66 FORDHAM L. REV. 737 (1997).
333 See, e.g., Joanne Medero, et al., Investing in Derivatives: Current Litigation
Issues, 8 INSIGHTS 4 (Nov. 1994) (noting that complaints include “claims for
common law fraud, negligence, negligent misrepresentation, and breach of fiduciary
duty” as well as claims under section 10(b) of the Securities Exchange Act, Sections
11 and 12(2) of the Securities Act, and various sections of the Investment Company
Act). Another potential ground for recovery is commercial frustration or
impracticability, based on unanticipated changes in one or more of the instrument or
indices underlying a particular derivatives contract. See, e.g., Aluminum Co. of
America v. Essex Group, Inc., 499 F. Supp. 53 (W.D. Pa. 1980) (purpose of contract
based on wholesale price index was commercially frustrated by unexpected increases
in the price of oil).
68 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
decisions to guide future parties. Facts are difficult to ascertain.
Complaints often do not describe the underlying transactions
accurately.334 Neither do the paltry number of judicial opinions.
Jurisdictional battles are fierce, and costly.335 Documents are not
available, or are under seal. Much important evidence is destroyed or
is otherwise unavailable by the time discovery begins.336 The result is
an expensive, inefficient, unfair, and uncertain process.
334 The parties and their lawyers may not completely understand the
transactions. See, e.g., STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 78 (“OTC products can be
complex enough to raise questions about how well understood they are even by
experienced corporate treasurers. There is an associated uncertainty about the value
of complex products for which there is no market.”).
335 For example, Judge Feikens held in Procter & Gamble v. Bankers Trust that
because the parties agreed to be bound by New York statutes and case law, there was
no claim under Ohio statutes, and therefore dismissed such claims. See Procter &
Gamble, supra note 217, at 1289. This ruling was not particularly controversial,
although it shows that federal judges are willing to defer to private choice of law
provisions, even when one party may have violated the law of that court’s
jurisdiction. (Note that this deference would be critical to the survival of a synthetic
common law regime. Although federal courts would retain limited judicial review of
synthetic common law dispute resolution, courts would need to show deference to
private parties’ choice of regime, even if one party acted contrary to federal or state
law.)
Several derivatives cases have presented difficult jurisdictional issues. When
Societe Nationale D’Expoitation Industrielle Des Tabacs (SEITA), the French
national tobacco company, filed suit against Salomon Brothers International
Limited, the London arm of a U.S. investment bank, in the Southern District of New
York, Judge Sweet dismissed the claim for lack of subject matter jurisdiction,
because the alleged fraudulent representations were made in London and “[a]s a
French corporation headquartered in Paris, SEITA relied on the alleged
misrepresentations, executed the Swaps, and realized its losses in Paris.” Societe
Nationale D’Exploitation Industrielle Des Tabacs et Allumettes v. Salomon Brothers
International Limited, No. 95-Civ-9484 (S.D.N.Y. 1996). SEITA subsequently sued
in New York Supreme Court. I served as a consultant to SEITA during a portion of
the litigation. In a more recent case, Merrill Lynch International moved to dismiss a
complaint by Slovnaft A.S., the former Slovak national oil company, on grounds of
forum non conveniens, claiming the parties had no New York interests and had
agreed to resolve any disputes in English courts. See Merrill Lynch Seeks Dismissal,
supra note 446, at 10. When PT Dharmala Sakti Sejahtera, an Indonesian financial
services company, sued Bankers Trust, arguing it was not obligated to pay for losses
on a complex derivative because it had not fully understood the transaction, see
Bankers Trust Int’l PLC v. PT Dharmala Sakti Sejahtera, Queen’s Bench Division
(Commercial Court) (Dec. 1, 1995), an Indonesian court ruled in favor of Dharmala,
but the case was transferred to a British court, which ruled that Dharmala was capable
of understanding the risks involved in the transaction. See id. The parties later
settled the dispute. Chase Manhattan Bank recently moved to dismiss on the basis
of forum non conveniens two complaints filed in the Southern District of New York
by two Liberian companies acting on behalf of Greek individuals, arguing that New
York was an inconvenient forum because witnesses and documents are in Europe,
and that the parties chose English law to govern their investments. See Briefs
Submitted on Motion to Dismiss Suit Against Chase Manhattan, 6 ANDREW’S
DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., July 3, 2000, at 5, 7. The suit and motion obviously were
motivated by the availability in the U.S. of punitive damages and liberal discovery.
This motion was pending as of August 2000.
336 For example, tape recordings of incriminating conversations were of critical
importance in the litigation against Bankers Trust. See BT Securities, supra note
331, at 86114; see also Donald C. Langevoort, Selling Hope, Selling Risk: Some
Lessons for Law from Behavioral Economics About Stockbrokers and Sophisticated
Customers, 84 CALIF. L. REV. 627, 627-28 n.1 (1996) (discussing and quoting
conversations among BT Securities employees). However, banks have learned from
Bankers Trust’s mistakes, and now either do not record conversations or set up
systems to erase or destroy the tapes within a relatively short period of time as a
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
69
Breach of Fiduciary Duty
One of the core common law claims in financial disputes has been
breach of fiduciary duty.337 However, the derivatives cases on
fiduciary duty have been so conflicted, muddled, and restrictive that
many plaintiffs are now choosing not to include fiduciary duty claims
in their complaints, in large part to avoid the cost associated with
resolving complex motions to dismiss, and for strategic reasons to
avoid early partial dismissal, which now seems likely given recent
cases.
Fiduciaries and fiduciary concepts have a long history in the law,
beginning in the Roman law.338 Yet there is no clear definition of a
fiduciary or a fiduciary relationship. As Justice Frankfurter famously
put it, “to say that a man is a fiduciary only begins analysis; it gives
direction to further inquiry. To whom is he a fiduciary? What
obligations does he owe as a fiduciary?”339 These inquiries rarely lead
to clear answers.
In recent years, fiduciary notions have become hopelessly
muddled in many areas of law. The term fiduciary is infused with the
concept of trust; a fiduciary holds something in trust for another. But
the term also includes notions of power and duty; a fiduciary
relationship is created when one person is given power, and the duty
to use that power to help another person.340 The term fiduciary is an
objective notion; a person either is a fiduciary or is not and fiduciary
duties may be triggered or halted341 based on certain objective
standards of conduct or behavior.342
routine business practice. In one recent case, the plaintiffs requested additional
depositions because the defendant bank allegedly had erased tape recordings related
to the relevant swap transactions. See Seita Claims SBIL Destroyed Tapes;
‘Nonsense,’ Salomon Says, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., May 7, 1998, at 9.
337 In contrast to the stock markets, where most breach of fiduciary duty claims
arise in the context of shareholder suits against managers and directors, most of the
breach of fiduciary claims in the derivatives context have been by one party to a
derivatives contract alleging a breach of fiduciary duty by the other, not by
shareholders alleging breach of fiduciary duties by managers. There are some such
shareholder-against-management cases, however. For example, in the litigation
related to Orange County’s losses on derivatives, shareholders of Merrill Lynch &
Co. sued the company’s directors in New York state court for breach of fiduciary
duty to Merrill and its shareholders. However, the suit was dismissed because
shareholders failed to support their assertion that a pre-suit demand on the board
would have been futile. See Wilson et al. v. Tully et al. and Merrill Lynch & Co., No.
619-2-61903 (N.Y. Sup. Ct., App. Div. June 18, 1998); Shareholder Suit Against
Merrill Lynch Dismissed for Failure to Make Pre-Suit Demand, PROFESSIONAL
LIABILITY LITIG. REPTR., Aug. 1999, at 10. For a discussion of such suits based on
hedging decisions by managers, see Kimberly D. Krawiec, Derivatives, Corporate
Hedging, and Shareholder Wealth: Modigliani-Miller Forty Years Later, 1998 U.
ILL. L. REV. 1039, 1102-04 (1998); see also George Crawford, A Fiduciary Duty to
Use Derivatives?, 1 STAN. J.L. BUS. & FIN. 307, 329-30 (1995).
338 The term fiduciary is derived from the Roman law. In general, a fiduciary was
a person holding the character of a trustee. For example, a fiduciary heir (fiduciaries
h?res) was the person who was instituted heir and who was charged to deliver the
succession to a person designated by the testament. A fiducia was an early form of
mortgage under Roman law. See BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 563-64 (5th ed. 1979).
339 SEC v. Chenery Corp., 318 U.S. 80, 85-86 (1943).
340 J. SHEPHERD, LAW OF FIDUCIARIES 97 (1981).
341 There is no fixed scale for measuring fiduciary duty, although the courts
have balanced allowing fiduciaries to act or transact with protecting shareholders.
See ARTHUR R. PINTO & DOUGLAS M. BRANSON, UNDERSTANDING CORPORATE LAW 182
70 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
For example, much of corporate law is fiduciary duty law.
Corporate law says that directors and officers of corporations – and
sometimes shareholders – are in a fiduciary relationship with their
corporation and its shareholders. Many corporate law scholars view
fiduciary duty simply as a gap filler. As two leading corporate law
scholars have noted, “[c]orporate law – and in particular the fiduciary
principle enforced by courts – fills in the blanks and oversights with
the terms that people would have bargained for had they anticipated
the problems and been able to transact costlessly in advance.”343
With this uncertainty about fiduciary duty as a backdrop, parties
began adding breach of fiduciary duty claims to their derivatives
complaints. The results of combining fiduciary duty claims with the
facts of complex derivatives have been abysmal, as one might expect,
given the complexity surrounding each notion independently.
The first judge to consider in detail a breach of fiduciary duty
claim by a derivatives purchaser against a seller was Judge John
Feikens of the Southern District of Ohio in the suit brought by
Procter & Gamble against Bankers Trust in 1994.344 Although most
scholars have focused on the federal securities and commodities claims
in P&G’s complaint, the complaint also included a variety of state
common law claims – fraud, misrepresentation, breach of fiduciary
duty, negligence, and negligent misrepresentation – in addition to
numerous federal statutory claims.345 These claims are of great
interest and relevance here.346
(1999); see also Guth v. Loft, 5. A.2d 503 (Del. 1961) (indicating that fiduciary
duties are subject to “no fixed scale.”).
342 Interestingly, the term fiduciary also refers to the system of marking in the
reticule of an optical instrument used as a reference point or a measuring scale. See
WEBSTER’S II NEW RIVERSIDE DICTIONARY 475 (1984).
343 Frank H. Easterbrook & Daniel R. Fischel, Contractual Freedom in
Corporate Law: Articles and Comments; The Corporate Contract, 89 COLUM. L. REV.
1416, 1444-45 (1989). The hypothetical bargain approach of corporate law assumes
that managers and shareholders have symmetric information. Fiduciary duty default
rules thus are intended to ameliorate asymmetric information that actually persists.
It is necessary to impose duties on management, because it is the rule shareholders
and managers would have agreed to absent transaction costs, i.e., it is the rule
necessary to resolve the information asymmetry between shareholders and
management. If management has superior information, the argument goes, fiduciary
duty rules are necessary to prevent management from using such information to
exploit shareholders.
344 See Procter & Gamble, supra note 217. Judge Feikens’s opinion remains one
of the most thorough and well-reasoned judicial considerations of any derivatives
claim to date, although many regard as dicta the discussion in that case of state
common law claims.
345 The federal statutory claims included alleged violations of Section 17 of the
Securities Act of 1933, Section 10(b) and Rule 10b-5 of the Securities Exchange Act
of 1934, and Sections 4b and 4o of the Commodity Exchange Act, and Section 32.9
of the Rules of the Commodity Futures Trading Commission. See Procter & Gamble,
supra note 217, at 1274. P&G also included claims based on Ohio state law,
including violation of Ohio Blue Sky Laws and the Ohio Deceptive Trade Practices
Act. See id. Gibson Greetings, Inc., a manufacturer of greeting cards, filed a suit
alleging similar state common law claims against Bankers Trust on September 12,
1994. See Gibson Greetings, Inc. v. Bankers Trust Co., 925 F. Supp. 1270 (S.D. Ohio
1994).
346 At the time, there already existed a body of statutory law and common law
cases for use in resolving the federal claims. However, the state common law claims
were novel in the derivatives context, and to some extent still are.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
71
P&G alleged that BT had not adequately explained the risks
inherent in swap transactions P&G entered into with the bank. In
each case, the swap payments were based on complex formulas, and
consisted in economic terms of a portfolio of forward and option
contracts. Because of leverage, the bets embedded in the swap
contracts were very large, approaching the size of the entire issue of a
U.S. government bond of comparable maturity. Moreover, the swap
contracts were designed in a way that masked the size of the exposure
on the contract, although the terms of the contract clearly specified
its payouts and a sophisticated party would have been able to analyze
the swap’s exposure. In addition, there were recordings of BT
salespeople discussing misrepresentations related to such swap
valuations. The suit was settled well before trial, with P&G agreeing
to pay $35 million of roughly $200 million it owed.347
P&G contended that a fiduciary relationship existed between it
and BT. Judge Feikens granted BT’s motion for summary judgment as
to P&G’s claim of breach of fiduciary duty, but noted that “[t]his
does not mean, however, that there are no duties and obligations in
their swaps transactions.”348 It is difficult to interpret this sweeping
statement. How are market participants to know if the seller bank
owes a fiduciary duty of any kind or scope? Did P&G’s size or
sophistication matter to this determination? Was the nature of the
relationship between P&G and BT a factor? Was the swap’s structure
relevant? Was the fact that a swap was individually tailored to a
particular counterparty evidence that the purchaser was receiving
some special treatment? Although this Ohio decision did not bind
other courts outside of Ohio deciding breach of fiduciary duty claims
under New York law, it did create uncertainty for future cases.
In a more recent, similar, case involving a more complex product
sold to a less sophisticated purchaser, a New York state court also
rejected a breach of fiduciary duty claim. In 1994 and 1995, Societe
Nationale D’Expoitation Industrielle Des Tabacs (SEITA), the French
national tobacco company, lost $29 million on two swap transactions
it entered into with Salomon Brothers International Limited
(SBIL).349 According to the allegations, a SBIL salesman in London,
Gilles Albou, acted fraudulently and concealed certain risks in order to
convince former SEITA treasurer, Marc Tardieu, that he could make
millions of dollars for his company by investing in two swaps.350
Thus, the facts resembled those of the earlier P&G case. SBIL,
like BT, ran a sophisticated derivatives trading operation, while
SEITA, like P&G, obviously was less sophisticated. SEITA had far
less experience with derivatives than P&G, which had been trading
billions of dollars of derivative instruments for several years.351 The
derivative SEITA purchased was a complex swap that SBIL had
designed in a way that masked both its size and risk, and that a
347 Gibson agreed to pay $6.18 million of roughly $20 million it owed to BT.
See Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 5 (describing resolution of Procter &
Gamble and Gibson Greetings cases).
348 Id. at 1289.
349 See SD NY Denies French Firm Federal Jurisdiction for Suit over U.S.
Swaps, ANDREW’S DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., July 8, 1996, at 3.
350 One swap was tied to the German mark; the other was tied to the Japanese
yen. See id.
351 See Partnoy, FIASCO, supra note 323, at 94.
72 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
sophisticated buyer might have understood fully, but that SEITA
likely did not. The instrument SEITA purchased involved a portfolio
of digital (or binary) options,352 and therefore was more difficult to
evaluate than P&G’s swap with BT. New York law applied in both
cases, although SEITA’s suit was in state court in New York, not in
Ohio.353
In deciding SBIL’s motion for summary judgment, Judge Charles
Edward Ramos found that SEITA was a sophisticated counterparty to
the swap and granted summary judgment to SBIL on the fiduciary duty
claim.354 Unfortunately, Judge Ramos did not clarify the coverage of
the P&G case, except to note in passing that a large French tobacco
company is a sophisticated party and was aware of the risks involved;
BT had made similar arguments in the prior case.355
At best, Judge Ramos’s five-paragraph discussion of fiduciary duty
in his opinion is of little or no value to other participants in the
derivatives industry. It fails to articulate any general principles of
law, to analyze existing precedents in other areas, to explain what
facts were important to the decision, or even to set forth the nature
of the transaction in any comprehensible detail. It provides roughly
the same guidance that the judge in Holmes’s story provided by
explaining he could not find applicable law dealing with churns.
At worst, Judge Ramos’s cursory dismissal of the claim is very
costly. Judge Ramos’s opinion has generated great uncertainty among
participants in the derivatives industry, who cannot understand from
the opinion when, if ever, a counterparty to a derivative contract
would be able to survive a summary judgment motion. The New York
Appellate Division, First Department, did not help matters, affirming
the decision with little additional guidance.356 The decisions’ naked
rejection of fiduciary duty claims seem to have scared plaintiffs from
including such claims in their complaints, a result that even
contractarian legal scholars should find difficult to justify based on the
historical treatment of fiduciary duty claims as gap-fillers in at least
some circumstances.
Recent federal cases also provide little guidance.357 The law in
the Second Circuit, the leading court for business disputes, regarding
352 Digital options either pay a fixed or sum or zero (i.e., have a discontinuous
payoff), depending on some contingency. See WILMOTT, supra note 227, at 34-35.
353 SEITA had sued first in federal court in New York, but that suit was
dismissed on jurisdictional grounds. See supra note 349. SEITA’s state court suit
also included other common law claims, including fraud. Societe Nationale
D’Exploitation Industrielle Des Tabacs et Allumettes v. Salomon Brothers Int’l Ltd.,
Index No. 113154/96 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Feb. 9, 1998).
354 See id. Ultimately, the judge dismissed SEITA’s other claims, too.
355 See id. at *6.
356 See Societe Nationale D’Exploitation Industrielle Des Tabacs et Allumettes
v. Salomon Brothers Int’l Ltd., 2000 N.Y. App. Div. LEXIS 5004 (N.Y. App. Div. 1st
Dep’t April 27, 2000) (denying without opinion leave to appeal to the New York
Court of Appeals). The First Department of the New York Appellate Division
previously noted that it did not subscribe to the articulation of New York law in the
P&G case, although it left open the possibility of finding something more than a
“business relationship” in future cases, thereby creating additional uncertainty. See
Societe Nationale D’Exploitation Industrielle Des Tabacs et Allumettes v. Salomon
Brothers Int’l Ltd., 674 N.Y.S.2d 648, 649 ((N.Y. App. Div. 1st Dep’t June 16, 1998).
357 A few cases have attempted to resolve these issues under federal statutory
law. See, e.g., Banca Cremi, S.A. v. Alex. Brown & Sons, Inc., 132 F.3d 1017 (4th Cir.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
73
fiduciary duties owed by brokers to clients is hopelessly muddled.358
For example, in Independent Order of Foresters v. Donaldson, Lufkin
& Jenrette, Inc.,359 the Second Circuit upheld the dismissal of a
complaint, noting that that where there were insufficient allegations
to support a finding of any broader duties, a broker owes a client only
limited duties with respect to a non-discretionary account.360
However, in interpreting Independent Order of Foresters and a
similar, later Second Circuit case,361 Judge Koeltl, in Kwiatkowski v.
Bear Stearns (Kwiatkowski II),362 held it remains clear that the
“relationship between a broker and its client is fiduciary in nature and
that duties broader than those related to the execution of a
transaction may arise as a result of the particular relationship between
the broker and the client and the scope of the matters with which the
broker is entrusted.”363 The catch phrase noting the existence of a
fiduciary duty, but limiting its scope to “matters relevant to affairs
entrusted to the broker” appears in numerous recent cases in the
Second Circuit.364
The results in the cases are difficult to reconcile. Consider, for
example, the differences between the allegations in Press v. Chemical
Investment Services Corp.365 and Independent Order of Foresters on
one hand, and Kwiatkowski II on the other. In Press, the broker failed
to disclose a substantial markup on the sale of a Treasury Bill. In
Independent Order of Foresters, the broker failed to explain the risks
1997) (evaluating claim related to investment in mortgage derivatives under federal
law).
358 To complicate the analysis further, there also are other, sometime
contradictory, lines of cases on fiduciary duty in New York. One line holds that
absent a showing of “special circumstances” that could have transformed a business
relationship into a fiduciary relationship, a court will dismiss a claim for fiduciary
duty; such “special circumstances” can include control by one party of the other, or
creation of an agency relationship. See, e.g., L. Magarian & Co. v. Timberland Co.,
665 N.Y.S.2d 413, 414 (1997) (citing cases for both sets of “special circumstances”
and, finding neither, dismissing the complaint). Another holds that generally the
legal relationship between customer and bank is arm’s length, but that a fiduciary
relationship may arise when the bank “assumes control and responsibility” over the
customer’s assets, or when the customer “places special trust and confidence in the
bank and thereby becomes dependent on it.” ADT Operations, Inc. v. Chase
Manhattan Bank, 662 N.Y.S.2d 190, 192-93 (1997). There are separate, related cases,
involving insurance companies. See, e.g., Goshen v. Mutual Life Ins. Co. of New
York, 1997 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 486, at *34 (Sup. Ct. N.Y. Oct. 24, 1997) (citing both
“special trust and confidence” and “dependence” prongs of the banking fiduciary
duty test).
359 See Independent Order of Foresters v. Donaldson, Lufkin & Jenrette, Inc., 157
F.3d 933 (2d Cir. 1998). This case involved the appeal of the dismissal of breach of
fiduciary duty claims by a fraternal society that issued insurance policies and
annuities to its members and had invested in certain derivatives. Id.
360 These duties include, for example, a duty to notify a customer before making
trades where authorization is required, and a duty to execute requested trades. See id.
at 940.
361 See Press v. Chemical Investment Services Corp., 166 F.3d 529, 536-37 (2d
Cir. 1999) (attempting to reconcile the notion that the broker owes no fiduciary duty
to the client with the notion that a broker’s fiduciary duty to a client is limited to
“matters relevant to affairs entrusted with the broker”).
362 Kwiatkowski v. Bear, Stearns & Co., 1999 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 19966, (S.D.N.Y.
Dec. 29, 1999) (“Kwiakowski II”).
363 See id. at *29
364 See Press, supra note 361, at 537; Rush v. Oppenheimer & Co., 681 F. Supp.
1045, 1055 (S.D.N.Y. 1988); Kwiatkowski II, supra note 362, at *31.
365 See Press, supra note 361.
74 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
associated with several complex transactions to a “fraternal society.”
In Kwiatkowski II, the broker liquidated the client’s positions in a
downward-moving market in order to avoid unsecured losses. In the
first two cases, the fiduciary duty claim was dismissed; in the third, it
was upheld.
Is it possible to say that secretly adding a substantial mark-up to a
virtually risk-free transaction or failing to advise a less sophisticated
party about a complex instrument is not a “matter relevant to affairs
entrusted to the broker,” but that liquidating a client’s positions in a
volatile market is? The rationale for fiduciary duty traditionally has
been based on the information or sophistication gap between parties.
It is difficult to understand how this gap varied in the three cases, and
the courts do not attempt to address the difficulty. There certainly is
no explanation, for example, of how the plaintiff in Kwiatkowski II,
but not in the other cases, could or would have bargained for fiduciary
protection absent transaction costs.
It is worth setting forth in greater detail some of the facts and
analysis in Kwiatkowski II, to demonstrate how difficult it is for a
judge to resolve a fiduciary duty claim in a complex financial
dispute.366 Before 1990, when he opened a foreign currency trading
account at Bear, Stearns, Henryk de Kwiatkowski, a wealthy individual
investor,367 had engaged in hundreds of millions of dollars of foreign
currency transactions through his bank in the Bahamas, Bank Leu.368
Bear, Stearns made standard form disclosures in which Kwiatkowski
acknowledged the risk of trading in foreign currency futures, and
Kwiatkowski then began trading billions of dollars worth of currency
futures on the Chicago Mercantile Exchange (CME).369 As
Kwiatkowski’s positions increased during late 1994, they became too
large for the CME,370 and on December 6 and 7, 1994, Bear, Stearns
transferred one half of his positions to the OTC derivatives
market.371 Although Kwiatkowski was making money in late 1994,
on December 28, 1994, the dollar weakened dramatically and he lost
$112 million in a few hours. Kwiatkowski posted margin for these
losses and other losses during the following several weeks.372
More than a month later, Kwiatkowski acknowledged in writing
that he was an “eligible swap participant” with total assets exceeding
$10 million and that he was familiar with foreign currency
366 Moreover, Kwiatkowski II is one of the few cases from which parties can
glean the relevant facts. In other cases, facts are missing, either because the judge
decided to omit them (or could not understand and articulate them), or because the
facts were under seal or subject to a confidentiality order. See, e.g., SEITA, supra
note (limited recitation of facts does not even include a description of the
transaction).
367 In 1991, Kwiatkowski had a net worth of $100 million. See Kwiatkowski II,
supra note 362, at *7.
368 See id. at *6.
369 See id. at *6-11.
370 At one point, Kwiatkowski’s positions constituted substantial percentages
of the December 1994 contracts available for trading on the CME. See id. at *11. The
court recognized that “the OTC market is a much larger market than the CME, with
more participants trading more currency” and that “[t]he OTC market is also more
liquid than the CME and it allows a large investor to liquidate a large position with
less impact on the market than would be the case on the CME.” Id. at *11-12.
371 See id. at *11.
372 See id. at *13-14.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
75
transactions.373 Bear, Stearns would have sought this
acknowledgment to satisfy the Part 35 swaps exemption,374 although
the hints at some uncertainty about the exemption. In early March
1995 the dollar declined in value again, and Bear, Stearns – facing a
potentially unsecured loss – liquidated all of Kwiatkowski’s
positions.375 Kwiatkowski alleged that he lost more than $300
million because of this hurried liquidation.376
Consider the array of questions raised in Kwiatkowski II. What
facts are relevant in deciding whether or not a purchaser of
derivatives is sophisticated? Does it matter that the purchaser is an
individual, as opposed to an institution? Does it matter that the
purchaser is not from the U.S.? Is the amount of the seller’s profit
from the sale of the derivatives relevant?377 How and why? What is
the relevance of standard form disclosures or disclaimers? Do they
insulate a seller from liability? What is the effect of the (delayed)
Part 35 acknowledgment? Does it matter if the disputed transaction
was economically equivalent to a transaction that would not have
generated losses?378 Finally, how should a judge distinguish among
federal statutory claims and state common law claims when there is
extensive overlap and some common elements.379 (Kwiatkowski’s
claims included fraud, negligent misrepresentation, breach of
373 See id. at *12.
374 See discussion supra at notes 279-287 and accompanying text.
375 Interestingly, Bear, Stearns seems to have liquidated Kwiatkowski’s
positions on Sunday, March 5, 1995, a day the CME was not open. See id. at *14-15.
The court did not discuss this fact.
376 See id. at *15. An expert for Kwiatkowski testified that even if Kwiatkowski
had begun liquidating his positions by March 1, 1995 – a Wednesday, just four days
earlier, when the markets were more active – he would have reduced his losses by
$139 million. See id. at *20. Kwiatkowski claimed he had asked Bear, Stearns to
segregate his trading account from a larger account he was holding for his children;
instead, Bear, Stearns used the children’s account to provide leverage for the OTC
derivatives transactions. See Businessman’s $300M Fiduciary Claims Survive Bear
Stearns’ Summary Judgment Motion, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Jan. 24, 2000, at 3.
377 The seller’s profits may be relevant in several ways. First, if the profits were
very large and undisclosed, the buyer may have a claim to damages for a portion of
those profits. Second, a very large profit margin may be a sign that the buyer did not
understand the transaction; the argument is that if the buyer had been able to value
the transaction properly, it would not have paid such a large mark-up to the seller
(alternatively, if the buyer understood the terms of the transaction, a very large profit
margin is evidence that the transaction was risky or illiquid for the seller in ways the
buyer might not have known and that the seller might not have disclosed). Third,
the seller’s profits – and particularly the individual salesperson’s compensation and
incentive structure – are relevant to discerning the seller’s motivation to complete
the transaction: was this a standard transaction the seller entered into repeatedly
with other, similar counterparties, or was it a kind of “this will make my year”
transaction the seller only rarely was able to sell?
378 For example, an OTC derivative might be economically equivalent to an
exchange-traded derivative, but might nevertheless generate additional losses due to
illiquidity, large mark-ups, or other factors unique to the OTC markets.
379 In most derivatives complaints, as in most commercial complaints generally,
a long recitation of facts is followed by and incorporated into much shorter, often
boilerplate, recitations of the formal claims being made in the case. In many ways,
the quandary faced by a drafter of such a complaint is not so different from that faced
by lawyers centuries ago; the major difference is that the choices (e.g., breach of
fiduciary duty or negligent misrepresentation, as contrasted with early common law
forms of complaint, e.g., trespass) have changed.
76 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
contract,380 and claims under the Commodity Exchange Act,381 all of
which the court dismissed,382 as well as claims for breach of fiduciary
duty and negligence, which the court allowed to proceed.383). These
questions, though posed in every derivatives dispute including
Kwiatkowski II, remain unresolved.
Such questions are so difficult to answer in part because it is so
impossible to know how much a judge will understand about the
particular OTC derivatives market and transactions at issue. An
understanding of the market is important in answering questions about
a dispute. Justice Cardozo argued that fiduciary duty was closely
linked to custom and practice. He wrote, “Some relations in life
impose a duty to act in accordance with the customary morality and
nothing more. In those the customary morality must be the standard
for the judge.”384 Unfortunately, the “customary morality” in
derivatives markets is often complex, counterintuitive, and largely
unknown to judges. In many situations, the customary morality is
that derivatives counterparties owe each no duties at all. Certainly
the trillions of dollars of swap transactions between large banks do not
involve expectations of any such fiduciary duty. Yet in other
instances the customary morality is that such duties not only are
owed, but also are a precondition to the transaction. Derivatives
sellers treat less sophisticated customers differently than they treat
each other, for good reason. Less sophisticated derivatives purchasers
rely on sellers to help them understand and access complex
transactions. Such reliance is efficient; it would be too costly for
every derivatives purchaser to understand every nuance to every
transaction. As a result, sellers rationally should believe they owe
some such duties, and their customers should not be willing to buy
from them if they do not believe they were entitled to such duties.
The information and sophistication gap between purchasers and
sellers warrants a rule that the seller owes the buyer at least some
limited duty in some circumstances.
Yet the courts have not understood either the implications of the
“customary morality” of the derivatives industry or the traditional
analysis of fiduciary duty claims. Courts have recognized two poles of
fiduciary duty analysis: one where no duties are owed, another where
they are. The problem is that in derivatives cases, courts have not
clarified where the line is drawn. That failure to draw the line has
generated great uncertainty.
My point here is not necessarily that the line should be drawn in a
particular location as to fiduciary duty claims; I would hope that a
sophisticated, fully-informed judge with adequate time and resources
who engaged in a careful hypothetical bargain analysis could do a fine
380 The breach of contract claim alleged an oral agreement that was inconsistent
with the terms of a written Foreign Exchange Memorandum. See id. at *48.
381 Kwiatkowski’s CEA claims included a claim that Bear, Stearns had solicited
and dealt in illegal futures transactions. This claim, which was dismissed, would
have raised the complex web of issues discussed supra in Part III.A.
382 See Kwiatkowski v. Bear, Stearns Co., 1997 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 13078 (S.D.N.Y.
Aug. 29, 1997) (dismissing claims pursuant to Fed. R. Civ. P. 12(b)(6))
(“Kwiatkowski I”).
383 See Kwiatkowski II, supra note 367, at *2-3.
384 Benjamin Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process 152, in SELECTED
WRITINGS OF BENJAMIN NATHAN CARDOZO (Margaret E. Hall, ed. 1947).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
77
job. Instead, my point is that the common law has failed to draw such
a line at all. It may be that it is simply too difficult and costly for the
judges selected to hear the relatively small number of real adjudicated
derivatives disputes to draw these lines in the manner suggested here.
If so, the common of law of fiduciary duty as applied to derivatives-
related disputes may be doomed to uncertainty.
Fraud (and Negligent Misrepresentation)
Derivatives complaints also have include fraud and fraud-related
claims. Like fiduciary duty analysis, the treatment of fraud has deep
historical roots. The common law of fraud is relatively easy to
describe, even if results in individual cases are no easier to predict.
Fraud involves reliance by one party to its detriment on a
material misstatement made by the other party. Fraud in the
derivatives context can be relatively easy to assess. Consider, for
example, the 1994 civil cases brought by the government against
Bankers Trust.385 In related cases, the SEC and CFTC found Bankers
Trust had committed fraud in its dealings with Gibson Greetings and
fined the bank $10 million, in part because the derivatives were too
complicated for Gibson Greetings employees to understand, and in
part because Banker Trust employees misrepresented the value of the
derivatives at various points.386 Similarly, the fraud claims involved
in cases filed by several Korean institutions against Morgan Guaranty
involved complex facts, but required relatively simple analysis.387
However, the fact that fraud claims in derivatives cases might not
be complex analytically does not necessarily mean they will be simple
to resolve. The question remains what facts support a claim of fraud,
and because the facts in derivatives cases can be difficult, so can the
resolution of a fraud claim.
For example, Martin A. Armstrong, president of Princeton
Economics International Ltd., was a defendant in several cases related
to hundreds of millions of dollars of losses on structured notes388
Princeton sold. Japan-based Amada Co. and its subsidiaries bought
$123 million of these notes from Princeton.389 Amada alleged that
Princeton falsely represented that the notes’ value was based on
Princeton’s holdings of AAA-rated U.S. government securities.
Amada sued in the Southern District of New York, claiming violations
of federal securities laws, common law fraud, breach of fiduciary duty,
and unjust enrichment.
The resolution of Amada’s fraud claim depends not on any
difficulties related to the law of fraud, but to complex fact questions
related to Princeton’s representations. The key facts involve the
385 See BT Securities Corp., Exch. Act. Rel. No. 35, 136 [1994-95 Tr. Binder] Fed.
Sec. L. Rep. (CCH) (Dec. 22, 1994); BT Securities Corp., CFTC Docket No. 95-a, app.
A, at 2 (Dec. 22, 1994). In those cases, tape recordings indicated that BT employees
had lied about material elements of the transactions, including how they should be
evaluated over time. Given such evidence, a fraud case can be simple, even in the
derivatives context.
386 See id.
387 See discussion infra at notes 392-406 and accompanying text.
388 Structured notes are a type of derivative instrument in which the payments of
the note are linked to one or more variables using mathematical formulas. See
Partnoy, Regulatory Arbitrage, supra note 5., at 220-21.
389 See Japanese Company Sues NY Bank for $123M Alleging Investment Fraud,
BANK & LENDER LIAB. REPTR., Jan. 19, 2000, at 5.
78 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
nature of the AAA-rated U.S. government securities that formed the
basis of the deals. Before the development of structured notes, the
moniker “AAA-rated U.S. government security” indicated a safe, low
risk investment. That indication is no longer true. Instead, such a
label now says virtually nothing about the market risk of an
instrument: AAA relates only to credit risk and can mask all sorts of
non-credit-related risks.390 Highly-rated issuers, including the U.S.
government and its agencies, issue securities with a wide variety of
market risk and leverage.391
Among the most prominent recent fraud cases in the derivatives
area involve are a series of suits filed in the Southern District of New
York arising out of losses sustained by several Korean entities on
purchases from Morgan Guaranty392 of derivative instruments linked
to the currency of Thailand, known as the baht. A brief recitation of
some publicly available facts from the cases will show how complex
even a relatively simple fraud case can become in the derivatives
context.393
In 1997, Morgan Guaranty arranged a series of complex
derivatives transactions for SK Securities and several other Korean
counterparties. The transactions involved the establishment of
Malaysian special purpose investment funds394 that borrowed money
to purchase units of a Korean trust, which then used the proceeds to
purchase Korean stocks, bonds, or complex derivatives. The loans
were to be repaid through a series of one-year-maturity total return
swap transactions.395 At the termination of these swaps, Morgan
Guaranty was to sell the trust units and pay the Malaysian funds the
value of those units plus (or minus) an amount to be determined by
reference to a formula based on a comparison of the prices of the
Thai baht and Japanese yen currencies to the U.S. dollar at the dates
of inception and termination of the underlying agreement,396 as well
as the value of the underlying stocks, bonds, or other derivatives.
Needless to say, the derivatives transactions were far from “plain
vanilla” interest rate swaps.
390 See Frank Partnoy, The Siskel and Ebert of Financial Markets: Two Thumbs
Down for the Credit Rating Agencies, 77 Wash. U. L. Q. # (1999).
391 See id. at #.
392 Morgan Guaranty is a U.S.-based lending institution and a subsidiary of J.P.
Morgan, a large U.S. commercial bank and one of the leading participants in the
derivatives market. I served as a consultant to certain Korean entities during
portions of this litigation.
393 Some of the details of these transactions are described in complaints
available through Andrew’s Derivatives Litigation Reporter. See, e.g, Second
Amended Complaint, Korea Life Ins. Co. v. Morgan Guaranty Trust Co., 99 Civ.
12175 (May 17, 2000), available at 6 DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., July 3, 2000, at A1-
A11.
394 In the derivatives market, it is very common for transactions to involve so-
called “special purpose” entities, which are established solely for the purpose of a
given transaction or group of transactions. See Partnoy, Regulatory Arbitrage,
supra note 5, at 221-22. Such special purpose entities typically are needed so the
transaction is in compliance with, or takes advantage of, a particular regulation. See
id.
395 In a total return swap, one party pays or receives the total return on some
asset in exchange for paying or receive a pre-specified periodic amount.
396 Robert W. McSherry, Candlelight, Midnight Sessions, and Dealings in the
Dark: SD NY Transcript Outlines the Road to a “Complex” Settlement, SEC. LITIG. &
REG. REPTR., Nov. 10, 1999, at 13.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
79
After the Thai baht collapsed on July 2, 1997,397 the valuation of
the total return swaps moved dramatically against the Korean parties,
and in favor of Morgan. Because the Malaysian companies involved
had been created only for purposes of this transaction, and therefore
had no other assets, Morgan looked to the Korean companies and to
four Korean guarantors to pay on the swaps.398 The Korean entities
refused to pay, and litigation ensued.
On February 10, 1998, two of the losing parties sued Morgan
Guaranty in the Southern District of New York, alleging violations of
federal securities laws; a few days later, Morgan Guaranty sued in the
same court, alleging breach of contract.399 The Korean entities
alleged that Morgan concealed information about the transactions,
including its insider knowledge that the Thai central bank was
preparing to allow the baht to devalue. Thus, the claims sounded in
fraud.
Although numerous issues in the case were complex, one appeared
to be quite simple. One of the Korean guarantor banks, Housing &
Commercial Bank (HCB), alleged that Morgan had inserted new pages
into an already-initialed document, thereby changing HCB’s limited
397 There have been several substantial disputes over derivatives losses in Asia,
including numerous losses related to the Thai baht collapse and ensuing crisis in
Asia. This collapse in foreign exchange rates triggered a second wave of derivatives
disputes, in the same way the increase in short-term interest rates in early 1994
triggered the first wave. The companies losing large amounts of money on
derivatives included Japanese companies such as Yakult Honsha, a maker of
fermented beverages, Alps Electric, a maker of electronics parts, and Aoyama Trading,
a fashion retailer, and Showa Shell Sekiyu K.K, an oil refiner; several large
Indonesian corporate groups, including the Indah Kiat, Sinar Mas., and Tanoto
groups, and several companies and corporate groups in Korea, Thailand, and
Malaysia. See Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 6-7 (describing details of losses).
Japanese companies in particular incurred large losses from derivative contracts,
although many of these losses were not caused by any market movements, but were
actually the losses associated with gains previously recognized on mirror derivative
contracts. In the mid-1990s, Japanese companies were notorious for engaging in
sham transactions that generated immediate false accounting profits, pushing the
corresponding losses to a future date. The losses recognized by many of these
companies were simply the inevitable losses associated with the previous false
accounting gains. For a detailed description of such transactions, see Partnoy,
F.I.A.S.C.O., supra note 323, Ch. 10.
Japanese regulatory authorities encouraged these sham transactions during the
1990s, perhaps because they believed accurate disclosure of the companies’ poor
financial condition would have hurt the economy, perhaps because they believed the
economy might improve, thereby reducing future losses. In any event the regulators
abruptly changed position in 1998, even suspending one non-Japanese bank’s
license for selling such transactions: “Beginning in 1998, however, the financial
authorities changed their regulatory posture on window dressing transactions.
Responding to both international and domestic pressure to address the problems in
the country’s banking system, the regulators determined that window dressing was
an inappropriate practice. Because of the ambiguity of the legal and accounting
framework for financial derivatives in Japan, this policy shift was possible without
any change or amendment to any regulation and without providing market
participants with any advance notice. The most dramatic result of this policy was the
severe penalties imposed on Credit Suisse.” Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 29
(footnotes omitted). Such an abrupt change in position adds to the regulatory
uncertainty concerning financial derivatives.
398 The four Korean guarantors were SK Securities, Hannam Investment
Securities, Housing & Commercial Bank, and Boram Bank. See id.
399 See id; see also J.P. Morgan Sues S. Korean Banks, Securities Firm Over
Derivatives Deals, SEC. REG. & L. REP., Feb. 20, 1998, at 282.
80 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
guarantee of $50 million to an unlimited guarantee.400 (The losses
greatly exceeded $50 million.) Such straightforward allegations, if
true, established a relatively simple case of fraud. The allegations
involving the other banks were more complex, but also included fraud.
However, the Korean entities and Morgan had ongoing business
relationships,401 and were able to agree to settle several of the
cases.402 Obviously, HCB was assisted in its settlement negotiations
by the fact that it was able to allege a relatively simple fraud case.403
However, note how little value the litigation and settlement of
these complex claims generated for participants in the derivatives
market. Parties to the case, and more importantly their attorneys,
may have intuited a sense of how the judge in the cases, Alvin K.
Hellerstein, might rule in future cases. Although confidentiality
orders governed the dispute, sufficient facts became public to give
non-parties some sense of the factual basis for the fraud claims. But
because the parties settled the case subject to a confidentiality
agreement, Judge Hellerstein’s role was simply to grant the stipulated
dismissal404 without a detailed opinion. Neither he nor any other
judge in New York would be bound by his actions in this series of
cases. Nor would any future party benefit from any wisdom or
judgment Judge Hellerstein accumulated during the litigation.
Notwithstanding millions of dollars of legal fees spent to resolve one
of the largest derivatives disputes in history, the result was absolutely
no common law – not a single legal rule – of use to future parties.
Not every Korean entity settled its claims, and there are ongoing
disputes involving Morgan, so there is some chance a common law
precedent still will be established. In a related case also before Judge
Hellerstein, Korea Life Insurance Co. (KLI) sued Morgan Guaranty
for fraud, unjust enrichment, frustration of commercial purpose,
negligent misrepresentation, lack of authority, breach of the duty of
good faith and fair dealing, and violation of the New York gaming
laws.405 In this suit, KLI seeks approximately $100 million in
damages it allegedly incurred on derivatives linked to the Thai baht
and Japanese yen.406 Part of the fraud claim in KLI’s complaint
relates to the structure of the transaction; part relates to Morgan
using information it procured to the disadvantage of KLI without
disclosing that information in advance.407 This latter argument has
empirical support: there is evidence of dealers acting to take
advantage of information in the foreign exchange markets to the
detriment of their counterparties.408
400 See Korean Bank: Morgan Fudged, BOND BUYER, Apr. 27, 1998, at 1.
401 The transcript of the settlement conference describes the parties as “business
partners.” See McSherry, supra note 396, at 13.
402 J.P. Morgan & Co., parent of Morgan Guaranty, agreed to purchase a
substantial stake in SK Securities and to forgo payment of the $300 million it was
owed. The value of the settlement was estimated at $250 million. See id.
403 See Morgan Fudged, supra note 400, at 1.
404 See id.
405 See Korean Insurer’s NY Swaps Suit Seeks $350M from Morgan Guaranty
Trust Co., DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Jan. 24, 2000, at 7.
406 See id. (describing negative effect of devaluation of Thai baht on the
investment).
407 See Second Amended Complaint, supra note 393, at 6-14.
408 For example, in early 1995, when the Japanese yen appreciated towards the
“knock-out” levels relevant to a series of structured derivatives transactions, dealers
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
81
Judge Hellerstein has a unique opportunity in this suit to
contribute an important common law decision to the global
derivatives market, an opportunity Holmes would have relished. The
case was pending as of August 2000.
In addition to “straight” fraud claims, fraud-related complaints
often include claims filed under the heading “negligent
misrepresentation.” The law of negligent misrepresentation is more
complex than that of fraud, and generates some additional difficulties
in derivatives disputes. Nevertheless, the analysis of negligent
misrepresentation claims, and the duties required for such claims,
parallels that of fiduciary duty claims.409
In general, a defendant is liable for negligent misrepresentation
only from the breach of a duty running to the plaintiff who is
injured.410 Specifically, in the commercial context, this rule means
that to be liable a defendant must “possess unique or specialized
expertise, or . . . [be] in a special position of confidence and trust with
the injured party such that reliance on the negligent
misrepresentation is justified.”411 The facts that justify a finding of
such special position include whether the person making the
representations knew how the information would be used and whether
this person appeared to hold a position of trust and confidence.412
New York courts have distinguished between (1) commercial
actors such as insurance agents, who are not in a better position than
their client insureds to know the insured’s personal assets and ability
to protect themselves, and (2) other providers of services, such as
doctors, attorneys, or architects, who are in a better position than
their clients to know and understand such information.413 The cases
do not specifically mention derivatives dealers: the question remains
whether (and when) a buyer of derivatives is “at a substantial
disadvantage to question the actions of the provider of services.”414
When might a derivatives purchaser be at a substantial
disadvantage to question the actions of the seller? The cases seem to
indicate that when a sophisticated party is “ripped off” by another
had an incentive to push the value of the yen up through these levels, and thus
eliminate their obligations on the transactions. See STEINHERR, supra note 5, at 109.
There is evidence that dealers did precisely this. See A.M. Malz, Currency Options
Markets and Exchange Rates: A Case Study of the U.S. Dollar in March 1995, 1
CURRENT ISSUES IN ECON. & FIN. 4 (1995) (describing substantial increase in such
transactions during the relevant period of time).
409 See, e.g., Pinky Originals, Inc. v. Bank of India, 1996 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 15575,
at *78 (S.D.N.Y. Oct. 21, 1996) (grouping together negligent misrepresentation and
fiduciary claims and noting that “plaintiffs’ claims premised on negligence, failure
to disclose, and breach of fiduciary duty are dependent on a showing that the Bank
owed some fiduciary duty to the plaintiffs”).
410 See, e.g., Kimmell v. Schaefer, 89 N.Y.2d 257, 263 (Ct. App. 1996) (“Liability
for negligence may result only from the breach of a duty running between a
tortfeasor and the injured party.”).
411 Id.
412 Id. Professionals, including lawyers and accountants, are subject to higher
duties. Id. at 263-64.
413 See, e.g., Murphy v. Kuhn, 90 N.Y.2d 266 (Ct. App. 1997) (affirming grant of
defendant’s motion to dismiss plaintiff insured’s claims for tortious
misrepresentation and breach of implied contract).
414 Id. at 273.
82 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
sophisticated party, there is no cause of action.415 However, cases are
less clear about facts that do not rise to the level of fraud or breach of
fiduciary duty, yet involve one party that is more sophisticated than
the other and therefore might support a negligent misrepresentation
claim.
For example, in Kwiatkowski II, there was evidence of a
“substantial advisory relationship”416 between the purchaser and
seller. Does providing financial advice trigger a duty that would
support a negligent misrepresentation claim? It is difficult to know
how to draw such a line. Courts have not done it, and lawyers pressing
such claims have had difficulty articulating any such line. In both
Press and Independent Order of Foresters, the courts criticized the
formulation and drafting of the complaint as inadequate.417 In
contrast, in Kwiatkowski II, the district court made great use of the
detailed allegations in the complaint, and cited favorably the
testimony of several experts that the plaintiff was exposed to an
excessive risk of loss, that based on existing industry standards the
defendants should have advised him of this risk, that the defendants
did not provide sufficient supervision or monitoring of the plaintiff’s
positions, and that the defendants failed to develop an appropriate
“exit strategy” for liquidating the contracts.418 Thus, the difference
in the cases may be due more to the quality of the lawyering than to
any distinguishing feature of fact or law.
The differences in these cases present some bitter ironies.
Perhaps the existence of a duty depends more on the quality of the
lawyering than on the facts in a particular case. Perhaps it is easier
for a judge to jettison a case on a motion to dismiss, before the parties
have had a chance to gather evidence, than on a motion for summary
judgment, even though the law states that allegations made in a
complaint are assumed to be true for purposes of deciding a motion to
dismiss. In any event, judges and lawyers faced with fraud-related
claims in derivatives cases have had a difficult time, and the result is
pitiful: increased uncertainty for participants in the derivatives
market and virtually no common law guidance.
Lack of Authority
The once-important topics of agency and authority receive short
shrift in law school today.419 Yet in recent derivatives disputes,
authority issues have been important, even dispositive.
415 See Compania Sud-Americana de Vapores, S.A. v. IBJ Shroder Bank & Trust
Co., 1992 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 1948, at *46 (calling the suit by a plaintiff who was
charged very high mark-ups in foreign currency transactions “merely an effort to
avoid the repercussions of its lack of diligence in monitoring the rates at which
conversions were made for over six years”).
416 See Kwiatkowski II, supra note 367, at *33.
417 See Independent Order of Foresters, supra note 359, at *8-10 (pointing out
absence and limitation of allegations); Press, supra note 361, at 386-87
(characterizing complaint as “naked allegation”).
418 See Kwiatkowski II, supra note 367, at *39.
419 Many schools do not offer courses in agency, although the topic receives
brief treatment at the beginning of many corporate law casebooks. See, e.g., WILLIAM
A. KLEIN, J. MARK RAMSEYER & STEPHEN M. BAINBRIDGE, BUSINESS ASSOCIATIONS:
CASES AND MATERIALS ON AGENCY, PARTNERSHIPS, AND CORPORATIONS 33-45 (4th ed.
1999) (discussing agency and apparent authority); see also MELVIN A. EISENBERG, AN
INTRODUCTION TO AGENCY AND PARTNERSHIP 1-27 (3d ed. 1995).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
83
The authority argument in the context of derivatives is relatively
simple. A financial derivative transaction is simply a contract,
typically between two parties. If one party did not have legal
authority to enter into that contract, it is not binding on that party.
Alternatively, even if the party did not have actual legal
authority, the party might be bound if there was apparent authority.
Apparent authority is a common law concept holding that a principal
may be bound by the actions of an agent who does not have actual
authority when the principal acts in a way that reasonably could lead a
third party to conclude that the principal consented to the agent’s
exercise of authority.420
Plaintiffs have claimed in derivatives disputes that the underlying
transactions were illegal or unauthorized.421 For example, in
Sumitomo Corp. v. J.P. Morgan & Co.,422 Sumitomo argued both (1)
that derivatives financing transactions entered into by an individual
trader were unauthorized because only Sumitomo’s treasury
department – not any individual trader – could authorize financing on
behalf of Sumitomo, and (2) that the transactions were prohibited by
Japanese law.423 These two claims – lack of authority and illegality –
are often put together. Lack of authority stems from the fact that a
grant of authority was illegal; illegality, in turn, implies that an
individual lacked authority.
Courts have held that contracts made in violation of a country’s
law (or with a view of being in violation of that country’s law) are
unenforceable.424 In Sumitomo Corp. v. J.P. Morgan & Co., for
example, a Sumitomo copper trader, Yasuo Hamanaka, obtained
financing from J.P. Morgan without the approval of Sumitomo’s
treasury department or board of directors. Sumitomo’s argument was
that if approval was required and not given, the transactions were null
and void. Alternatively, Article 260 of the Japanese Commercial
Code prohibited such financing transactions without approval of the
420 See, e.g., JAMES D. COX, THOMAS LEE HAZEN & F. HODGE O’NEAL, CORPORATIONS
129-130 (1997) (describing apparent authority).
421 The first prominent derivatives case in the area was a British case holding
that derivatives transactions entered into by the London boroughs of Fulham and
Hammersmith were contrary to law. See Hazell v. Hammersmith and Fulham London
Borough Council, 2 W.L.R. 372 (1991). The state of West Virginia raised similar
claims in West Virginia v. Morgan Stanley. See State v. Morgan Stanley & Co., 459
S.E.2d 906 (W. Va. 1995) Authority issues also arose in the Orange County
litigation. Orange County sued the brokers who sold it certain derivatives and
alleged that the transactions were ultra vires, or beyond the limits of the law. The
specific allegation was that the investment strategy was so risky it violated
California law, and that the brokers had a duty to halt their business dealings with
Orange County and report the activities. See Orange County, Brokers File Cross-
Motions for Summary Judgment, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Oct. 15, 1998, at 5.
Orange County also claimed that certain reverse repurchase transactions it entered
into with the brokers violated state law and would have required voter approval. Id.
422 See Sumitomo Corp. v. J.P. Morgan & Co., No. 99-CV-8780 (S.D.N.Y. 2000).
423 See Memorandum of Plaintiff Sumitomo Corporation in Opposition to
Defendants’ Motion to Dismiss Certain Claims in the Complaint, at 32, Sumitomo
Corp. v. J.P. Morgan & Co., No. 99-CV-8780 (S.D.N.Y. May 25, 2000) (copy on file
with the author).
424 See, e.g., Dornberger v. Metropolitan Life Ins. Co., 961 F. Supp. 506, 532-38
(S.D.N.Y. 1997) (contract made in violation of European law subject to rescission);
Rutkin v. Reinfeld, 229 F.2d 248, 255 (2d Cir. 1956) (contract entered into “with a
view of violating the laws of another country is unenforceable”).
84 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
board of directors.425 According to this argument, if Japanese law
required board approval, and approval was not given, the transactions
were illegal, and therefore were void. This case was pending as of
August 2000.
Authority issues can arise based on the scope of an investment
agreement between two parties, where one is investing in derivatives
on behalf of the other. For example, AT&T Corp.’s pension plan
and the Massachusetts Pension Reserves Investment Trust lost a
combined $162 million based on unauthorized trading by the chief
investment officer of Rhumbline Advisers, an investment adviser the
two pension funds were using.426
Authority issues also have arisen in recent derivatives disputes in
Asia. For example, Indonesian corporations often have a two-tiered
board structure and articles of association requiring that major
financial transactions be approved by both boards: the board of
directors, which has general executive authority, and the board of
commissioners, which oversees and advises the directors.427
Unfortunately, Indonesian law and most articles of association are
unclear about when the board of commissioners must approve a
transaction. Although in theory, a party could eliminate authority-
related risk by requiring the board of commissioner’s approval, most
Indonesian companies balk at obtaining such approval.428
Plaintiffs in derivatives disputes often include along with lack of
authority claims an argument that the derivatives were not suitable
investments.429 The underlying rationale for suitability claims is
similar to that for breach of fiduciary duty: the seller has an
information, knowledge, or sophistication advantage over the
purchaser and therefore owes the purchaser a duty not to mislead it
about the risks of the instrument and, in any event, not to sell
instruments that are too complicated for a particular purchaser to
understand.430 Unfortunately, no jurisdiction has clarified what
circumstances or facts would generate such a duty owed by derivatives
seller to buyer.
In addition, derivatives purchasers have brought an array of
common law claims based on the notion that the instruments were
425 Article 260 provides that “[t]he Board [of Directors] cannot delegate the
following decisions to a manager, but must itself make them: . . . (2) Borrowing a
substantial sum of money.” 12 Commercial Laws of the World 40 (1993). The
amount borrowed in this case was approximately $283 million (in Japanese yen), see
Brief, at 33, arguably a “substantial sum.”
426 See DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR, supra, note 421, at 5.
427 See Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 30, n.121 (citing advice received by
the authors from the Jakarta law firm of Ali Budiardjo, Nugroho, Beksodiputro).
428 See id. at 31 n.123.
429 See Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 35. For a recent general discussion
of suitability claims in the securities context, see Lewis D. Lowenfels & Alan R.
Bromberg, Suitability in Securities Transactions, 54 BUS. LAWYER 153 (1999).
There are numerous articles about derivatives and suitability. See Lyle Roberts,
Suitability Claims Under Rule 10b-5: Are Public Entities Sophisticated Enough to
Use Derivatives?, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. (1996); Geoffrey B. Goldman, Crafting a
Suitability Requirement for the Sale of Over-the-Counter Derivatives: Should
Regulators Punish the Wall Street Hounds of Greed, 95 COLUM. L. REV. 1112 (1995).
430 This rationale is not based on some notion of fairness to particular
purchasers. Rather, it is an economic-based rationale designed to benefit the
derivatives industry as a whole. Without some such perceived protection,
purchasers might not transact.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
85
not suitable. For example, in UBS Int’l Trustees Ltd. v. Morgan
Stanley Dean Witter & Co.,431 the plaintiff alleged, as trustee on
behalf of the purchaser who lost money on the instruments that the
purchaser was not sophisticated in the use of leverage and
derivatives.432 These suitability allegations supported common law
claims of fraud, misrepresentation, and breach of fiduciary duty. In
Springwell Navigation Corp. v. The Chase Manhattan Bank,433 the
plaintiff alleged breach of contract, breach of fiduciary duty,
fraudulent misrepresentation, negligent misrepresentation,
professional negligence, and negligent supervision, all based on the
defendant’s failure to inform the plaintiff that investments in certain
emerging markets bond derivatives434 were very risky and unsuitable
for the plaintiff’s goals.435
Unfortunately, the legal basis for suitability claims is wrought with
ambiguity and confusion. Under U.S. law, suitability claims typically
arise out of “securities” transactions only. The National Association
of Securities Dealers has adopted suitability rules, including rules
extending suitability obligations to broker-dealers selling securities to
institutional customers.436 Outside of the U.S., the law is even less
clear, and there are no guidelines or standards describing the suitability
obligations of a derivatives seller.437 As in other areas of derivatives
litigation, disputes over suitability typically are settled before judicial
decision or trial.438
It is unclear whether suitability claims fit under breach of fiduciary
duty439 or lack of authority,440 or whether they are even relevant in
OTC derivatives disputes. Courts facing lack of authority claims have
not clarified the issue.
431 UBS Int’l Trustees Ltd. v. Morgan Stanley Dean Witter & Co., No. 99 Civ.
8957 (S.D.N.Y. amended complaint filed Dec. 20, 1999).
432 See, e.g., U.K. Investment Co.’s Amended Complaint Names Morgan Stanley
Director, SEC. & COMMODITIES LITIG. REPTR., Jan. 26, 2000, at 7 (describing
sophistication difference between derivatives purchaser and Morgan Stanley).
433 Springwell Navigation Corp. v. The Chase Manhattan Bank,, No. 99 Civ.
11855 (S.D.N.Y. complaint filed Dec. 7, 1999).
434 A large portion of the plaintiff’s money was used to buy Russian derivatives
consisting of CMSCI Notes, which were tied to Russian government short-term zero
coupon ruble-denominated bonds known as Gosudarstvenniye Kratkosrochniye
Obligatsii, or GKOs. See Greek Company Sues Chase Manhattan over $200M Bond
Derivatives Loss, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Jan. 10, 2000, at 4. Interestingly, the
complaint’s description of the derivative instrument was incomplete, presumably
because either the plaintiff or the lawyers or both were unable to understand and
describe it. See id. (“The value of the Note was linked in as yet an unexplained way
to the value of the underlying GKOs.”).
435 See id.
436 See NASD Release No. 34-37 588, 61 Fed. Reg. 44, 100 (1996).
437 See, e.g., Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 36 (noting that in Asia “[t]he
local legal systems contain neither guidelines on what constitutes a suitable
derivative nor express obligations on the part of a lesser of a derivative instrument
to ensure that the instrument is suitable for the buyer in light of its particular
circumstances”).
438 See id. at 36 n. 150, 38 n.160 (citing examples of suitability claims by TPI
Polene PLC, a Thai plastic and cement maker, against UBS and claims by SK
Securities, a Korean firm, against J.P. Morgan & Co., both of which settled for
undisclosed amounts).
439 The question in this case would be whether unsuitable trades were made in
violation of a duty owed by seller to buyer.
440 The question in this case would be whether unsuitable trades were beyond
the authority of a purchaser.
86 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Contract-Based Claims
Finally, derivatives disputes often involve claims for breach of
contract. A breach of contract claim can be relative straightforward,
even in the derivatives context. For example, in a 1997 state court
case in Maryland, a judge awarded $1.7 million to two businessmen
who lost money on several currency swaps with FX Concepts Inc.441
FX Concepts claimed to have a sophisticated computer model that
identified winning foreign currency bets.442 An official of FX
Concepts had instructed the employee dealing with the two
businessmen to tell them about certain risks in European currencies,
and that employee failed to do so. The court found that failure to
deliver this instruction was a breach of contract.443
I have found only one case involving OTC derivatives that went
to trial, and that case essentially presented a breach of contract claim.
Although numerous other claims were involved in the case, the
verdict is based primarily on a breach of contract rationale.
Unfortunately, this case provides no certainty at all to a prospective
derivatives investor, and in fact contains confusing and contradictory
statements about the applicable derivatives transactions.
This case, BankAtlantic v. PaineWebber, Inc.,444 involved two
interest rate swaps between two financial institutions: BankAtlantic
and Homestead Savings, with PaineWebber serving as a broker to
BankAtlantic. BankAtlantic lost more than $30 million on the
swaps, and sued PaineWebber for breach of contract, breach of
fiduciary duty, fraud, fraudulent concealment, negligence, and
negligent misrepresentation. After a five-week jury trial in 1989, the
jury returned a verdict in favor of PaineWebber. BankAtlantic
appealed on various grounds, and the Eleventh Circuit affirmed.
The opinion is notable, not for its analysis of any particular legal
issues, but for how little guidance it provides to any derivatives
market participant. The relevant portion of the Eleventh Circuit
opinion – in its entirety – is as follows:
“Based on PaineWebber’s recommendation, BankAtlantic entered
into the two interest rate swaps with Homestead Savings
(“Homestead”) in an effort to hedge its adjustable rate deposit
payables against an increase in interest rates. Alleging non-
performance under the agreement, BankAtlantic terminated the
services of PaineWebber as financial advisor and employed another
firm to assist with the interest rate swaps. During this time, interest
rates were falling drastically, allegedly causing BankAtlantic to suffer
losses in excess of $30 million.
In August 1987, BankAtlantic brought suit against PaineWebber
alleging these losses were caused by PaineWebber’s failure to disclose
the risks involved in interest rate swaps, e.g., that if interest rates fell,
the high yielding fixed rate mortgages would be prepaid as borrowers
refinanced. BankAtlantic also alleged that PaineWebber failed to
disclose its extensive relationship with Homestead, that Homestead
441 Investors Win $1.7 Million Award on Md. Claim Against Management Firm,
SEC. REG. & L. REP., Oct. 17, 1997, at 1455.
442 Id.
443 Id.
444 See BankAtlantic v. Paine Webber, Inc., 955 F.2d 1467 (11th Cir. 1992).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
87
was not creditworthy and therefore that BankAtlantic should have
obtained collateral from Homestead.”
That is the relevant discussion, in its entirety. The remainder of
the opinion is no more illuminating; neither is the district court’s
three-page opinion and order denying the plaintiff’s assertions of
error, motion for judgment notwithstanding the verdict, and motion
for a new trial.445 Consider the questions someone considering a
derivatives transactions would have about this case: What were the
basic terms of the interest rate swap? Did BankAtlantic agree to pay
a fixed rate and receive a floating rate, or vice versa? If BankAtlantic
lost money when interest rates dropped, how were the swaps designed
to hedge against an increase in interest rates? If these were truly
interest rate swaps, what did the prepayment risk associated with fixed
rate mortgages have to do with the transaction? How was
Homestead’s credit and collateral related to BankAtlantic’s losses?
Did BankAtlantic money lose money because the swaps moved in its
favor and Homestead defaulted , or because the swaps moved against
BankAtlantic? What was the relationship of the parties, and was it
relevant? Were there alleged misrepresentations? A party looking
for guidance from this case will not find answers.
Other contract-based claims have been for excessive fees changed
in derivatives deals. Between 1994 and 1997, Slovnaft A.S., the
former Slovak national oil company, purchased four structured loans
from Merrill Lynch International, Inc., and lost $175 million.446
Slovnaft sued Merrill in 1999 in New York state court alleging that
crude oil-linked derivatives embedded in the loans had cost Slovnaft
$75 million in “exorbitant” interest payments.447
Contractual duties can arise out of obligations described in
standard form agreements signed by both parties. These agreements
can serve as the basis for claims based on implied contractual duties.
Judge Feikens found support for such a claim in the P&G case. In that
case, Section 4 of the standard form ISDA agreement between the
parties provided that each party must furnish specified information
and that such information must also relate to any documents specified
in the confirmation.448 In other words, the specification of such
information in the standard form created a duty to furnish the
specified information.
New York case law establishes such an implied contractual duty to
disclose in business negotiations. As Judge Feikens read this duty, it
may arise where (1) a party has superior knowledge of certain
information, (2) that information is not readily available to the other
party, and (3) the first party knows that the second party is acting on
445 See BankAtlantic v. Paine Webber, Inc., 130 F.R.D. 153 (S.D. Fla. 1990)
(three-page opinion, less than one page of which considers the plaintiff’s motions).
446 See Merrill Lynch Seeks Dismissal of $75 Million Slovnaft Derivatives,
BANK & LENDER LIABILITY LITIGATION REPORTER, Jan. 19, 2000, at 10.
447 See Slovnaft A.S. v. Merrill Lynch Int’l Inc., (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1999).
448 Judge Feikens wrote in the P&G case, “Documents that are referred to in the
Confirmation (here I allude specifically to the documents that will enable a party to
determine the correlation between the price and yields of the five-year Treasury notes
and thirty-year Treasury bonds, the sensitivity tables, the spreadsheets regarding
volatility, and documents related to the yield curve) should be provided.” Id. at
1290.
88 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
the basis of the mistaken knowledge.449 Such a duty to disclose may
arise even in the absence of a fiduciary duty between the parties.450
Judge Feikens concluded “that defendants had a duty to disclose
material information to plaintiff both before the parties entered into
the swap transactions and in their performance, and also a duty to
deal fairly and in good faith during the performance of the swap
transactions.”451
As a result, even if the duty-based claims for breach of fiduciary
duty, negligent misrepresentation, and suitability fail, an implied
breach of contract claim may survive based on obligations created by
swap documentation. Analytically, this result makes little sense.
These claims all are based on essentially the same rationale:452 that
sophistication or information asymmetry will support a duty to
disclose material facts. This rationale is wrapped in different
packages, each with a different jurisprudence, each with a small set of
indeterminate cases. Not surprisingly, it is very difficult for parties to
derivatives transactions – even if they agree on the facts – to know
how or why a judge will resolve their dispute.
The remaining two alternatives merit only brief consideration.
They have presented only a handful of issues relevant to derivatives
disputes.
3. The Limited Applicability of Private Law
The implied breach of contract claim in the P&G case is a rare
instance of a claim arising out of a private derivatives contract.
These contracts are form agreements created by derivatives dealers
and their lawyers, and – not surprisingly – are structured to ensure
that derivatives contracts are not subject to federal regulation and to
prevent most non-dealer derivatives parties’ claims in a dispute with a
dealer from surviving.453
Private law has evolved in the derivatives area along two paths.
The first path, designed for transactions between derivatives dealers,
has ended in a very complete, self-regulatory mechanism of little
relevance in the derivatives disputes discussed here. For private law
enthusiasts, these packages of default rules are things of beauty. The
standard form contract, created by the International Swap Dealers
Association (ISDA), is a complete, well-constructed private law
governing most contingencies that might arise between dealers.454 It
is flexible yet comprehensive, and is a standard within the industry.
449 See Procter & Gamble, supra note 217, at 1290 (citing Banque Arabe et
Internationale D’Investissement v. Maryland National Bank, 57 F.3d 146 (2d Cir.
1995)).
450 See id. (citing numerous New York cases).
451 See id. at 1291.
452 An additional rationale not yet addressed in any derivatives dispute is
commercial frustration or impracticability. See supra note 333.
453 For a general description of such contract-based efforts in the securities
context, see Margaret V. Sachs, Freedom of Contract: The Trojan Horse of Rule 10b-
5, 51 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 879 (1994).
454 The basic form contract is the 1992 ISDA Master Agreement (Local Currency
– Single Jurisdiction). There also are more complex standard forms, forms in
translation, as well as recent annexes with updated definitions. The basic form is
available to non-members through the ISDA website for $25; the complete set of
forms is $1,600. See <http://www.isda.org> (2000).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
89
But because few derivatives disputes are between dealers, it is largely
irrelevant here.
The second path, designed for transactions between dealers and
non-dealers, is much shorter, ending in a relatively small number of
non-reliance provisions included in the standard ISDA documentation,
as well as in other documentation related to derivatives transactions
between dealers and non-dealers, including term sheets, economic
reports and forecasts, and analysis of particular trades, including
“scenario analysis.”455 These non-reliance provisions, or
“disclaimers,” which are virtually the same in every derivatives
transaction, purport to absolve the dealer of liability associated with
the transaction.456 A typical disclaimer says something like “the
purchaser fully understands the above terms and conditions, including
the risks and benefits of the transactions.”
Derivatives sellers argue that if they obtain a signed disclaimer of
a duty and/or provide adequate scenario analysis, a purchaser should
not be able to sustain the common law claims articulated in Part
V.B.2. For example, derivatives sellers argue that if a purchaser
represents that the seller owes no duty to it, the buyer cannot later
sue to recover on a duty-based theory; similarly, a buyer cannot later
complain about oral misrepresentations if they are inconsistent with a
later-signed written statement setting forth in an accurate way the
substance of the allegedly misrepresented facts.
There is an initial question about whether disclaimers actually are
negotiated provisions that should be enforced against buyers. If some
derivatives contracts were sold with disclaimers and others were not,
there would be an argument that the disclaimers were both negotiated
and priced by the parties. It is more difficult to make this argument
when there is unanimous use of essentially similar disclaimers. It
seems incredible to argue that each such disclaimer was priced and
negotiated in a multi-trillion dollar argument. Neither is it credible to
argue that it is sufficient if a small number of disclaimers are priced
and negotiated because then all contracts will reflect those prices and
negotiations; such an argument makes little sense in a market
consisting of privately negotiated, often-confidential transactions.
However, even if one assumes that the disclaimers were negotiated
and are not adhesion contracts, there are other strong reasons to
believe neither a signed disclaimer nor a detailed scenario analysis
should preclude a duty-related claim. First, disclaimers or scenario
analyses may be misleading, inadequate, or fail to disclose important
information the seller possesses that the buyers does not.457 For
example, prior to the Asia crisis, numerous investment and
commercial banks had information about specific countries’ central
455 Analysis of particular trades includes “scenario analysis,” which describes
the gains and losses on a particular derivative transaction based on changes in one
or more variables. For example, scenario analysis for a swap based on a particular
index might show the financial position of the purchaser given a increase or decrease
of one, two, and five percent in the index.
456 Courts have upheld such nonreliance clauses in the securities context. See,
e.g., Rissman v. Rissman, 213 F.3d 381 (7th Cir. 2000) (holding that written non-
reliance clause prohibited recover based on prior oral statements).
457 See, e.g., Bennett & Marin, supra note 305, at 39 (“A scenario analysis that is
based on historical volatility, for example, may prove to be inadequate if markets
move in an unexpected manner.”).
90 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
bank practices and currency reserves and were in fact taking large
speculative positions based on this information. Any bank selling
derivatives based on foreign exchange rates in those countries would
have an obvious information and knowledge advantage. If the bank
did not disclose this information, and made other disclosures
(including scenario analysis) that would be made misleading by this
information, any purchaser of derivatives from the bank would have a
strong argument that the bank owed that purchaser a duty (because of
the superior information and knowledge) and breached that duty
(because of the omissions and misrepresentations).
In addition, a disclaimer must be sufficiently specific to disclaim
the misrepresentations and omissions that form the basis of a
purchaser’s claim. For example, the Second Circuit has held that the
contract language must “match the alleged fraud.”458 The New York
appellate courts have held that a disclaimer of reliance on
representations must be specifically related to the contents of the
fraud claim.459 For example, disclaimers related to the “physical
nature of the premises” and “environmental matter” were not
sufficiently specific to preclude a fraud claim based on the “presence
of underground tanks containing possible toxic chemicals.”460
The policy behind these cases is, consistent with hypothetical
bargain analysis, that purchasers would not willingly accept a broad
disclaimer absent some reduction in price or increase in quality. At
the extreme, purchasers cannot (and would not ex ante) disclaim
fraud. Accordingly, such disclaimers should be read narrowly,
especially when the parties were in a situation involving information
or sophistication asymmetry.
To the extent disclaimers arise as issues in derivatives disputes,
they should be read narrowly and certainly should not be read to
preclude purchaser claims based on inaccurate or misleading
statements. Even ISDA, the dealers’ own organization has recognized
this principle.461 No court has yet published an opinion on this issue
in a derivatives dispute. The first judge to do so should carefully
consider the implications of informational asymmetry in a
hypothetical bargain analysis, and should not simply accept a dealer’s
attempts to skirt a principle in a dispute that it previously had
endorsed through ISDA as good policy.
4. Some Attempts at Arbitration
Given the problems associated with the alternative means of
resolving disputes, one might expect derivatives counterparties to sign
arbitration clauses. Yet arbitration of such disputes is rare. One
reason may be that both counterparties fear the uncertainty
associated with an arbitrator even more than they fear the courtroom.
The recent evidence of New York Stock Exchange arbitration panels
458 See Manufacturers Hanover Trust Co. v. Yanakas, 7 F.3d 310, 317 (2d Cir.
1993).
459 See Hi Tor Industrial Park v. Chemical Bank, 494 N.Y.S.2d 751 (2d Dep’t
1985).
460 See id. at 752.
461 See Raj Bhala, Applying Equilibrium Theory and the FICAS Model: A Case
Study of Capital Adequacy and Currency Trading, 41 ST. LOUIS L.J. 125, 209 n.369
(1996) (citing ISDA’s strong recommendation that U.S. members follow the ISDA
Principles and Practices for Wholesale Financial Market Transactions).
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
91
ruling against Wall Street investment banks in ways the banks did not
expect would support this reason.462
Another reason may be that more sophisticated counterparties
may prefer the less fair forum of court precisely because it is more
expensive. In court, a derivatives dealer can force a plaintiff to
engage in expensive litigation, which the dealer easily can afford, but
which the purchaser may find more difficult to sustain, especially
given the expense of discovery. Delay typically works to the dealer’s
advantage. If the case seems to be moving in the plaintiff’s favor,
the dealer can, and will, simply settle to avoid an adverse ruling.
There is little evidence of derivatives disputes moving from court
to arbitration. On the other hand, it seems clear that parties to a
derivatives contract may effectively incorporate external law into an
arbitration agreement, or may authorize an arbitrator to decide such
questions of external law.463 Parties also may, by agreement,
establish discovery rules, including rules resembling those applicable to
disputes in federal court.464 These benefits might make arbitration
more attractive to derivatives market participants.
The evidence of arbitration agreements in the derivatives market
is scant and very recent. In late 1999, Panama-based Dorigol S.A.
agreed to arbitrate a derivatives dispute with J.P. Morgan & Co.
before a National Association of Securities Dealers panel.465 Dorigol
had filed sued in the Southern District of New York, alleging J.P.
Morgan committed fraud when it sold Dorigol OTC call and put
option on Brady bonds without disclosing facts it knew about risks in
that market.466 Specifically, Dorigol alleged J.P. Morgan knew it was
going to issue a margin call against Long-Term Capital Management
in late 1998, and that such a margin call would cause the market for
emerging market bonds to collapse.467 In fact, this market did
collapse, and Dorigol ultimately lost $7 million on the trades.468
Although attorneys for J.P. Morgan were advocating the move
from court to arbitration, attorneys for Dorigol also suggested they
might be better off with an arbitration panel.469 Resisting arbitration
would have been expensive, and not necessarily in Dorigol’s best
interest. Morgan did not disclose its motives in moving to
arbitration.
462 See Smith, supra note 176, at C1, C4 (citing several awards to employees in
bonus disputes with their employer bank).
463 See COOPER ET AL., supra note 149, at 153 (“No one doubts that the parties
may authorize the arbitrator to decide external law questions, either by incorporating
the law in the … agreement or by posing the external law issue in the submission
agreement.”). Where private parties have not indicated that particular external law
should govern, arbitrators are not constrained by external law or cases. See id. at 247
(noting that “arbitrators usually do not treat as conclusive the determinations of
administrative agencies or courts”).
464 See id. at 225 (describing contract assuring parties access to “all
nonconfidential information as is relevant and appropriate to the negotiation,
maintenance and enforcement of this agreement”).
465 See Panamanian Firm, J.P. Morgan Agree to Arbitrate $7M Derivatives Case,
SECURITIES LITIG. & REG. REPTR., Jan. 12, 2000, at 8.
466 Id.
467 Id.
468 Id.
469 Id. (quoting one attorney for Dorigol as saying “educating an already
‘highly educated’ panel about financial derivatives will be much easier than
educating a lay jury”).
92 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
In a similar case, in early 2000, Lehman Brothers Inc. filed a
motion asking the Southern District of New York to stay a suit
against Lehman and compel arbitration.470 The plaintiff, Banco Disa
S.A., a Panamanian bank, had filed suit alleging common law breach
of fiduciary duty, fraud, and negligent misrepresentation, as well as
fraud and misrepresentation under Section 10(b) of the Securities
Exchange Act, for losses it incurred on several investments in U.S.
Treasury-based derivatives.471 Again, the parties’ motivations were
unclear.
The defendant banks may have been motivated by very large,
recent settlements other banks had agreed to pay in other cases.472
To the extent the motivations were to avoid large settlements
encouraged by the unpredictability of a jury verdict, the role of
arbitration in derivatives disputes might become more substantial over
time, as it has in other areas.473
C. How Synthetic Common Law Could Govern Disputes
Parties to derivatives transactions could eliminate much of the
uncertainty surrounding such transactions by agreeing ex ante to have
a synthetic common law regime govern any future disputes. This
section explains the arguments in favor of synthetic common law and
suggests a few synthetic cases for parties to use.474
Most obviously, parties could select or modify already-decided
cases to include as part of a contract. For example, parties might
include Procter & Gamble v. Bankers Trust,475 but eliminate Judge
Feikens’s sweeping statement about duties and obligations in swap
transactions. Alternatively, parties might adopt the facts of the case,
but have the judge in the case refuse to grant summary judgment in
470 See Lehman Brothers Files Motion to Compel Arbitration in $6.6M Dispute,
BANK & LENDER LIAB. LITIG. REPTR., Jan. 19, 2000, at 3.
471 Banco Disa S.A. v. Lehman Brothers Inc., No. 99 Civ. 9487 (S.D.N.Y. 1999).
The suit contended that Lehman knew the portfolio was risky and unsuitable, but
pressed the risky strategy in order to make commissions and fees. See $6.6M
Dispute, supra note 470, at 3.
472 In 1998, several investment banks paid very large settlements to settle suits
related to Orange County’s 1994 bankruptcy. Merrill Lynch paid $400 million, the
fifth-largest settlement in Wall Street history; Morgan Stanley paid $69.6 million;
CS First paid $52.5 million. See Credit Suisse First Boston Settles Orange County
Suit for $52.5 Million, SEC. REG. L. REP., May 15, 1998, at 748; FIASCO, supra note
323, at 268. In agreeing to settle these claims, CS First Boston’s CEO, Allen Wheat,
noted that “given the magnitude of the County’s losses and the fact that litigation is
unpredictable and distracting for any firm, this settlement is the right course of
action.” Id. Similarly, Bear Stearns & Co. paid $39 million to settle a suit brought
by three bankrupt hedge funds alleging fraud in the sale of collateralized mortgage
obligations known as “toxic waste.” See Bear Stearns Settles Granite Partners
“Toxic Waste” CMO Suit for $39M, DERIVATIVES LITIG. REPTR., Jan. 24, 2000, at 4.
The losses, totaling $225 million, were incurred following the Federal Reserve
Board’s increase in interest rates in 1994.
473 See supra Part III.C.
474 I am including the synthetic cases for illustrative purposes only, and I would
defer to the choices of current derivatives market participants (and their lawyers) to
determine whether particular cases satisfy the expectations of the parties to a
particular contract. In fact, it is precisely such deference to the market – based on the
assumption that private parties will choose the cases that most efficiently and fairly
would govern any dispute – that is critical to the success of a synthetic common law
regime.
475 See Procter & Gamble, supra note 217.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
93
favor of Bankers Trust, perhaps noting that a fiduciary relationship
existed. Similarly, parties might adopt the facts of the SEITA
case,476 but reverse the outcome, or incorporate Press, Independent
Foresters, and Kwiatkowski II into a single, sensible decision.477
In addition, parties could create new cases to govern future
disputes. The following cases are meant to be illustrative, not
comprehensive, and indicate the types of issues that parties might
decide to address in individual cases. In addition, parties could specify
how important certain facts were to the decision in the case, or what
type of reasoning they would like an adjudicator to use if the facts do
not match the facts of the case.
First, the regime could reduce uncertainty associated with
differential statutory coverage of derivatives.478 The parties would
make it clear that federal securities and commodities statutes did not
govern their disputes. For example, the menu of cases could include
the following illustrative case:
Case No. 1: Party A and Party B enter into the derivative
transaction described in the attached term sheet.479 Party B loses
money and sues in federal court, claiming the federal securities
laws should govern the dispute because derivative is a
“security.”480 Held: the derivative instrument is not a security.
Note that the above case depends on the acquiescence of the
federal courts. When Party B filed suit, the judge drawing the case
would need to recognize the party’s prior agreement to resolve all
disputes through the synthetic common law regime, and dismiss the
claim. Notwithstanding the Supreme Court’s statement that such
dismissal is warranted based on the parties’ prior agreement,481 there
is some risk that a judge would refuse to dismiss the claim. In such an
event, the parties would bear the litigation costs associated with an
appeal, and the litigation risk of a change in Supreme Court position.
However, this same problem is present for arbitration generally and
does not appear to be serious. In any event, the costs would be lower
than the costs of litigating a federal claim, which neither party
believed ex ante would govern any future dispute.
Second, synthetic cases could reduce the uncertainty associated
with ambiguous common law decisions. For example, consider the
case law dealing with lack of authority claims.482 To the extent
parties are concerned, as they seem to be, that one party could avoid
its obligations on a derivatives contract simply by refusing to pay any
losses, the parties could include a case holding that refusal to pay
would be a breach of the derivatives contract, entitling the non-
breaching party to damages under the regime.
476 See Societe Nationale, supra note 353.
477 See discussion at notes 361 to 383 and accompanying text.
478 This uncertainty is described in detail supra at Part V.B.1.
479 The parties would simply attach or incorporate by reference a copy of the
term sheet for their transaction, once the terms are finalized.
480 The parties could include a similar case to make it clear the commodities
laws did not apply, either.
481 See cases cited supra note 169.
482 See supra notes 421-437 and accompanying text.
94 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
Case No. 2: Party A and Party B enter into the derivative
transaction described in the attached term sheet. Party B
provides evidence that the transaction is both legal and
authorized.483 Party B loses money and is in “default”484 on the
transaction. Party B claims the contract is illegal and
unenforceable. Held: unless another case in this menu establishes
otherwise,485 Party A is entitled to payment from Party B of the
amount owed.
Including such a case in a derivatives contract might resolve the
problem of authority in a way statutes or cases could not. Recall the
problem associated with the Indonesian statute requiring board
approval, notwithstanding the fact that it often is impracticable to
obtain such approval. An Indonesian statute could specify when a
contract will be binding on an Indonesian company even without
board of commissioner’s approval. Alternatively, Indonesian courts
could hear and resolve cases, preferably by reported opinion, in a way
that provided guidance to future parties. However, neither resolution
by statute nor common law seems likely, given the dearth of finance-
related legislation and cases. Nor does it seem probable that a treaty
or executive agreement between Indonesian and another country
would allow parties to choose another, clearer legal regime, with the
knowledge that they would be able to collect and enforce a judgment.
A synthetic common law regime could specify what types of
contracts would require board of commissioner’s approval, and give
plenty of examples, based on easy-to-discern variables, such as
notional amount, value-at-risk, and scenario analysis, as functions of
revenue, net income, or some other accounting variables. The parties
to the contract could choose among these regimes the one most
closely corresponding to their expectation of which transactions
would be authorized. Unauthorized transactions would be
unenforceable, although such transactions still might occur with
adequate collateral. As an alternative, or perhaps additional,
synthetic case, consider the following.
Case No. 3: Party A and Party B enter into derivative transactions
with a notional value in aggregate of [$100 million] or less.
Party B is an Indonesian company and therefore normally must
obtain the approval of its board of commissioners for any
derivative transactions. Party B loses money on the derivative
transaction described in the attached term sheet and fails to pay
Party A. Party B’s board of commissioners did not approve the
transaction. Held: the transaction was deemed approved because
Party A and Party B had entered into derivative transactions with
483 Such evidence might include the signed authorization of the board of
directors or particular managers, applicable powers of attorney, or even a video or
audiotape of a conversation in which the purchaser authorized approval of the
transaction.
484 Events of default are specified in great detail in the standard form ISDA
agreement already used by derivatives counterparties. Accordingly, the parties
could simply make reference to that agreement and incorporate the definitions there
by reference.
485 For example, another case might hold that if Party A defrauded Party B, then
Party B would not be liable.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
95
notional value of [$100 million] or less, and Party A therefore is
entitled to payment from Party B of the amount owed.
Similar problems arise when the purchaser of derivatives attempts
to renege by claiming one its employees (a “rogue trader”) engaged in
unauthorized trading in those instruments. This issue has arisen in
numerous cases, including disputes between three Chinese companies
and Lehman Brothers Inc.,486 between Sumitomo Corp. and several
large banks,487 and between a Malaysian company and Credit
Suisse.488 Many of these suits were filed under non-U.S. legal regimes
that do not recognize the common law doctrine of apparent
authority. As a result, derivatives sellers need to assure themselves
before a transaction occurs that the agent for the purchaser has actual
authority.
A synthetic common law regime would enable the parties to
specify in advance what facts would constitute apparent authority.
For example, the synthetic cases might find that there was authority
when an employee with the title “managing director” (or some similar
title) signs a derivatives contract, representing that she has authority
to act on behalf of the purchaser. Or the case might say that it is not
enough to rely on only one signature; two or three are required. Or
the case might require board approval for each transaction. In any
event, the parties in advance could choose the law that fits their
situation best. Significantly, the fact that parties engaged in
deliberations about the choice of synthetic law would be strong
evidence that they considered the authority issue in advance and that
the transaction would be either authorized or not, if the facts fit one
of the hypothetical synthetic cases.
As to other common law claims, the parties could include cases
related to duty-based claims (i.e., breach of fiduciary duty or negligent
misrepresentation), describing several relationships and then
concluding for each whether a particular duty existed. Then, if the
parties’ relationship changed over time, a duty might or might not be
486 The suits occurred after United Petroleum & Chemicals Co., China National
Chemicals Import & Export Corp., and Minmetals International Non-Ferrous Metals
Trading Co. refused to pay amounts owed to Lehman on various foreign exchange
and interest rate derivatives transactions. Each Chinese firm claimed the trades were
unauthorized because the employees who signed the contracts did not have the
necessary corporate authority. The argument was simple: if the trades were
unauthorized, they were unenforceable. In each case, Lehman filed suit in the
Southern District of New York for breach of contract. See Victor Hou, Derivatives
and Dialectics: The Evolution of the Chinese Futures Market, 72 N.Y.U. L. REV. 175,
187 (1997).
487 Sumitomo sued Union Bank of Switzerland (in Tokyo District Court) and
Chase Manhattan Bank (in the Southern District of New York) claiming that the
banks had made unauthorized loans to Sumitomo’s head copper trader who had
engaged in unauthorized copper trading, sustaining losses of $2.6 billion.
Sumitomo alleged not only that the banks knew that the trader was not authorized to
take out loans, but that the banks had disguised the loans as derivative swap
transactions to help hide the unauthorized losses. See Bennett & Marin, supra note
305, at 33.
488 Malaysian conglomerate Berjaya Group lost $14 million on a derivatives
transaction between Credit Suisse and Berjaya’s Cayman Islands’ subsidiary, and
sued in Malaysia High Court, claiming the transaction was unauthorized because the
Berjaya director who entered into the transaction had not obtained the required
approvals. See Stephen Duthie, Berjaya Group Files Suit Over Interest Rate Swap,
ASIAN WALL ST. J., Mar. 7, 1995, at 3.
96 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
triggered. The parties could do the same for fraud-related claims.
Cases might specify what type of misrepresentation would be
actionable. Consider the following case:
Case No. 4: Party A and Party B enter into the derivative
transaction described in the attached term sheet. Party A sends to
Party B the attached scenario analysis.489 Party B loses
materially490 more money on the derivative than the scenario
analysis had indicated Party B would lose. Held: Party A is not
entitled to payment from Party B of any amount owed, and Party
B is entitled to payment from Party A of any amount owed.
A series of similar cases could define the parameters of the
actionable misstatements, and thereby define precisely the parameters
of any disclaimer statements included in the contracts.491 The cases
would provide a guidepost indicating what sort of behavior would
constitute reasonable reliance by the purchaser.
Descriptions of cases in an ISDA Master Agreement might even
cover which contracts would fall under anti-gambling statutes.492 For
example, synthetic cases involving direct bets on a single economic
variable (i.e., interest rates, foreign exchange, stock prices) would be
enforceable, whereas cases involving complex bets on multiple
economic variables that could have been made more simply, or that
involve non-economic variables (e.g., bets on a sporting event) would
be unenforceable.
Finally, a synthetic common law regime could incorporate
whatever aspects of private law and private adjudication the parties
489 A scenario analysis indicates how a particular instrument is expected to
perform, given changes in one or more variables. Typically, scenario analysis is
provided by the more sophisticated derivative seller (e.g., Party A) to the less
sophisticated derivative buyer (e.g., Party B). For example, consider a derivative
contract that paid Party B $10 million x (JPY/USD – 100)/100 minus $10 million,
where JPY/USD is the Japanese Yen to U.S. Dollar exchange rate at the maturity of the
contract. A scenario analysis might resemble the following:
JPY/USD Payment Owed To (From) Party B
120 $2 million
110 $1 million
100 $0 million
90 ($1 million)
80 ($2 million)
If the numbers in the “Gain (Loss) to Party B” column were materially
inaccurate, Party A would not be entitled to payment from Party B of any amount
owed. For example, if materially was defined to be a deviation of more than one
percent, and the scenario analysis indicated that if JPY/USD = 80, the Payment Owed
To (From) Party B would be ($1 million), when the actual expected amount owed was
double that amount, then Party A would not be entitled to payment of the $2 million
owed to Party A by Party B.
490 Materially could be defined to be more than a certain percentage above the
amount of losses indicated in the scenario analysis. If the payoff from the derivative
security was linear, the exact amount of loss implied by the scenario analysis could
be calculated simply using linear interpolation. If the payoff from the derivative
security was non-linear, the exact amount of loss implied by the scenario analysis
could be calculated by Party A, with review by the adjudicator and/or appointed
experts.
491 See supra notes 454-461 and accompanying text.
492 See supra notes 316-324 and accompanying text.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
97
found of value. Nothing in the regime would prohibit parties from
signing a detailed ISDA agreement, or from specifying additional
provisions in the form of private law contractual language. Neither
would the regime prohibit the use of already-established arbitration or
mediation regimes, to the extent they were to accept the
methodology of reasoning by analogy to synthetic cases. Synthetic
common law simply adds another arrow or two to the quiver.
D. Institutional Barriers to Synthetic Common Law
What are the barriers to parties implementing a synthetic
common law regime today? There are several. First, there is no
evidence private parties have actively considered the idea; it may be
the case that no private party has thought to consider such a regime,
or that a few parties have considered it but either did not implement
the regime or did not publicize their implementation.
Second, arbitrators and arbitration systems might benefit from
uncertainty about future decisions. Arbitration regimes appear to
have a degree of market power493 and might benefit if its legal rules
and conclusions remain both secret and indeterminate.494 Synthetic
common law would turn arbitration into a much more commodity-like
product than it currently is.
Third, the prohibition of judicial advisory opinions495 prevents
courts from using synthetic common law, and might lead some courts
to balk at enforcing awards if the decision used advisory opinions.
The synthetic cases could be considered advisory opinions, although it
is arguable they are simply an expression of the intent of the parties,
in case form. Of course, if a federal district court were to implement
directly a synthetic common law regime, it almost certainly would be
reversed. But there is little reason to believe a court’s reliance on
such a system, especially given the limited standards of review of
arbitration judgments, would trigger much appellate court scrutiny.
Fourth, it is possible that there is market failure in the market for
competitive adjudication firms. There is some evidence that the
market for arbitration does not work particularly well, and there are
structural reasons competition among adjudicators might not be
effective. Judge Richard Posner has considered and rejected the
notion that a competitive industry might evolve in which adjudicators
competed for business, although he seems to have assumed such
competition could occur only on an ex post basis.496 Posner appears
493 There are reasons to believe arbitration may be the sort of business that leads
to oligopoly: there are economies of scale associated with arbitration, arbitration
may be a natural monopoly, and there may be a path dependence story in which
particular regimes are chosen first and then persist. In any event, there are only a few
arbitration regimes, the market is highly concentrated, and there has been very little
entry into or change in structure of the arbitration industry.
494 See Kamar, supra note 34 (making the same indeterminacy argument for
Delaware corporate law).
495 See HART & WECHSLER'S THE FEDERAL COURT AND THE FEDERAL SYSTEM 65-67
(Paul M. Bator et al., eds., 3d ed. 1988). Some state courts do not have a
constitutional prohibition against advisory opinions. See Barry Latzer, Whose
Federalism?, or Why “Conservative” States Should Develop Their State
Constitutional Law, 61 ALB. L. REV. 1399, 1413 (1998) (noting that “some state
courts, unlike the Supreme Court, have no prohibition against advisory opinions”).
496 “Hiring competitive judicial firms is not the answer either, quite apart from
the difficulty of maintaining consistency of legal decisions. Competition doesn’t
98 10/9/00 DRAFT – DO NOT CITE WITHOUT PERMISSION [VOL. #:#
not to have considered the possibility of dispute resolution firms
competing on an ex ante basis, as private synthetic common law
services would. In such a competitive environment, private parties
easily could assess the quality of firms, as well as the menu of already-
decided cases. Private parties considering competing firms could
examine the cases offered, read any additional decisions by the firms,
examine other representations as to process or mode of reasoning,
and then – after any dispute – compare the result with prior cases and
representations. Firms whose decisions did not match the agreed-
upon cases would not exist for long, because they would acquire a
reputation for such decisions, and private parties would not choose
them. By writing clear opinions in the cases it adjudicated, a firm
could obtain a competitive advantage over firms not offering such
opinions. For example, parties clearly are able to obtain sufficient
information to enable them to choose which judge in a particular
district they would like to govern their dispute; in fact, the selection
of a particular judge typically drives the parties’ litigation
strategies.497
Fifth, private law typically has been generated by sophisticated
parties, who benefit from the use of uniform contract terms when
contracting with less sophisticated parties. A few investment banks,
and primarily a single law firm, developed the standard form ISDA
contracts used in the derivatives area, and an unsophisticated party is
at a great disadvantage when negotiating over such documents with an
investment bank’s lawyers. As a result, many of the ambiguities and
omissions in these contracts may be intentional on the part of the
investment bank, but unanticipated or unknown on the part of the
less sophisticated counterparty. Synthetic common law might not
generate as serious an information asymmetry problem as private law
ISDA provisions, because a description of the results in particular
cases would be more obvious, even to an unsophisticated
counterparty. Suppose a sophisticated party selects synthetic cases
that are unfavorable to the unsophisticated party; at least in this
instance, the unsophisticated party would be able to (and likely would
want to) read the cases and might even recognize an unfavorable
result. In contrast, an unsophisticated party presented with a long,
standard-form contract written in broad, general terms is less likely to
read the contract and even less likely to understand it. If synthetic
common law would impose costs on the more sophisticated party to
an established contractual arrangement, that party naturally would
oppose the regime.
These arguments indicate some reasons why synthetic common
law is not the way of the world today, and some obstacles that would
need to be overcome in order to implement a synthetic common law
regime. They do not indicate that a synthetic common law regime
would be inefficient or unfair. There is support for private law regime
generally, and the Supreme Court has endorsed the notion of two
contracting parties in different jurisdictions specifying ex ante the law
work well when customers cannot determine even roughly the quality of the output
offered by the competing firms and when warranties or equivalent guarantees are
infeasible.” POSNER, OVERCOMING LAW, supra note 123, at 115.
497 A recent example of this was the selection of Judge Thomas Penfield Jackson
to adjudicate the antitrust suit by the U.S. Department of Justice against Microsoft.
2000] SYNTHETIC COMMON LAW
99
to be applied to their contractual relationship.498 These barriers could
be overcome, and, at the very least, the arguments supporting the
regime merit a try.
VI. CONCLUSION
Certainty is important. When the common law or its alternatives
cannot provide certainty, private parties may benefit from a system
of synthetic common law. In areas of rapidly evolving technology, it
is increasingly difficult for either public or private entities to specify
useful legal rules ex ante. In addition, as the cost of resolving disputes
increases, it is more difficult for judges or arbitrators to resolve
disputes in a fair and efficient manner ex post. A synthetic common
law regime captures the ex ante advantages associated with statutes,
while preserving the flexibility associated with ex post adjudication.
In this article, I have analyzed how parties transacting in
derivatives markets might use synthetic common law to resolve their
disputes. The proposal would provide much needed certainty to
derivatives market participants.499 I also have attempted to set forth
enough general principles and arguments to guide scholars in other
areas of rapidly evolving technologies500 to make use of the synthetic
common law idea.
As our society shifts to more synthesized experiences and virtual
realities, it is tempting to stick by what is authentic and real. Real
common law will always have a place in modern society, just as some
people always will prefer organic food, natural fur clothing,
antediluvian housing, and interacting with human beings rather than
computers. But in some segments of society, the cost of holding fast
to reality based on subjective or uncertain belief is too great. In those
areas, it is time to consider abandoning the reality of law.
498 See Scherk v. Alberto-Culver Co., 417 U.S. 506, 516 (1974) (stating that
where the governing law is unclear “[a] contractual provision specifying in advance
the forum in which disputes shall be litigated and the law to be applied is, therefore,
an almost indispensable precondition to achievement of the orderliness and
predictability essential to any international business dispute . . . .”).
499 It is difficult to overstate the importance of certainty to the derivatives
markets. Following the uncertainty associated with unwinding transactions
involving Long-Term Capital Management in August and September 1998, the
volume of derivatives trading dropped markedly. The Bank for International
Settlements said the “most striking development” in the derivatives market during
the first half of 1999 was the sharp decline in foreign exchange contracts, a decline
that began during the second half of 1998. See Global Derivatives Statistics, supra
note 269, at 6.
500 Likely candidates for a synthetic common law regime include
telecommunications, intellectual property, computer law, the Internet, and perhaps
commercial or corporate law.