Columbia Law School
Public Law & Legal Theory Working Paper Group
Paper Number 02-33
Courts or Tribunals? Federal Courts and the Common Law
BY
Peter L Strauss
Columbia Law School
Alabama Law Review, Forthcoming
This paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network electronic library at:
http//papers.ssrn.com/abstract=296031
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
* Vice Dean and Betts Professor of Law, Columbia University School of Law. Michael Dorf, Harold Edgar,
Cynthia Farina, Helen Hershkoff, Larry Kramer, John Manning, Henry Monaghan, Jim Pfander, and a faculty
workshop at Rutgers-Camden Law School all contributed thoughtful commentary on earlier drafts; any deficiencies
in this analysis are my doing only.
-1-
Courts or Tribunals? Federal Courts and the Common Law
Peter L Strauss*
“I do not think the United States would come to an end if we lost our power to declare an Act of Congress void. I
do think the Union would be imperiled if we could not make that declaration as to the laws of the several States.”
O.W. Holmes, Collected Legal Papers 295-96 (1920).
“I recognize without hesitation that judges do and must legislate, but they can do so only interstitially; they are
confined from molar to molecular motions. A common-law judge could not say I think the doctrine of
consideration a bit of historical nonsense and shall not enforce it in my court. No more could a
judge exercising the limited jurisdiction of admiralty say I think well of the common-law rules
of master and servant and propose to introduce them here en bloc."
O.W. Holmes, J., dissenting, in Southern Pacific Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 221 (1917) .
“[T]he standard so fixed scarcely advances the solution in a concrete case; it only eliminates the egregious,
leaving the tribunal a free hand to do as it thinks best. But that is inevitable unless liability is to be
determined by a manual, mythically prolix, and fantastically impractical. ... In the end
[my judgment] may seem merely a fiat, but that is always true, whatever the disguise.”
Learned Hand in Sinram v. Pennsylvania R. Co., 61 F.2d 767 (1932).
In his masterpiece, A Man For All Seasons, Robert Holt puts his protagonist, Thomas More, into
conversation with his son-in-law Roper. Rich, an evil character who will bring More's downfall, has just
left the stage:
Roper: While you talk he's gone!
M: And he should go, if he was the Devil himself, until he broke the law!
R: So now you'd give the Devil the benefit of the law!
M: Yes. What would you do? Cut a great road through the law to get after the Devil?
R; I'd cut down every law in England to do that!
M: Oh? And when the last law was down and the Devil turned round on you -- where would you
hide, Roper, the laws being all flat? This country's planted thick with laws from coast to coast --
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
1 Alexander v. Sandoval, U.S. , (2001), quoting Justice Scalia’s separate concurrence in Lampf, Pleva,
Lipkind, Prupis & Petigrow v. Gilbertson, 501 U.S. 350, 365 (1991).
2 Unied States v. Mead Corp. 121 S.Ct. 2164 (2001), discussed in Peter L. Strauss, Publication Rules in the
Rulemaking Spectrum: Assuring Proper Respect for an Essential Element, 53 Admin.L.Rev. 803 (2001); see Larry
Kramer, Judicial Asceticism, 12 Cardozo L. Rev. 1789, 1798 (1991].
-2-
man's laws, not God's -- and if you cut them down -- and you're just the man to do it – d'you
really think you could stand upright in the winds that would blow then? [Quietly] Yes, I'd give the
Devil the benefit of law, for my own safety's sake.
These words stand as an important warning to us today, as we work to contain and destroy the Devil
himself. They can serve, too, to introduce the less dramatic subject I had chosen when you honored me
with your invitation to give the Meador Lecture, well before the recent horrors so disturbed us all. I chose
as my text a recent Supreme Court dictum that had seemed to me to knock over quite a few trees:
“Raising up causes of action where a statute has not created them may be a proper function for common
law courts but not for federal tribunals.”1 What? When Article III established the federal judiciary its
drafters imagined something other than a court, as that term would then have been conventionally
understood, something different in kind from the black-robed members of state judiciaries? To invoke a
special class of “federal tribunal” whose actions are not to be confused with those of common law courts
suggests broader implications than the long-familiar debates about Erie, or the more recent contentions
over when if ever it is appropriate to infer privately enforceable judicial remedies in aid of federal statutes;
this seems to be about the nature of the institutions, not elements of their jurisdiction or prudential rules for
the exercise of their powers. The question has a lot less importance than diverting the dagger currently
aimed at America’s heart and the world’s liberties. But the aside was uttered in Alexander v. Sandoval,
a case that came to the Court from here in Alabama, and it directly evokes Professor Meador’s lifetime
of scholarship about federal courts. At the time it was hard to imagine a more appropriate subject for this
lecture; I hope you will forgive my continuing to address it, even as we honor our dead and confront yet
again the truth of enduring evil in our world.
Justice Antonin Scalia is the author of these words – he is quoting himself, as he likes to do, from an
earlier, lonelier concurrence. And there is some reason to think that, so far as common law method is
concerned he remains alone. In another of last Term’s decisions, that I have written about in a different
context, he was the sole dissenter from an opinion by Justice Souter that relied on the potential for case-
by-case development of an imperfect statutory framework to resolve a difficult issue of federal
administrative law – that is, the classic common law approach to resolution of an issue the Court concluded
had not been crisply resolved by Congress or its prior decisions.2 Justice Scalia’s dissent angrily insisted
on forcing what would be, in my judgment, an unnatural and unwise reading, to avoid any such inquiry,
necessarily subjective in his view. Justice Souter, writing for all the other members of the Court, remarked
that
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
3 A. Christopher Bryant & Timothy J. Simeone, Remanding to Congress: The Supreme Court’s New “On the
Record” Constitutional Review of Federal Statutes, 86 Cornell L.Rev. 328 (2001); Neal Devins, Congressional
Factfinding and the Scope of Judicial Review: A Preliminary Analysis, 50 Duke L.J. 1169 (2001), William W. Buzbee &
Robert A. Shapiro, Legislative Record Review, 54 Stan. L.Rev.87 (2001); Larry Kramer, Foreword: We the Court , 115
Harv.L.Rev. 1 (Nov. 2001), all discussing cases such as City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507 (199 ) and United States
v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000). [add others]
4 Manning/Eskridge debates in Colum.L.Rev.
5 I am not the only commentator to find in the current phase a remarkable activism, in the sense that the Court
is essentially dismissive of settled expectations, either of the legal community or of the legislature, in pursuing its
own vision of the proper state of the law. Kramer, Aleinikoff & Shaw, Strauss (SupCtRev), others?
6 Francis LieberLegal and Political Hermeneutics 28-31 (1839); Peter L. Strauss, the Common Law and Statutes,
70 U.Colo.L.Rev. 225 (1999); Stevens in WUVH, 449 U.S. 83 (1991); Reynolds v. Martin, 985 F/2d 470, 475 n. 2 (1993).
-3-
“Justice Scalia’s first priority over the years has been to limit and simplify. The Court’s choice has
been to tailor deference to variety. ... Our respective choices are repeated today.”
Yet while the Court as whole continues, perhaps unsurprisingly, to deploy the familiar methods of the
common law – insisting, notably, on the force of precedent as well as the possibility of case by case
development of doctrine – its members also join with some regularity in expressing doubts, as in Sandoval,
about federal courts fashioning law in the common law way. Indeed, modern times have brought greater
scholarly and judicial ferment about the judicial function than perhaps we have seen since the New Deal.
The Court’s work and the commentators engender the sense of a virtual revolution, whether the subject
is respect for congressional judgment about social fact,3 debates over the proper approach to statutory
interpretation,4 or – my subject tonight – suggestions that the courts of state judicial systems and the
“federal tribunals” of the national judiciary fundamentally differ in their nature. America has gone through
more than one cycle of judicial activism and retreat – the activism sometimes in service of liberal principles
and sometimes conservative ones; the retreats often under the banner of expressed appreciation for the
appropriate limits on judicial function. We are again, at least ostensibly,5 in a retreat phase. Yet this
retreat is marked by a quarrelsomeness in relation to Congress, a skepticism about its instructions, that
should signal to us that not only judicial modesty is in the air. Professions abound that the courts should act
as faithful servants of Congress in interpreting statutes, for example; yet one overhearing the conversations
between master and servant – seeing how they bicker, how uninterested the servant appears to be in the
context within which its master issued its instructions, how insistent it is on deploying its own sense of
syntax – could wonder just how “faithful” is the service being rendered.6
While strong-minded judges and debates over the propriety of judicial activism are hardly a new
phenomenon, all courts today – state as well as federal – face three linked challenges that put our
common-law suppositions about judicial process under considerable stress. These are the increasingly
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
7 Hart v. Massanari
8 But see Edward Hartnett, Questioning Certiorari
9 Viz., “It is admitted that there is no precedent for the present action by a servant against a master. We are
therefore to decide the question upon general principles, and in doing so we are at liberty to look at the
consequences of a decision the one way or the other.” Priestly v. Fowler, 3 Mees, & Wells 1, 150 Eng.Rep. 1030
(Exchequer of Pleas 1837).
-4-
statutory character of law, the proliferation of legal issues, and the explosion of judicial dockets. We could
see an number of linked results from these challenges: a heightening of judicial discretion over what issues
get decided; an emphasis then on law-making rather than case-deciding as the basis on which this
discretion gets exercised; a dramatically lowered exposure of trial and intermediate courts to principled
public correction; and a temptation for the high court, then, to speak in simple terms it might expect to have
broad impact rather than respond to the subtle particulars of complex facts. I want just briefly to set these
challenges and their results before you, and then turn to some recent Supreme Court decisions that may
illustrate the troubles, and shed some light on Justice Scalia’s Sandoval claim.
There are many important differences between today’s courts and those the Framers might have
imagined – our very ideas about such matters as precedent and stare decisis, as Judge Alex Kozinski
pointed out in an interesting opinion published last month, 7 owe a great deal to conventions about the
writing and publication of opinions that did not emerge until the Nineteenth Century. Among the most
important of these differences, in my judgment, is the conversion of appellate review into a discretionary
exercise substantially controlled, for its own ends, by the reviewing court.8 We have conferred on the
judiciary’s highest levels essentially free choice when to act; and our expectations are that they will choose
with reference to law-making rather than party claim to justice. Whether we imagine judicial lawmaking
as secondary or primary, these changes transform and deeply challenge the rationales we have for
tolerating it.
Prior to this century, to the extent people understood that courts independently shaped the law, they
would have understood that this function – what we can call the common law function – emerged from the
necessity to decide cases according to reason driven by party fact. This was a passive function, a
corollary of the obligation to decide, according to reason, any matters that parties put before them. One
looked first to established principle, to the force of stare decisis; if existing law did not control, the court
still had to decide – and the absence of controlling principle did not entail an automatic judgment for
defendant.9 Rather, the court was then to look to considerations of justice – what analogy to the
established structures of law best fit the facts on which the court was compelled to render decision – and
of policy – what outcome would best govern future cases that the court could imagine following upon this
one, once decision in the pending matter had acquired precedential force. The obligation to decide not
only excused the judicial presumption in lawmaking – new law was merely and unavoidably its byproduct,
the preferable alternative to automatically dismissing claims not previously provided for – the obligation to
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
10 Lecture I, following n. 19.
11 Southern Pacific Co. v. Jensen, 244 U.S. 205, 221 (dissent;1917).
12 Numbers from the last Term in paid and pro bono dockets, HLR.
13 Cass Sunstein, Leaving Things Undecided, 110 Harv.L.Rev. 4 (1996) and One Case at a Time 10-11 and Ch. 9
(1999).
-5-
decide also gave the polity some assurance against programmatic judicial lawmaking. The parties chose
the disputes, not the courts; the necessary force of the court’s decision was limited to the material facts of
the case before it; the facts of the next case, uncontrollable by the judges, might well compel a conclusion
looking in quite the opposite direction from its predecessor. Common law development was in this sense
the product of an invisible hand, if you like, that ineluctably provided corrections to doctrinal drift in one
direction by generating the facts and disputes that would illustrate its dangers. The “work of modification,”
Benjamin Cardozo remarked in his famous lectures on The Nature of the Judicial Process, “goes on inch
by inch. Its effects must be measured by decades and even centuries. Thus measured, they are seen to
have behind them the power and the pressure of the moving glacier.”10 They grow out of repeated
exposures to fact and perspective, exposures over which the judiciary had little control.
Justice Holmes, in an oft-cited dissenting passage, framed this understood authority in a way that
highlighted its subsidiary character:
I recognize without hesitation that judges do and must legislate, but they can do so only
interstitially; they are confined from molar to molecular motions. A common-law judge could not
say I think the doctrine of consideration a bit of historical nonsense and shall not enforce it in my
court. No more could a judge exercising the limited jurisdiction of admiralty say I think well of the
common-law rules of master and servant and propose to introduce them here en bloc.11
The necessity of the case, within the pre-existing general framework, set the confines within which judges
could act and, in acting, further confine those whose judgment would follow after theirs.
How different the judicial function has become since the Judges’ Bill created a power to choose which
matters our highest court would hear! Decision is no longer a necessity, nor new law merely its by-
product. A court with certiorari authority is not merely able, but is expected, to choose its targets with
reference to what law seems most important to enunciate. Having thousands of petitions from which to
select, say, 100 controversies for decision12 enables judges to have agendas. It encourages them to speak
more broadly than the particular facts before them require, counsel against that as we may.13 It permits
them to defend themselves against the inconvenience of facts that might appear to compel movement
opposite to the direction they prefer. And, thus, it inevitably heightens our sense that in appointing judges
we are appointing lawmakers and should be concerned with the kinds of law they are likely to make.
Freed from the discipline of the unavoidable call of justice, lured by the opportunity, perhaps even felt as
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
14 Consider in this respect the debate between the Eighth Circuit, Judge Arnold writing, Anastasoff v. United
States, 223 F.3d 898, vacated as moot on reh'g en banc, 235 F.3d 1054 (8th Cir. 2000) and the Ninth, per Judge
Kozinski, Hart v. Massanari, 2001 U.S. App. Lexis 20863, F.3d (9/2001).
15 George Priest, Strict Products Liability: The Original Intent, 10 Cardozo L. Rev.2301, 2302, 2329 (1989).
16 Goldberg v. Kollsman Instrument Corp., 12 N.Y.2d 432 (1963).
17 Strauss, 150 Cases.
18 Id.; Schauer on textualism as a second best.
-6-
responsibility, to speak broadly, the judge can shape her agenda as she chooses. We are used to this in
litigants, but not in judges. Even at intermediate levels of review, where appeal is a matter of right, the
realities of opinion-writing and publication – 80% of decisions rendered essentially invisible to any but the
immediate parties – entail similar possibilities and effects.14
Not often are the courts as candid about their power as was the New York Court of Appeals when
it cemented for New York the change in tort law George Priest has characterized as “a radical overturn
of 300 years of civil jurisprudence.”15 Its opinion opened with this remarkable sentence:
We granted leave to appeal in order to take another step toward a complete solution of the
problem partially cleared up in [two prior cases, both of which were decided after the making of
the orders being appealed from].16
While such candor is not often seen, and in this common law context the New York legislature could have
corrected the court had it wished to, the state of mind toward judicial function thus revealed is strikingly
different from what we ordinarily assume in rationalizing judicial development of the common law.
The limitations on decision at the highest courts not only tend to highlight their lawmaking function, but
also suggest threaten the viability of the context-specific techniques of common-law reasoning. Dockets
have swollen, and legal questions multiplied, but not the institution responsible for managing them. Thus,
the very changes that called forth the certiorari function have strong implications for the Supreme Court’s
possibility of generating coherence in the legal order, or effectively controlling the actions of lower courts.
Questions arising under any one of the dozens of complex federal statutory schemes, with enormous
financial or social consequences, will not be heard even once a year; no familiarity with that statute and its
administration will result. A circuit judge who might have expected his written opinions to gain the Court’s
attention three times a year when the Judges’ Bill was enacted, today must know that this will occur, on
average, less often than once in three years.17 We head towards one law for the Ninth Circuit, another for
the Third. The Justices of the Supreme Court, then, face a considerable temptation to follow Justice Scalia
into relatively simple, either-or, bright-line rules – approaches that avoid the rich contextualism and
modesty of classic common law reasoning, yet might from the Court’s perspective seem to promise control
over adventurism in the lower echelons of the federal judiciary.18
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
19 Larry Kramer, We the Court, 115 Harv.L.Rev. 1 (2001).
20 My thanks to Professor Kramer for suggesting this striking link between our papers.
21 D’Oench, Duhme & Co v. FDIC, 315 U.S. 447, 471 (Jackson, J., concurring)
-7-
Thus, we might think courts – and not just federal courts – ought to be thought of in contemporary
terms, certainly in terms transformed from what the Framers might have imagined. That rethinking is
perhaps especially called for in constitutional contexts, where the Supreme Court’s voice tends to exclude
the possibility of dialogue with Congress. You will want to read Professor Larry Kramer’s important
Foreword to the November issue of the Harvard Law Review, that I had the privilege to read as a paper
he delivered to my faculty this September.19 But my interest is at the more mundane level of ordinary law
– federal and state statutes, regulations, and the common law. Here, what the courts do legislatures can
undo, and one can fairly imagine the continuing processes that engage Congress, the agencies and the
courts as a kind of continuing dialogue. If not in a century ago, in today’s statute and agency-dominated
world, we can fairly characterize the judicial role in this dialogue as secondary – yet it is not absent, and
it is here that Justice Scalia’s trenchant observation intrigues me. If in the constitutional context, as Prof.
Kramer argues, the Court’s approach essentially excludes Congress from voice, in this more ordinary
setting it appears to be denying its own law-generating competence.20
Let me start by putting in front of you a contrasting formulation to Justice Scalia’s, framed by Justice
Robert Jackson in the immediate wake of Erie RR. v. Tompkins, one of those few cases I think I can
mention without having to tell you about it – at least for the moment:
The federal courts have no general common law, as in a sense they have no general or
comprehensive jurisprudence of any kind, because many subjects of private law which bulk large
in the traditional common law are ordinarily within the province of the states and not of the federal
government. But this is not to say that wherever we have occasion to decide a federal question
which cannot be answered from federal statutes alone we may not resort to all of the source
materials of the common law or that when we have fashioned an answer it does not become a part
of the federal non-statutory or common law. ... Were we bereft of the common law, our federal
system would be impotent. This follows from the recognized futility of attempting all-complete
statutory codes, and is apparent from the terms of the Constitution itself.21
For Justice Jackson, the field on which the Court might play was indeed a function of federal authority.
In contrast to state law federal law is invariably interstitial and so cannot be “general.” Yet that does not
render federal courts special “tribunals,” different in their nature from the common law courts of the states.
“Were we bereft of the common law, our federal system would be impotent.”
I mean to speak principally this afternoon about the little-noticed majority and dissenting opinions in
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
22 Cite [2000]
23 511 U.S. 164 (1994); Peter L. Strauss, On Resegregating the Worlds of Statute and Common Law,1994
Supreme Court Review 429, 509 ff. (1995).
24 It is important to distinguish here between the proposition that it is improper on, as it were, separation of
power grounds for federal courts to infer a remedy Congress has not provided for, and the conclusion that a
particular statutory scheme signals by its complexity, or by the judgments that have apparently been made, that it
would be inappropriate to that statue to infer such a remedy. See, e.g., Block v. Community Nutrition Inst.., 467 U.S.
340 (1984). A standard judicial move, which until rather recently a member of Congress would have had every reason
to expect, might indeed be inappropriate in particular circumstances, but thaty is not the voice of these opinions.
-8-
Alexis Geier v. American Honda Motor Company, Inc.,22 a 5-4 decision from the next previous Term
of the Supreme Court. Three of the four dissenting Justices in Geier also dissented from Sandoval, and
so did not subscribe to that majority’s “federal tribunals” characterization. Yet their Geier dissent seemed
strongly to express the same sentiment, that federal judges and state judges are different in kind. That is
where we will spend most of our remaining time. Before turning to Geier, however, I want first briefly to
set before you some other illustrations of this problem, to set its context.
One, about which I have previously written, is the the Supreme Court’s 1994 decision in Central
Bank of Denver v. First Interstate Bank of Denver.23 The question in the lower courts had been how
to understand Central Bank’s possible liability for aiding and abetting others’ violations of SEC Rule
10b(5) in a private action First Interstate had brought under the authority of that rule. The possibility of
private actions under Rule 10b(5) had long been established. For at least sixteen years, the SEC had been
bringing enforcement actions against alleged aiders and abetters; all eleven circuit courts of appeal to face
the question had also sustained private actions against aiders and abetters; Congress had thoroughly
revised the securities statutes without any question being raised about this development. In the certiorari
process seeking Supreme Court review, as well, the papers suggested no issue on this score. In a
common law world, one would say the issue of aider and abettor liability had come to rest. The Supreme
Court, however, reached out and asked for argument on the question; it then decided, on the basis of its
conclusions about what the 1934 Congress had enacted, that aider and abettor liability could not be
sustained. That judgment about the understanding of the Congress in 1934 might have been right or it
might have been wrong. Justice Stevens, writing in dissent for four Justices, plausibly argued that the
majority’s interpretation was, to say the least, anachronistic. What I want to call to attention to for present
purposes is the Court’s striking independence in reaching out for an issue that parties had not raised, yet
which served an agenda reflected in many decisions of the current majority, most recently Sandoval itself
– that of subordinating private actions for the enforcement of federal regimes, that have not been directly
provided for by statute. The Court used its certiorari prerogative to serve its own policy ends. And, as
in Sandoval, those ends were to deny conventional common law moves to federal courts – and thus to
terminate any sense of continuing legislative/executive/judicial conversation about the development of law,
any sense of partnership in which courts provisionally work toward integration.24 In the Central Bank
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
25 Cf. United States v. Mead Corp., (Scalia, J., dissenting).
26 Cite
-9-
majority’s contemplation, statutes and regulations are static texts – subject to future development only by
the legislature or executive, yet to be accorded meaning by courts applying their own and rather
independent syntactic views.25
This want of sensitivity and attention to the possibilities of integration is suggested by an opinion from
the Term just ended. Egelhoff v. Egelhoff26 presented questions of preemption of state law by federal,
another context where one might expect the fact-driven and cautious processes of the common law to
dominate. David Egelhoff died intestate just two months after finalizing his divorce from his wife Donna.
Under the terms of their settlement, she had received a business, an IRA account, and stock; he had
retained 100% ownership of his pension and life insurance under his employer’s plan. That plan was
subject to ERISA, the federal statute regulating retirement plans. He had neglected to redesignate the
beneficiaries under these benefits, so that when he died the primary beneficiary named in his policy
remained “Donna Egelhoff wife.” A Washington state statute provided for this contingency; in such a case,
it said, non-probate assets should pass as if the divorced spouse had predeceased the decedent. Thus,
they would go to his secondary beneficiaries under the plan, his children. ERISA, on the other hand, states
that the federal statute “shall supersede any and all State laws insofar as they may now or hereafter relate
to any employment benefit plan.” Acknowledging that the operative terms, “relate to,” were so indefinite
as to threaten infinite preemption of state law, Justice Thomas’s majority opinion nonetheless found that a
state rule specifying a beneficiary other than the one mentioned in the plan would unacceptably burden plan
administrators and so must be regarded as preempted.
It is striking that the majority, whose members have generally been so solicitous of state interests, gave
the federal statute such broad sweep. As Justice Breyer’s dissent observed, Washington law would be
permitted to govern if Donna had actually predeceased David (or had murdered him); there is no
necessary conflict with the federal statute; the injustice of the result commanded by the majority opinion is
transparent; and it interferes with state judgments in contexts, those of inheritance and the consequences
of marital dissolution, that are of central importance to state and not federal policy. It is virtually
inconceivable that Congress would have chosen this outcome; the plan in terms contained provisions
pointing at David’s children as beneficiaries if his beneficiary designation was invalid – and making the
designation invalid was what state law accomplished. The majority’s response to these arguments was to
advance highly improbable hypotheticals which, it asserted, could not be distinguished in principle from the
case at hand. Even acknowledging the indeterminacy of the statutory language, it is as if they feared
acknowledging any responsibility for reconciling state and federal law for themselves; it must all be placed
in the lap of Congress or, rather, Congress’s language as the judges chose to read it. For the dissent, the
better course would be to “apply[] pre-emption analysis with care, statute by statute, line by line, in order
to determine how best to reconcile a federal statute’s language and purpose with federalism’s need to
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
27 [121 S.Ct. 1693.]
28 Justices ... with agendas which go beyond the just resolution of current cases are likely to plant
seeds in opinions which can be nourished and made to bloom in later cases. The common law
concept of dicta aims to inhibit and thwart such ploys. Accepted legal methodology instructs that
general expressions in judicial opinions are to be geared back to the specific case facts which
generated them. The problem is that judges who are willing to plant language in their opinions for
future fruition will disrespect these methodological constraints, including the fact that the
language appeared in a dissent, when it suits their purpose in a future case.
Richard Cappelli, A Legal Method Look at Rogers v. Tennessee,
http://www.angelfire.com/pa4/cappalli/analysis.htm, visited October 10, 2001.
29 Id.
-10-
preserve state autonomy.” For the majority, perhaps conscious of the implications for their cpacity to
control the actions of lower courts, the development of a common law on the subject was not to be
trusted.
The last preliminary case I’d like to mention before turning to Geier is Rogers v. Tennessee,27 a case
notable here less for its result than for Justice Scalia’s planting of what appear to be seeds for future
developments along this line.28 Wilbert Rogers stabbed James Bowdery in the heart in 1994; surgery to
repair the wound failed to prevent Bowdery’s immediate loss of mental function and lapse into a coma
from which he could not be expected to recover. Bowdery was maintained on life support for fifteen
months, however, until a kidney infection carried him away, and so he did not die within a year and a day
of the stabbing. A 1907 case had described death within a year and a day as a common-law element of
second degree murder, the offense of which Rogers was convicted in state courts. That description need
not have been taken as holding.29 A 1989 statute had abolished common law defenses in the state, and
might have been taken to abrogate this rule. Yet the Tennessee Supreme Court found that Tennessee law
did encompass such a rule, and that it had survived that statutory change. Acting, then, in a common law
mode, it found the rationale for the rule had lapsed, and so overruled it. In this context, with the year-and-
a-day rule definitively established as having been a part of Tennessee law on the dates both of the stabbing
and of Bowdery’s death, the question for the Supreme Court was whether abrogation of the rule deprived
Rogers of due process of law, given its retrospective effect and the explicit constitutional prohibition on ex
post facto legislation. Could a common law court make law, in this respect, in ways that a legislature could
not?
I hold no brief for Justice O’Connor’s conclusion for a group identifiable as the five middle Justices of
the Court, that Tennessee could constitutionally effect this change to Rogers’ detriment. Claims of
unfairness arising from the characteristic retrospectivity of changes in the common law are often properly
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
30 Cf. Securities & Exchange Commission v. Chenery Corp., 332 U.S. 194 (1947).
31 It is inconceivable that the wielder of a butcher knife inflicting numerous deep wounds would or could so
calculate a stab penetrating his victim’s heart, meaning to cause death (a remaining element of the offense for which
Rogers was convicted), that it would not to cause that death until more than a year and a day had lapsed.
32 Justice Scalia does not indicate why he takes late Eighteenth Century (Fifth Amendment) rather than
Nineteenth Century (Fourteenth Amendment) readings of judicial function to be controlling.
33 Laurence Friedman,
-11-
answered by arguments denying proper reliance – that one ought to have seen this change coming,30 or
that knowledge of the change could not be imagined to have affected the behavior concerned.31 The
persuasiveness of these answers in the particular case of the criminal law does not turn on the Ex Post
Facto Clause alone. Justices Scalia, Thomas, Breyer and Stevens – an unusual quartet – strongly
dissented. What caught my eye in relation to today’s talk was that Justice Scalia took the occasion for a
lengthy disquisition on the proposition that, as a historical matter, the authors of the Fifth Amendment’s
Due Process Clause would not have thought common law judges had the “power to change the common
law.”32 The discussion is hedged with qualifiers; both Justice Stevens and Justice Breyer, to varying
degrees, distance themselves from it even so. Yet the remarkable fact is that it is there at all. It would not
have been hard to dissent without it.
One senses here the further building of an argument, by one who professes no judicial authority to
make law, for radical change in our conception of what it means to be a court – or, at the least, a “federal
tribunal.” Justice Scalia conceded that the new American courts, that had so recently freed themselves
from the English yoke, “felt themselves perfectly free to pick and choose which parts of the English
common law they would adopt.” One of the great early figures of American law, Chancellor James Kent,
describing his self-conception in late eighteenth century New York, wrote that
I took the court as if it had been a new institution, and never before known in the United States.
I had nothing to guide me, and was left at liberty to assume all such English Chancery powers and
jurisdiction as I thought applicable. ...This gave me grand scope, and I was checked only by the
revision of the Senate, or Court of Errors. ...
My practice was, first, to make myself perfectly and accurately. ..master of the facts. ...I saw
where justice lay, and the moral sense decided the court half the time; and I then sat down to
search the authorities until I had examined my books. I might once in a while be embarrassed by
a technical rule, but I most always found principles suited to my views of the case. ... .33
One would hardly suggest that judges of the time felt free to adopt any rule they chose; the system and
broadly stated principles of the common law required adherence, even as the judge accommodated them
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
34 One readily understands in this way Judge Kent’s contemporaneous refusal to reach a conclusion he knew
judges of the continent would reach but that he could not reconcile with the premises of the common law, although
“if the matter were res integra with the common law, I would be overwhelmed by the reasoning of the civilians.”
Seixas v. Woods, 2 Caines 48 (Sup.Ct. N.Y. 1804).
35 The majority writes as if the claim was specifically that the Honda lacked an airbag; the dissent reiterates, with
a cite to the joint appendix (App. 3) that Ms. Geier’s complaint was about the absence of any “effective and safe
passive restraint system, including, but not limited to, airbags,” that might have reduced her injuries from those she
suffered. Since she was wearing a buckled manual lap and shoulder belt at the time of the accident, it is hard to
imagine that the alternative passive restraint devices that had been demonstrated to meet the requirements of
Standard 208 at the time, automatic seat belts, would have been any more effective in preventing her injury than the
manual devices she in fact used. While room was left for the development of alternative, cheaper and safer passive
restraint systems in the Standard, nothing at the time (or in subsequent developments) suggests that this
opportunity had been availed of by any manufacturer.
-12-
to the particular facts before him and to changing social circumstance.34 Yet Justice Scalia’s way of
putting it appears to threaten these common law functions of dynamic accommodation and change, at least
for “federal tribunals” – even at Justice Holmes’ level of the molecular. The argument being built, the
agenda apparently being pursued, is stunning indeed.
Now at last let us turn to Geier v. American Honda. This case was a minor event in the Supreme
Court’s 1999 October Term, yet a curious one in several respects. Ms. Geier had been driving her 1987
Honda, using the manual lap and shoulder belts with which it came equipped, when she ran her car into a
tree. She suffered injuries more serious, she claimed, than she would have suffered had the Honda been
equipped with a driver’s side airbag [or other equally safe and effective passive restraint device].35 The
question presented was whether Honda could be held liable in a product liability action at common law for
this failure to equip its product with a readily available safety device. Honda was in compliance with the
then operative federal regulatory standard on passive restraint devices, which required that it equip only
10% of its fleet with passive restraint devices (not necessarily airbags); it had done so, but by equipping
cars other than the one Ms. Geier happened to buy. Whether that compliance with federal standards
operated to shield it from possible liability under the ordinary tort law of the jurisdiction required, inter alia,
understanding two provisions of the federal statute in evident tension with one another.
Under 15 U.S.C. §1392(d),
Whenever a Federal motor vehicle safety standard established under this subchapter is in effect,
no State or political subdivision of a State shall have any authority either to establish, or to continue
in effect, with respect to any motor vehicle or item of motor vehicle equipment[,] any safety
standard applicable to the same aspect of performance of such vehicle or item of equipment which
is not identical to the Federal standard.
Under 15 U.S.C. §1397(k), however
Compliance with any Federal motor vehicle safety standard issued under this subchapter does not
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
36 In 1988, Justice Scalia was the author of Boyle v. United Technologies Corp., 487 U.S. 500, that in effect
extended to defense contractors the benefit of the “discretionary function” exemption from tort liability Department
of Defense officials would enjoy under the Federal Torts Claims Act, for specifying design elements in military
equipment that a court might otherwise find to have been defectively (negligently) designed. Over the dissents of
the liberal wing of the Court as it then was, he found “uniquely federal interests,” at 505, warranting a uniform
national rule to assess the possible liability of defense contractors – federal common law – and significant conflict
between those interests and the operation of state law, at 507, if the design the federal government affirmatively
required could be made the source of manufacturer liability for defective design. Justice Brennan, for Justices
Blackmun and Marshall, dissented essentially on Erie grounds. Justice Stevens dissented on the basis of prudential
concerns that in balancing “the conflicting interests in the efificient operation of a massive governmental program
and the protection of the rights of the individual ... we should defer to the expertise of Congress.” At 532. For
neither Justice Scalia nor Justice Stevens, it would appear, did some special characteristic of “federal tribunals”
-13-
exempt any person from any liability under common law.
Nine Justices agreed that neither state legislative nor state executive authority could adopt requirements for
vehicle safety differing from federal standards – that under the first of these provisions, state lawmaking on
a subject otherwise easily within reach of state authority had been mjnsuspended. But judicial law-making
power, it appeared, was reserved; and on the implications of this reservation the Court divided 5-4.
For the majority, Justice Breyer writing, the savings clause served only to preclude automatic
preemption of common law authority. The Secretary in adopting any given standard could indicate special
circumstances that would preclude a particular, conflicting state common law rule. If the Secretary did not
do so, the courts might nonetheless be able to find a disabling conflict. Such a conflict was established, in
this case, by the Secretary’s affirmative wish to require only gradual deployment of passive restraint
devices. A common law standard of care imposing a universal obligation to equip cars with such devices
would necessarily conflict with a federal standard that attached affirmative importance to gradualism, and
so, the Court held, could not survive. Note that, as neither Congress nor the Secretary had made this
judgment, the majority was, necessarily, asserting a law-making authority in the federal courts –
corresponding roughly to the law-making authority the courts have exercised in “dormant Commerce
Clause” cases excluding various state regulatory measures for conflict with interstate commerce .
For the minority, Justice Stevens writing, “this is a case about federalism,” about the respect owed
state courts’ law-making powers. Acknowledging that Congress or the Secretary might have excluded
state judges (as well as state executives and state legislatures) from acting in ways inconsistent with federal
regulations, the minority stressed that this had not happened. Federal courts, it argued, could not
appropriately develop the law in such a setting; they had necessarily to await instructions from the other
branches, lest the traditional powers of state courts to create law be impinged. Justice Stevens’ opinion
invokes the spectre of unelected “federal judges ... running amok” with authority that can be appropriately
entrusted only to elected representatives.
The curiosities in the case are several. The majority for whom Justice Breyer wrote comprised the
Chief Justice and Justices Kennedy, O’Connor and Scalia36; the minority, in addition to Justice Stevens,
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
distinguish them from their state counterparts.
37 See n. 44 within.
38 41 U.S. 1 (1842).
39 304 U.S. 64 (1938).
40 E.g.,Edward A. Purcell, Brandeis and the Progressive Constitution (2000); Bradford R. Clark, Federal
Common Law: A Structural Reinterpretation, 144 U.Pa.L.Rev. 1245 (1996); Larry Kramer, The Lawmaking Power of the
Federal Courts, 12 Pace L.Rev. 263 (1992); Martha Field, Sources of Law: The Scope of Federal Common Law, 99
-14-
Justices Ginsburg, Souter and Thomas. Usual lines of division, whether the broad liberal-conservative
scale, or even other contexts for attachment to “federalism” as an important issue for the Court, do not
appear.
Strikingly, for all the dissenting talk about the importance of the States and the traditional state common
law function, as a technical matter this was not a case about conflict between federal and state law. As no
Justice thought significant enough to address, Alexis Geier’s accident occurred in the District of Columbia.
The common law developed there is federal common law,37 its judges federal judges, as were the
common law and the judges of the federal territories. Of course it might as easily have been Maryland or
Virginia. But it was not. The constitutional status of the District of Columbia – for example, in respect of
the Fourteenth Amendment’s requirement that states assure equal protection of the laws – has long been
a challenge, perhaps best swept under the carpet as here. The habit of regarding the District as a state
might even redound, one day, to the benefit of its citizens.
What these curiosities may do is direct our attention to the possibility that the real stakes here too have
less to do with federalism, than with the question whether our national courts are courts in the same sense
as are local courts – those in the states and those in the District of Columbia alike. Whether the federal
airbag standard and the local common law rule being argued for were in such conflict that the two could
not stand was, undoubtedly, a federal question. As that question had not been answered by Congress or
by the Secretary of Transportation, it had to be answered by the federal courts. Federal judicial
lawmaking – the judicial articulation of a controlling federal standard – the dissent argued, would be
inappropriate, because local judicial lawmaking – the only kind of local lawmaking that remained even
arguably available given §1392(d) – is so important. Judicial lawmaking in local judges is of central
importance, even when other forms of lawmaking are forbidden local authorities. Judicial lawmaking in
federal judges is suspect, raises the spectre of judges run amok, even when invoked in aid of detailed law
created by other, legitimate lawmakers. A certain tension is evident between these two propositions.
Discussions of the common law authority of federal courts are conventionally framed by Swift v.
Tyson38 and Erie RR v. Tompkins39. The rich literature appearing under their influence has invoked
considerations of federalism, separation of powers, (relatedly) democratic principle, and changing
conceptions about the nature of the common law to derive theoretical structures for this question.40 The
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
Harv. L.Rev. 881 (1986); Thomas Merrill, The Common Law Powers of Federal Courts, 52 U.Chi.l.Rev. 1 (1985);
William Fletcher, The General Common Law and Section 34 of the Judiciary Act of 1789: The Example of Marine
Insurance, 97 Harv.L.Rev. 1513 (1984); Tony Freyer, Harmony & Dissonance: The Swift and Erie Cases in American
Federalism (1981); Henry Monaghan, The Supreme Court, 1974 Term – Foreword: Constitutional Common Law, 89
Harv.L.Rev. 1(1975); Henry J. Friendly, In Praise of Erie – and of the New Federal Common Law, 39 N.Y.U.L.Rev. 383
(1964).
41 William Fletcher’s The General Common Law and Section 34 of the Judiciary Act of 1789: The Example of
Marine Insurance, n. 40 above,
-15-
spectre of judges who might run amok has a distinguished political history in this country, most prominently
in relation to constitutional law (where the legislature is not available to control their running) but also in
respect of judicial attitudes towards statutory interpretation and statutory intrusions on judge-made law,
and also the common-law function simpliciter. Both constitutional and prudential concerns can be imagined
to underlay these concerns: constitutional concerns about whether courts are permitted to be lawmakers
in contradistinction to legislatures; and prudential concerns about the relative merits of legislative and
judicial lawmaking, supposing the latter is permitted to occur.
Whether federal courts are permitted to be lawmakers might seem to have been settled, as Justice
Jackson argued, by the Constitution’s creation of a judiciary in the familiar English mold and reference in
constitutional text to such common law concepts as the sanctity of contracts. To be sure, the Constitution
vests in Congress “all legislative Powers” – that is, the power to enact free-standing statutes having the
force of law. Courts uncontroversially lack any such power (save possibly an inherent authority to adopt
rules of procedure to control their own business). Yet the common law system of precedent and stare
decisis just as uncontroversially permits judges to find duties which they enforce against the parties, that
one could not have found before they acted; and the system as a whole enforces a whole range of duties
that draw their legal force only from accumulated judicial pronouncements. Thus, one might suppose that
the constitutional description of judicial power, extending to “all cases, in Law and Equity, arising under
this Constitution, the Laws of the United States, and Treaties made, or which shall be made, under their
Authority,” imagined that the federal courts Congress could create to exercise that power would be courts
in the ordinary understanding – that is, common law courts or equity courts of that time, before the
universal mergers of the twentieth century.
I risk here, as others have before me, a certain anachronism. For contemporary eyes, it is hard to
escape the conclusion that courts make law when they enforce a duty or require adherence to a
construction that was not previously certain, and the operation of stare decisis assures that this conclusion
will be projected into future controversies. Further, we think of that law in positivistic terms – it is the law
of New York, or Alabama, or the United States. As William Fletcher among others has shown,41 in the
early years of the Republic federal (and other) courts acted as common law courts without necessary
attention (save where “local law” was clearly in point) to the question which sovereign’s law they were
enunciating; what Holmes would later dismiss as a brooding omnipresence in the sky, the universality of this
body of general principle was what made their work uncontroversial. Only when they had to tie the
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
42 United States v. Hudson and Goodwin, 7 Cranch U.S. 32 (1812). It seems unnecessary for these purposes to
delve into the debates among William Crosskey and others over the precise extent to which common law and
jurisdiction were tied. Crosskey finds in early history an understanding that federal common law could control state
common law, William W. Crosskey, Politics and the Constitution in the History of the United States chs. 21-26
(1953). His work attracted extended critical responses by some distinguished reviewers that it would be an
understatement to call insulting. See, e.g., Ernest Brown, 67 Harv.L.Rev.. 1439 (1954); Henry L. Hart, 67 Harv.L.Rev.
1457 (1954); Julius Goebel, 54 Colum.L.Rev. 450 (1954). Yet the passages on federal common law expectations seem
to have escaped these attacks, and drew praise from other distinguished commentators, Malcolm Sharp, 54
Colum.L.Rev. 439, 440 (1954); Irving Brandt, 54 Colum.L.Rev. 443, 450 (1954); Arthur Corbin, 62 Yale L.J. 1137 (1953);
Charles Clark, 21 U. Chi. L. Rev. 24, 31 (1953); Grant Gilmore, The Age of Aquarius: On Legal History in a Time of
Troubles, 39 U.Chi.L.Rev. 475, 485 (1972) and The Ages of American Law 117 n.3 (1977). Morton Horwitz’s The
Transformation of American Law 1780-1860 Ch. 1 (1977), suggests an awakening American realization that the
common law was not a natural law artifact to be discovered but the product of human reasoning by authorized
lawmakers acting in particular jurisdictions, that could be turned to social ends.
43 Grant Gilmore, The Ages of American Law pp. 11 and 19 ff. (1977).
44 The issue is not in my judgment settled by reference to the absence of a federal reception statute, as was
sometimes argued. See Wheaton v. Peter, 33 U.S. 591, 658 (1834), discussed in Gilmore, supra, at 117 n. 3 and 121
n.22.. If such a statute were necessary, it would have been required for places where the common law had no
connection to state authority, yet Congress’s performance in those contexts hardly exceeded in specificity the
Constitution’s reference to “all cases in Law and Equity.” The Northwest Ordinance of 1787, 1 Stat. 51,52 states
only that the court whose appointment is provided for “shall have a common law jurisdiction” and that the
Territory’s inhabitants “shall always be entitled to the benefits of ... judicial proceedings according to the course of
the common law.” See R. Kent Greenawalt, The Rule of Recognitions and the Constitution, 85 Mich.L.Rev. 621, 648-
49 (1987).
Similarly, the laws creating the District of Columbia simply established them as having cognizance of “all cases
in law and equity.” 2 Stat. 103 Sec. 5 (1801). Congress provided for the continuance in effect of the laws of the
states from which the District was created, Virginia and Maryland, “until Congress shall otherwise by law provide,” 1
Stat. 130 Sec. 1 (1790) and 2 Stat. 103 Sec. 1 (1801), but never seems to have thought it necessary to free the east and
west banks of the Potomac from the need to follow developing explications of the common law in Richmond and
Annapolis, respectively; while heeding those jurisdictions’ constructions of statutes the District thus inherited, see
Hawley v. Hawley, 114 F.2d 745 (D.C. Cir. 1940), Clawans v. Sheetz, 92 F.2d 517 (D.C. Cir. 1937), the D.C. courts
appear to have made their common law their own. See Busby v. Electric Utilities Employees Union, 65 S.Ct. 142
(1944). While Prof. Fletcher reports early attention to the fact of these directions, his account also makes clear that
the federal courts sitting on the Virginia (and, one supposes, Maryland) side of the Potomac felt no inhibition
-16-
common law to the law of a particular jurisdiction did controversy arise; if federal courts could deploy the
common law to define federal crimes, what would keep Congress within the limited law-making authority
the Constitution had conferred?42 But in the midst of the disputes over states rights and slavery that would
become the Civil War, Justice Story could write of universal principles of common law in Swift v. Tyson
without provoking that concern. Federal courts were indisputably, uncontroversially common law courts,
acting as all such courts did to enunciate principle even during those times – Llewellyn’s Golden Age or
Gilmore’s Age of Discovery43 – when they quite clearly understood that their task was accommodating
general law, never expressed by anyone but judges, to the realities of a new continent and a new age.44
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
following their own views of the best rule, where the lex loci was not involved. 97 Harv.L.Rev. at 1534 n.103 and
1541. See also id., 1524-25, 1575 (little concern with reception statutes or like formalities).
45 These diagrams make three assumptions: first, that the federal government has limited legislative authority;
second, that this limited authority overlaps, but neither completely subsumes nor is completely subsumed by, the
fields within which state courts uncontroversially might make common law; and, finally, that even if one were to
allocate the realms within which state courts make common law between “general” and “local” subjects, at least
some of the “general” subjects would fall outside the area of federal legislative competence. These propositions
would surely have been agreed with in Swift’s time, although our expansive contemporary notion of federal
legislative competence makes them more uncertain today.
46 U.S. Const. Art. VI. Before reflexively dismissing the argument on the ground that “Laws” in the Supremacy
Clause must mean “statutes,” and not the common law, the reader should pause to consider that the same clause’s
“any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding” must certainly refer to the
common law and, indeed, that the same proposition underlies the Supreme Court’s eventual reading of “laws of the
several states” in Section 34 of the Judiciary Act of 1789 to refer to state common as well as statutory law as
constituting the rules of decision in diversity cases.
-17-
Realm of the
common law
Area of fede-
ral legisla-
tive com-
petence
State common law
controls absent
federal statutes
Exclusive federal
legal authority
Realm of the
common law
Area of fede-
ral legisla-
tive com-
petence
State common
law controls
Exclusive federal
legal authority
Shared common
law authority
local attributes
Realm of the
common law
Area of fede-
ral legisla-
tive com-
petence
State common
law controls
Federal statute &
common law
controls
Neither of the attorneys in Swift seemed to have thought the Court’s common law authority settled by
earlier decisions. Their arguments suggested three possibilities I want to put before you in schematic
form45 – first, that in the absence of federal statute, state common law must control; second, the possibility
we associate with the case, that outside the realms of local matters and federal statutes, state and federal
courts shared a non-exclusive common law authority; and third, that common law judgments properly
articulated by the Supreme Court independent of state common law – that is, within the reach of federal
lawmaking authority – would be among the “Laws ... made under the authority of the United States”46 by
which state court judges would be bound. Note that it would not have been hard to conclude, although
Justice Story did not explicitly state, that the case was within Congress’s lawmaking authority. It
presented a standard problem of commercial law, and Swift’s attorney, hoping to avoid confronting
defenses Tyson might have made under New York law against those to whom he had made the note,
strongly argued a need for uniformity, grounded in the needs of interstate and foreign commerce. Implicit
in the argument was our third possibility – that a federal rule, if proper, would control – in the same manner
as federal admiralty law controlled the states, or the dormant commerce clause. The second possibility
appears in the arguments of Tyson’s attorney, who argued as if, should the Court find authority to develop
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
47 Edward A. Purcell, Jr., Brandeis and the Progressive Constitution [39-40, 46, 51-52, 55, 58] (2000).
-18-
a federal common law rule on the subject, that common law rule, of necessity, would be only for the
federal courts. Since it would have no authority over state courts, he argued, it would permit a “perpetual
confliction” between federal and possibly differing state law rules. The only proper conclusion, he argued,
was that state law must apply.
The difference in premises might have seemed unremarkable to anyone who had followed the political
struggles of the preceding decades, but has largely passed from view today. Justice Story wrote Swift as
if he were addressing a natural field for national law. He discussed the commercial law issues in the case
in a way that prominently suggested Congress’s ability to reach them under the clause empowering it to
regulate interstate and foreign commerce. As a result, it was at least open to future courts to discover that
the capacity of federal courts he was asserting had two qualities: first, that it was limited to matters
respecting which Congress had authority to legislate; second, that this federal common law was binding on
the states – in the same manner in which a state’s common law, on questions respecting which Congress
could not legislate, would control the decisions of the federal courts (or the courts of any other state
applying that law under conflicts of law principles) to which it applied. This is the state of affairs illustrated
by the third diagram above: a limited domain for federal common law, coextensive with federal legislative
competence, and within which federal common law is controlling on all courts, federal and state.
The federal courts did not develop Swift in this way. Rather, they took Swift to assert a privilege of
the federal courts to declare “general” common law that was coordinate with the authority of the state
courts (save only distinctly “local” questions reserved exclusively to the states); and over time the courts
lost sight of any possible limitation of this privilege to settings within Congress’s legislative competence.
The brilliant recent scholarship of Professor Edward A. Purcell, Jr.,47 describes as “the most pervasive and
enduring achievement” of the late Nineteenth-Century Supreme Court its movement “to establish the
primacy of the national judiciary” in just this way. Justices like David Josiah Brewer
repeatedly ... voted to reaffirm the constitutional limitation on congressional power [over the
insurance industry], and just as regularly used the authority of the federal courts to make general
common law rules for insurance contracts. ... The Constitution gave Congress ‘no general grant
of legislative power’ ... . Conversely, Article III ‘granted the entire judicial power of the Nation’
to the federal courts, and its charter was ‘not a limitation nor an enumeration.’ Rather, Article III
granted ‘all the judicial power which the new Nation was capable of exercising’ ... Thus, he
established a more flexible and expansive test for judicial power than for legislative power,
necessarily broadening the reach of the former beyond that of the latter.
This led, notoriously, to the results catalogued at length by dissenters and academics through the late
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries: those who could use the diversity jurisdiction were sometimes
afforded a choice of applicable law unavailable to other litigants; and federal courts purported to have the
right to declare federal law on questions about which Congress could not legislate. Neither result was
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
48 27 Stat. 531.
-19-
intellectually sustainable.
Erie’s dominant voice, its constitutional voice, is repudiation of Justice Brewer’s interpolation, “the
power to declare rules of decision which Congress was confessedly without power to enact as statutes,”
permitting diversity parties an unjustifiable choice of law when the “persistence of state courts in their own
opinions on questions of common law prevented uniformity.” The fault lay both in the presumption of
acting outside federal legislative power, and in the (corresponding) failure to make the federal rule
exclusive. “In attempting to promote uniformity of law throughout the United States, the doctrine had
prevented uniformity in the administration of the law of the State” and, by empowering diversity parties to
require decision on the basis of otherwise inapplicable general federal common law, denying the equal
protection of the laws.
Just as Swift was read to claim more for federal courts that could properly be claimed, Erie can be
read to disclaim more than it must – to insist, in effect, on the situation of the first diagram above. The
paragraph that contributes most to this understanding is perhaps the following:
Third. Except in matters governed by the Federal Constitution or by Acts of Congress, the law
to be applied in any case is the law of the State. And whether the law of the State shall be
declared by its Legislature in a statute or by its highest court in a decision is not a matter of federal
concern. There is no federal general common law. Congress has no power to declare substantive
rules of common law applicable in a State whether they be local in their nature or "general," be
they commercial law or a part of the law of torts. And no clause in the Constitution purports to
confer such a power upon the federal courts.
Consider, for example, “Congress has no power to declare substantive rules of common law applicable
in a State whether they be local in their nature or ‘general,’ be they commercial law or a part of the law of
torts.” This sentence can only be understood as referring to a power that could be independent of the
legislative powers conferred on Congress by Article I, Section 8 of the Constitution. Congress had
unhesitatingly declared such rules in contexts within reach of its power over interstate commerce, as in
Section 8 of the federal Railway Safety Appliances Act of 189348 – a provision subsequently expanded
upon to similar effect by the Federal Employees Liability Act:
That any employee of any such common carrier who may be injured by any locomotive, car, or
train in use contrary to the provision of this act shall not be deemed thereby to have assumed the
risk thereby occasioned, although continuing in the employment of such carrier after the unlawful
use of such locomotive, car, or train had been brought to his knowledge.
This provision is, transparently, addressed to the content of state common law as it would be applied in
state court common law actions by railroad employees against their railroad employers. In the Senate
debates over this provision, questions were raised about Congress’s constitutional authority to adopt such
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
49 Mr. Gray. I think there is a very serious objection to this amendment, and I have doubt about the right of
Congress, in regulating the instrumentalities of commerce, to stretch its powers so as to regulate the contracts in
every respect which may be made with these people. I have enough doubt about it to control my vote.
...
Mr. President, this amendment seeks to introduce to every one of our forty-four States an amendment to the
common law of that State of a character more far reaching than any which has ever been before attempted by
Congress, so far as I can now recall, by one enactment. We undertake now to prescribe to the courts in every State
in this Union a rule in regard to negligence, a rule in regard to the liability of employers, and a rule in regard to the
ordinary risk assumed by all persons who engage with their eyes open in certain employment, to be administered not
only by the courts of the United States, but by the courts of every State in this country, whether that contravenes
the policy of a State or not, whether, in the opinion of its Courts or in the policy adopted by its Legislature, such a
rule be wise or not. I believe that this exercise of power by Congress in this respect is unnecessary, and that there is
no exigency demanding so far reaching and radical an exercise of power as would be made by this amendment if
adopted. ...
Senator, later Chief Justice, Edward White responded: I wish to make a very brief statement, if it be in order.
I entirely agree with the constitutional view expressed by the Senator from Delaware [Mr. Gray], but I do not
think that constitutional view will operate to prevent me from voting for the amendment, because if there be a class
of contracts which, under the Constitution is not brought within the purview of this section by the operation of this
proposed law and the Constitution upon which it rests, then this proposed law will not affect that class of contracts;
but if there be a class of contracts which it is within our constitutional power to legislate in reference to, then I think
the provision will be a wise one, and the legislation will be valid to the extent of its constitutionality, and necessarily
invalid wherever it extends beyond the limits of the Constitution.
[Congressional Record for Feb. 11, 24 Cong.Rec. Pt. 2]
50 Schlemmer v. Buffalo, Rochester & Pittsburg R. Co., 205 U.S. 1 (1906).
-20-
legislation, and answered in interstate commerce terms.49
Congress’s constitutional authority for this measure is beyond question. In an obscure but remarkable
decision,50 Justice Holmes – Swift’s most vociferous critic – built on that authority to discover a federal
question authorizing Supreme Court review of a state court decision ostensibly applying state common law.
Although the decision was closely divided on strongly held federalism grounds, with Justice Brewer in
dissent, no Justice questioned the constitutionality of the statute, as none would today. A brakeman had
been called upon to couple two railroad cars not equipped as the federal act required, under highly
dangerous circumstances, and died in the effort when he lifted his head a bit too high between the cars as
they came together. To his widow’s suit in state court for wrongful death damages, the railroad counter-
posed a claim that he had been twice warned to keep his head down and had been contributorily negligent.
The state courts, seeming to acknowledge the federal denial of “assumption of the risk” as a defense, found
contributory negligence in this behavior. For the four Justices of the dissent, that ended the matter; the
decision was one of state law, presenting no federal question for the Court. “ If an iron is dangerously hot,
and one knows that it is hot and is warned not to touch it, and does touch it without any necessity therefor
being shown, and is thereby burned, it is trifling to say that there is no evidence of negligence.” For
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
51 E.g., Henry J. Friendly, In Praise of Erie – and of the New Federal Common Law, 39 N.Y.U.L.Rev. 383 (1964).
52 Presumably Congress might have legislated on the duty of care interstate railroads, in particular, owed to
pedestrians near their tracks; but the common-law proposition put was general, not one about special rules
applicable to interstate railroads.
-21-
Holmes, the Court was called upon to protect the policy of the federal statute.
We cannot help thinking that ... the ruling upon Schlemmer's negligence was so involved with and
dependent upon erroneous views of the statute that if the judgment stood the statute would suffer
a wound. ... We are clearly of opinion that Schlemmer's rights were in no way impaired by his
getting between the rails and attempting to couple the cars. So far he was saved by the provision
that he did not assume the risk. The negligence, if any, came later. We doubt if this was the opi-
nion of the court below. But suppose the nonsuit has been put clearly and in terms on Schlem-
mer's raising his head too high after he had been warned. Still we could not avoid dealing with the
case, because it still would be our duty to see that his privilege against being held to have assumed
the risk of the situation should not be impaired by holding the same thing under another name. If
a man not intent on suicide but desiring to live, is said to be chargeable with negligence as matter
of law when he miscalculates the height of the car behind him by an inch, while his duty requires
him, in his crouching position, to direct a heavy drawbar moving above him into a small slot in
front, and this in the dusk, at nearly nine of an August evening, it is utterly impossible for us to
interpret this ruling as not, however unconsciously, introducing the notion that to some extent the
man had taken the risk of the danger by being in the place at all.
So also, as has long been understood,51 the Erie paragraph’s dismissive reference to “federal general
common law,” (emphasis added) must be read in the context of a case involving only diversity, and a
question on which the Court assumes Congress lacks Article I authority to legislate.52 Within the area of
Congress’s legislative competence, neither the constitutional objection to federal common law making
Justice Brandeis invokes – that the Court could not act if Congress could not – nor the injustices involved
in having competing systems of law potentially applicable to the same dispute would present themselves.
As in Schlemmer what was “assumption of the risk” had become a federal question from which
Pennsylvania courts were not free to depart even by misnaming the basis for their action, federal common
law within the area of Congress’s legislative competence would be exclusive. Prudential questions might
arise – suggestions that it would be preferable to await the judgment of Congress – but these are quite
distinct from any claim that federal courts lack common-law authority; rather, they are reasons not to use
it.
Such reasons are hard to find in Geier. Consider either of two possible statements of a local common
law rule that might have been applied to decide whether marketing a car without air bags or the like
amounted to marketing car with a design defect. In the 1930's, in a much admired and influential
formulation, Learned Hand had written that
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
53 The T.J. Hooper, 60 F.2d 737 (2d Cir. 1932).
54 Restatement Third of Torts
-22-
Indeed in most cases reasonable prudence [in equipping a boat] is in fact common prudence; but
strictly it is never its measure; a whole calling may have unduly lagged in the adoption of new and
available devices. It may never set its own tests, however persuasive be its usages. Courts must
in the end say what is required; there are precautions so imperative that even their universal
disregard will not excuse their omission.53
Much more recently, the American Law Institute proposed as its definition of “design defect” the following:
A product ... is defective in design when the foreseeable risks of harm posed by the product could
have been reduced or avoided by the adoption of a reasonable alternative design by the seller or
other distributor, or a predecessor in the commercial chain of distribution, and the omission of the
alternative design renders the product not reasonably safe.54
Both formulations constitute general common law tests, and one readily imagines a court undertaking to
apply them, in the particular context of automotive air bags as that technology was known at the time
Honda designed its 1987 cars. The Schlemmer question then becomes, whether federal judgments about
the imperativeness of air bags (Hand) or the reasonable safety of cars without them (Restatement) are
entitled to control. For the majority, preserving the integrity of the federal regulatory judgments in the
particular instance overcomes the general saving of state common law judgments; permitting a state court
to find the airbags “imperative” or their omission “not reasonably safe” in the face of the Secretary’s
contrary judgment and her stated reasons for that would impermissibly wound the strong federal policy for
uniformity reflected in the clear denials to state legislatures and executives of any possibility of taking action
inconsistent with the federal standards.
At one point in his opinion for the dissent, Justice Stevens remarks
Before discussing the preemption issue, it is appropriate to note that there is a vast difference
between a rejection of Honda’s threshold arguments in favor of federal preemption and a
conclusion that petitioners ultimately would prevail on their common-law tort claims. I express no
opinion on the possible merit, or lack of merit, of those claims. I do observe, however, that even
though good-faith compliance with the minimum requirements of Standard 208 would not provide
Honda with a complete defense on the merits, I assume that such compliance would be admissible
evidence tending to negate charges of negligent and defective design. In addition, if Honda were
ultimately found liable, such compliance would presumably weigh against an award of punitive
damages. ...
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
55 §4(b) provides,
(b) a product’s compliance with an applicable product safety statute or administrative regulation is properly
considered in determining whether the product is defective with respect to the risks sought to be reduced
by the statute or regulation, but such compliance does not preclude as a matter of law a finding of product
defect.
56 Comment (e) to §4(b), a kind of legislative history even the recent doubters of legislative history on the
Court have been willing to consult, Salinas v. United States, 522 U.S. 52, 64 (1997), expressly disclaims as “beyond
the scope of this Restatement” “[t]he complex set of rules and standards for resolving questions of federal
preemption.” It would be particularly hard to find in the section a judgment that state common law judges should
have a general power of reaching common law results disruptive to a federal legislative scheme, in circumstances in
which that power had been explicitly denied state legislatures and executive bodies.
57 Merrrell Dow Pharmaceuticals v. Thompson, 478 U.S. 804, 815 (1986).
58 Suppose, my colleague Michael Dorf asks, a state legislature had adopted the Third Restatement formulation
of “design defect” as statutory standard to govern civil liability, and the same question arose in that context. Now it
appears that §1397 would not in terms apply (no “common law”) – nor might §1392 (no “safety standard,” in the
probable intendment of those words). Nonetheless the preemption question framed by the majority would again be
present.
-23-
In so writing, he apparently relies on Section 4 of the Third Restatement55 – itself (for these purposes) a
proposition about state common law embodying no particular theory of federal-state relations.56 Suppose
that Ms. Geier’s case were permitted to go forward, and Honda sought a judicial ruling that, in the
particular circumstances of Standard 208, the federal determination regarding “reasonableness” must be
respected. To judge by earlier opinions, at that point Justice Stevens might agree that a federal question
had been presented respecting the “merit, or lack of merit, of those claims.”57 To give that question up,
in the presence of undoubted federal legislative authority and weakened claims for state law (state
legislative and executive action creating standards58 clearly having been precluded) would be to dismember
what the redoubtable Holmes characterized as the central pillar of the federal system.
Must the savings clause be understood, as the minority assumes, as a strong recognition of the
continuing law-making authority of state courts, a blank check given them for whatever future
developments they might choose in the particular context of auto safety? One could suggest alternative
constructions that would not have raised the issues so troubling Justice Stevens.
First, it might have been read quite weakly: as a declaration by Congress that no rights existing when
it acted (that is, under the common law as it then was) should be found prejudiced by its action. This
is a rather common precaution against seeming to interfere with “vested rights,” and implies nothing about
state courts’ law-making authority; it simply denies a purpose to interfere with such claims as may already
exist under present state law. Many law suits would be preserved by even the weakest of these readings.
Liability for “design defects” was not very well developed when the savings clause was enacted, but
liability for manufacturing defects was. Section 1397 would defeat any argument that, for example, a
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
59 George L. Priest, Strict Products Liability, The Original Intent, 10 Cardozo L.Rev. 2301 (1989).
60 Sen.Rep. No. 1301, at 12 (1966).
-24-
manufacturer could successfully defend against liability for an accident that occurred when a particular turn
signal it had manufactured proved defective, by showing that the manufacturing run of its turn signals met
the federal standards created for its reliability. The latter showing would be sufficient to establish its
“[c]ompliance with any Federal motor vehicle safety standard” from the federal regulatory perspective.
One easily understands the judgment that that showing should not defeat liability for a manufacturing defect
in a particular instance.
Preserving exactly such actions is most likely what any member of Congress who thought about the
matter imagined the savings clause would accomplish. It was enacted in 1966, the very same year as
Section 1397. As George Priest has interestingly shown,59 the previous generation’s development of strict
liability principles, culminating in the ALI’s adoption of Section 402A of the Second Restatement of Torts
in 1966, was driven by concern with manufacturing defects, not design defects. A member of Congress
thinking about the common law liability problem through that lens would not see frequent occasions for
actual disabling conflict between common law principles of liability and the federal standards to be
developed. She would not see a conflict between Section 1397 and her strong purpose to see that “motor
vehicle safety standards be not only strong and adequately enforced, but that they be uniform throughout
the country.”60 She would simply wish to be sure that in authorizing the creation of standards, Congress
did not interfere with the established remedies for manufacturing defects.
If one thinks, alternatively, that the savings clause should be read to leave some room for the
development of state common law principles, there would remain the issue whether it was intended to
pretermit questions of consistency with particular federal standards. The “design defect” issue raises these
questions rather dramatically. Section 402A came to be seen as having spoken to such defects; permitting
them to be found evidently can lead to judgments in conflict with safety standards generated by federal
regulation. It is hard to imagine, however, that a Congress that explicitly denied to state legislatures and
executives any right to create policy in conflict with federal standards believed that it was important that
state common law judges be able to do so, unsupervised.
Thus, the minority’s reading of the savings clause seems the least probable, as well as the most
problematic. If we are to imagine Section 1397 as extending to new developments in common law, not
just those existing when Congress acted, some possibility for judgment about the consistency of those state
common law developments with federal policy, as applied in particular circumstances, seems essential.
Inevitably, this would entail judgments of federal law and – just as inevitably – judgments that would often
have to be reached in particular cases by federal courts. In its strong preference for federal executive or
legislative action over federal judges running amok; but for unsupervised state court judges making law in
matters denied to their corresponding legislatures and executives because it might disturb important
elements of the federal program, the minority threatens to discard a central element of federal court
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
61 O.W. Holmes, Collected Legal Papers 295-96 (1920).
62 See, e.g., Harry Jones, Some Causes of Uncertainty in Statutes, 36 A.B.A.J. 321 (1950).
63 Op. cit n. 40 above
64 E.g., the oft-cited dicta in Texas Industries v. Radcliffe Materials, 451 U.S. 630, 640 (1981).
65 See, for example, Frank Easterbrook, Statutes’ Domains, 50 U.Chi.L.Rev. 533, 544 ff.(1983), invoking the
example of the Sherman Act.
-25-
authority and presents us with a disturbingly bifurcated view of the judicial role.
The importance of this issue is suggested by a datum marking the majority opinion’s initial paragraphs.
A number of courts, state and federal, had previously considered the relationship between sections
1392(d) and 1397(k). All the state courts had found against preemption in those cases; all the federal
courts had found that state law had been preempted. Justice Holmes once remarked in relation to the
Court’s policing of interstate commerce issues that “I do not think the United States would come to an end
if we lost our power to declare an Act of Congress void. I do think the Union would be imperiled if we
could not make that declaration as to the laws of the several States.”61 The point is no less apt for
preemption issues. As in Schlemmer, the importance of the Court’s policing state common law for
potential interference with federal programs, within the area of federal legislative competence, carries equal
importance for the success of national government.
Federal questions are likely to involve statutes or regulations simply because today we live in an age
of statutes and regulations. Yet inevitably those statues and regulations will leave matters undecided,62 and
in this respect analyses that look only at the statutory function, are misleading. Putting the issue in these
terms brings the particular issues in Geier comfortably within the special case for “preemptive lawmaking”
that Thomas Merrill has persuasively identified.63 It is a case about federalism, but one in which successful
federalism requires a national common law court to assert its control over state common law tribunals that
may prove insufficiently attentive to national policy. A broader case for federal common law in the strong
sense, in the interstices of Congress’s action, would require an effort considerably more elaborate than the
preceding paragraphs, and it is clear enough that the dominant judicial sentiment is unreceptive.64 Yet even
as to the exercise of its legislative power, we acknowledge Congress’s authority to create subsidiary
lawmaking functions in others, including the courts.65 Granted that, in the 21st Century, the Court should
focus its energies on the statutes that now dominate the legal landscape (as they assuredly did not in 1789),
and conceding as well that legislative processes are often superior to judicial ones in acquiring the
information on which sound policy can be made, we cannot blink the inevitable lawmaking implicit in
judicial decision of unanticipated matters. To do so is either to put intolerable strain on what is
denominated statutory construction or, as Justice Jackson argued, to render the federal system “impotent.”
Toward the beginning of the last century, progressive commentators urged the use of statutes as
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
66 Roscoe Pound, Common Law and Legislation, 21 Harv.L.Rev. 383 (1908); Harlan F. Stone, The Common Law
in the United States, 50 Harv.L.Rev. 4 (1936).
67 See, e.g., Neal v. United States, 516 U.S. 284 (1996), in which the Court invokes stare decisis to require rigid
adherence to its reading of a statute, once given, that could readily have been read in another way. In civilian
jurisdictions, the text with all of its possibilities– not the Court’s limiting judgment about its meaning – would
continue as the controlling element.
68 Compare Egelhoff v. Egelhoff, decided March 21, 2001, in which the two authors in Geier, Justices Breyer
and Stevens, joint in a dissent criticizing their colleagues for just such a failure of sensitivity.
69 120 S.Ct. 2143 (2000)
-26-
preferable sources of instruction for the courts in building towards coherent and just law, a process they
identified with the common law.66 Such uses are not interpretation as such – yet they are no more law-
making, in the precedential sense or in their operation on individuals, than interpretation. So long as one
maintains the common law habits of stare decisis, taking the view that “federal tribunals” are limited to
statutes and to what they say hardly abandons the practice, nonetheless, of making law.67 To turn simply
to statutes one by one, without a sense of responsibility for constructing (as best may be) a unified whole,
is nonetheless to give up the quest for coherence;68 this molecular capacity to legislate, that has been so
important to the appropriate functioning of the law, is simply wiped away. It abandons is the sense of
partnership, of supportive collaboration in a mutual enterprise, for a stance that, at heart, subordinates
Congress and insists on ultimate judicial authority as strongly as did Justice Brewer.
One can, indeed, often find in the interstices of the Court’s opinions continuing recognition of their
necessary common law role even as it sensibly also characterizes that role as subordinate to the Congress.
When operating in the shadows of federal statutes the Court unselfconsciously often writes simply as a
common-law court. A unanimous opinion decided in the same Term as Geier implicitly affirms the
point, while also suggesting a principled basis for prudential caution. Pergram v. Herdrich,69 concerning
a health management organization’s possible liability for the harm a patient suffered as the result of a
medical judgment its policies were alleged to have induced, led the Court into an extended discussion of
fiduciary responsibilities under common law trust principles. With ERISA lurking in the background, this
would plainly have been a federal question, and the discussion proceeds unselfconsciously in just the
manner of late nineteenth century Supreme Court discussions of issues of general commercial law. At an
early point in the argument, the Court considered whether to adopt a distinction proposed by the plaintiff-
respondent that, if successful, would considerably have narrowed the sweep of a decision in her favor (and
thus, arguably, made it more palatable for judicial adoption). Said the Court:
any legal principle purporting to draw a line between good and bad HMOs would embody, in
effect, a judgment about socially acceptable medical risk. A valid conclusion of this sort would,
however, necessarily turn on facts to which courts would probably not have ready access:
correlations between malpractice rates and various HMO models, similar correlations involving
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
70 Patterson v. McLean Credit Union, 491 U.S. 164, 222 (1989); Central Bank of Denver v. First Interstate bank of
Denver, 511 U.S. 164, (1994).
-27-
fee-for-service models, and so on. And, of course, assuming such material could be obtained by
courts in litigation like this, any standard defining the unacceptably risky HMO structure (and
consequent vulnerability to claims like Herdrich’s) would depend on a judgment about the
appropriate level of expenditure for health care in light of the associated malpractice risk. But such
complicated fact-finding and such a debatable social judgment are not wisely required of courts
unless for some reason resort cannot be had to the legislative process, with its preferable forum for
comprehensive investigations and judgments of social value, such as optimum treatment levels and
health care expenditure. Cf. Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U.S. 622, 665—666
(1994) (opinion of Kennedy, J.) (“Congress is far better equipped than the judiciary to ‘amass and
evaluate the vast amounts of data’ bearing upon an issue as complex and dynamic as that
presented here” (quoting Walters v. National Assn. of Radiation Survivors, 473 U.S. 305, 331,
n. 12 (1985))); Patsy v. Board of Regents of Fla., 457 U.S. 496, 513 (1982) (“[T]he relevant
policy considerations do not invariably point in one direction, and there is vehement disagreement
over the validity of the assumptions underlying many of them. The very difficulty of these policy
considerations, and Congress’ superior institutional competence to pursue this debate, suggest that
legislative not judicial solutions are preferable” (footnote omitted)).
The reasoning here is not that federal courts cannot adopt suggested legal principles in common-law
fashion, but that it may be unwise for them to do so when those principles turn on assessments better suited
for legislative than adjudicative fact-finding. The parallel to the conventional arguments for preferring
rulemaking to adjudication in administrative policymaking – while not excluding the latter as an available
option to be used by the adjudicator as it finds it required – are evident.
The author of the Geier dissent, Justice Stevens, has in other contexts upbraided his colleagues for
their failures to respect the incremental and reasoned processes of the common law.70 As judges are
lawmakers, the habits of the common law are what restrain them from running amok. That risk is equally
present among state judges as federal, particularly as regards federal matters; and federal judicial control
seems important to guard against its fruition.
Where all this is going, I would not venture to predict. Discussions of federalism, statutory
interpretation, or one’s attitude toward congressional fact-finding generally find the Court split along
predictable lines. But not these issues. Every Justice save perhaps Justice Breyer has subscribed to an
opinion raising questions in one or another context about the common law functions of federal courts. The
discomfort is widespread, and it is perhaps more instinctual than intellectual, a realization that the ground
has shifted without yet quite knowing what to do about it. In the repeated arguments about precedent, the
perhaps unexpected adherence to precedent in cases like Dickerson, one can find expression of the
tensions between the prior model of judging, and the new powers of policy-directed choice. We cannot
deny that what it means to be a court has changed, although the change has nothing to do with original
DRAFT Please do not quote or cite without written permission
-28-
understandings; it is the product of the last century’s changes in how law is made and, in particular, in the
nature of judicial review. The certiorari function brings forward the law-making side of judging, and at the
same time reflects a weakening of the possibilities for hierarchical control within the judiciary. Our
common-law premises cannot explain either development. In groping for an understanding and
accommodation, the Justices appear often enough to be behaving in the familiar, unconscious mode. In the
unspoken battle between agenda-setting and judging, we should all hope judging wins.