International Human Rights, International
Humanitarian Law, and Environmental Security:
Can the International Criminal Court Bridge the
Gaps?
Mark A. Drumbl*
I. INTRODUCTION 2
II. OVERVIEW OF THE ENVIRONMENTAL CONSEQUENCES OF ARMED CONFLICT 4
III. THE ICC AND ENVIRONMENTAL PROTECTION: THE LANGUAGE OF THE ROME STATUTE 7
A. The Physical Act: Widespread, Long-term and Severe Damage 12
B. Exculpatory Effects of Military Advantage 16
C. The Mental Element: Strict Intentionality 19
IV. IS IT WORTH GREENING THE ICC? 21
A. Environmental Concerns Lost in the Shuffle 24
B. Low Environmental Expertise of the Judges and Prosecutors 25
C. Inappropriate Sanctions 25
D. Limited Scope of Judicial Interpretation 27
E. No Room for Negligence or Recklessness 28
V. PUNITIVE SANCTION, PROACTIVE PROTECTION, OR ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE? 30
VI. CONCLUSION 40
I. Introduction
Human rights law has evolved considerably over the past half-century. Much of this evolution has occurred at the
international level. Evolution can, of course, consist of growth and expansion, or decline and regression. For the most
part, the recent international evolution of human rights law has tended towards growth and expansion.
Growth can involve the creation of new mechanisms to enforce basic civil rights by holding accountable those who violate
these rights. In recent years, the creation of mechanisms to promote accountability has become a focal point of activity for
international lawyers. This activity has most immediately culminated in the adoption of the Rome Statute of the
International Criminal Court (hereinafter “Rome Statute”)1 in July, 1998. The Rome Statute innovates on both the
procedural and substantive fronts. Along with creating an enforcement mechanism in the form of the International
Criminal Court (hereinafter “ICC”), the Rome Statute also refines prior customary and conventional rules by providing a
detailed list of what can prospectively be sanctioned as the “most serious crimes of concern to the international
community as a whole.”2 In this regard, the Rome Statute creates important linkages between human rights, international
humanitarian law, and international criminal law. This gives rise to what one scholar has labeled the “humanization” of
international humanitarian law.3
Although there has been considerable parallelism between international human rights and international humanitarian law,
this has, for the most part, occurred within the nexus of classic human rights such as the right to life, the right to freedom
from persecution, and the right to bodily integrity. The evolution and growth of social and political rights, and their
penetration into the world of international humanitarian law, has been much slower. A traditionally socio-political right
whose exploration shall constitute the focus of this Article is the right to live in a healthy and productive environment,
which some have called “environmental security.”4 For the most part, the linkage between international humanitarian law
and environmental security is weak and may in fact reflect a somewhat troubling disjunction between international
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (1 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:21 PM]
environmental law and humanitarian concerns. Although international humanitarian law may well be “humanized,” it is
not showing signs of being “environmentalized.”
The gap between international humanitarian law and environmental security should trouble international lawyers. Just as
armed conflict often creates a context in which the most serious human rights abuses occur, so too, does it create a similar
context for the infliction of wanton and extensive destruction to the environment. This destruction creates profound
environmental insecurity. Part II of this Article explores the insecurities caused by the environmental consequences of
armed conflict. Although the international community has shown considerable concern for the humanitarian
consequences of war,5 it has been significantly more hesitant in accounting for war’s environmental consequences. It is
for this reason that a very fruitful exploration of the progress that has been made and that still needs to be made in terms of
harmonizing international humanitarian law with environmental protection can emerge from a study of how the
international community monitors the environmental consequences of war. Part III examines the successes and failures of
the international legal order in controlling these consequences and directs its focus on the ICC’s jurisdiction to prosecute
environmental war crimes. Part IV argues that the ICC may not be particularly well-suited to sanction environmentally
destructive behavior. This raises the more penetrating question whether punitive criminal approaches pursued in isolation
of other policy devices can ever promote environmental security. Part V is proscriptive, sketching ways in which the
promotion of environmental security can be made more effective. Part V posits that the effective promotion of
environmental security requires a multifaceted approach, which combines criminal prosecution, preventative measures,
and specially tailored remedies. An additional element of this multifaceted approach, inspired by environmental justice
litigation in the United States, involves more proactive use of international anti-discrimination conventions to guard
against the infliction of environmental insecurity on already disempowered groups. In the end, this encourages
environmental security to become more closely integrated with both the protection of human rights and international
humanitarian law.
II. Overview of the Environmental Consequences of Armed Conflict
Modification or desecration of the natural environment has often been used as a strategic mechanism to safeguard state
sovereignty. Over two millennia ago, Roman soldiers salted the soil of Carthage. Much more recently, Agent Orange was
used to defoliate the Vietnamese jungle. In fact, it is estimated that, from 1962 to 1971, the United States sprayed twelve
million gallons of defoliant over more than ten percent of what was then South Vietnam.7 United States estimates reveal
that fourteen of the area’s forests were destroyed.8 Other estimates place the figure at nearly one-third.9 Regardless of
the exact numbers, Abroad stretches of the landscape are still bare of trees.@10 Civilians and soldiers who had been
exposed to defoliants claim to have passed the ill-effects through their family lines. In fact, there are tens of thousands of
physically or mentally disabled children in Vietnam whose disabilities can be linked to the spraying of Agent Orange
which occurred before they were born or even conceived.11
During the 1990-1991 Gulf War, vast quantities of oil were dumped into the Persian Gulf to contaminate Kuwait’s water
supply.12 Kuwaiti oil wells were also deliberately ignited by Iraqi troops.13 Remedying the losses and damages suffered
as a direct result of Iraq’s unlawful invasion and occupation of Kuwait has prompted the creation of the United Nations
Compensation Commission (hereinafter “UNCC”) as a subsidiary organ of the United Nations.14 The UNCC is a unique
initiative (part court of law, part arbitral tribunal) which adopts mass tort litigation approaches to settle claims and pay
compensation, including for damage to the Kuwaiti environment and public health. Iraq, whose liability is presumed, is to
pay reparations out of its frozen international assets as well as from a portion of its future oil export earnings. Thus far,
2.6 million claims have been filed.15 The asserted value of these claims is $250 billion.16
Reports of significant ecological destruction are also emerging from the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia (hereinafter
“FRY”). NATO aerial bombardment of the FRY under Operation Allied Force has resulted in the destruction of oil
refining installations as well as storage facilities for other industrial products. Much of this destruction arose from the
indiscriminate effects of bombing from very high altitude levels.17 In particular, the destruction of a petrochemical,
fertilizer and refinery complex in Pancevo resulted in the discharge of oil, gasoline, and dichloride (a powerful
carcinogen) into the Danube river.18 The bombardment of the Pancevo facility also caused the emission of toxic
gases.19 The result, according to one Western observer, is an “ecological disaster”, with the pollution “spread[ing]
downstream to Romania and Bulgaria and then into the Black Sea.”20 Scientists are also very concerned that extensive
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (2 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
flooding may result from ice which may form on the Danube and then become lodged behind three bridges in Novi Sad
which were bombed during Operation Allied Force.21 The areas most at risk include low-lying portions of Serbia, as well
as Croatia and parts of Hungary.22
In short, “[f]rom antiquity to the present, examples of environmental destruction in war abound.”23 But it is not only
actual war which creates environmental insecurity. The environment also faces severe threats as nations prepare to go to
war (mobilization) and as nations turn back from the threat of war (decommissioning and disarmament).24 On this latter
point, Russian attempts to decommission its nuclear submarines in the Arctic Ocean are being carried out with insufficient
financial and human resources and seriously threaten that particularly fragile marine environment.25 Testing of weapons -
specifically nuclear and chemical weapons - also has particularly noxious effects on the environment. These activities
collateral to actual armed conflict therefore require regulation. Nonetheless, for the most part, the environmental
consequences of such activities remain unsupervised and unmonitored.
III. The ICC and Environmental Protection: The Language of the Rome Statute
It is only very recently that the international community has made inroads into contemplating the prosecution of those who
engage in unacceptable use of the environment during wartime. In this regard, the language of the Rome Statute is
important. For the first time, environmental war crimes are independently sanctioned and an apparatus is provided for the
punishment of those who commit such crimes. Although there was some scattered mention of environmental war crimes
at the Nuremberg Trials,26 over the past five decades humanitarian abuses have been treated separately from
environmental desecration. This disconnect is revealed in the Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for the
Former Yugoslavia27 and the Statute of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda.28 Neither Tribunal is directly
empowered to prosecute those who propagate environmental insecurity through the commission of environmental war
crimes. The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia has some jurisdiction over war crimes which bear
an incidental relationship to the security of the natural environment.29 The International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda
essentially lacks jurisdiction over even incidental violations of environmental security.30
Under the language of the Rome Statute, however, intentional infliction of harm to the environment may constitute a war
crime.31 More specifically, Article 8(2)(b)(iv) prohibits [emphasis added]:
Intentionally launching an attack in the knowledge that such attack will cause incidental loss of life or injury to civilians or
damage to civilian objects or widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment which would be clearly
excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated.32
The negotiation history of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) merits a brief review. The draft of the Rome Statute which served as
the basis for the final negotiations listed three other options along with the language which was eventually adopted in
Article 8(2)(b)(iv).33 The three rejected options are:
1. Intentionally launching an attack in the knowledge that such attack will cause incidental loss of life or injury to
civilians or damage to civilian objects or widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment which is
not justified by military necessity.
(Or)
2. Intentionally launching an attack in the knowledge that such attack will cause incidental loss of life or injury to
civilians or damage to civilian objects or widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the natural environment.
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (3 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
(Or)
3. No paragraph [in other words, no prohibition on intentionally inflicting widespread, long-term and severe damage
to the natural environment].
In the end, the provision which was adopted was a compromise and, from an environmental perspective, occupies a
middle ground. However, it shares with the first option the important limitation that environmental integrity is secondary
to the military advancement of national security interests. There are other important limitations. The jurisdiction of the
ICC is restricted to “war crimes in particular when committed as a part of a plan or policy or as part of a large-scale
commission of such crimes.”34 The question consequently arises whether the “in particular” language will allow isolated
incidents to fall within the purview of the Rome Statute. A more important limitation, however, is the fact that prohibiting
harm to the natural environment is explicitly mentioned only once in the entire Rome Statute.35 This provision may
therefore become peripheral given the broad array of other crimes to which the ICC’s energies will be directed. As a
result, the effect of this provision may well be more apparent than real. Also, the environmental war crimes provision of
the Rome Statute only applies to inter-state armed conflicts. Environmental desecration during internecine conflicts is
consequently left unaddressed.36 This is a troubling gap.37 Also troubling is the fact that the ICC can only capture
environmental crimes committed by military forces actively engaged in hostilities. There is therefore no jurisdiction to
sanction the environmental insecurity created by armed forces in the testing of weapons or in the mobilization of forces.
Nor is there jurisdiction to supervise any disarmament process.38
Article 8(2)(b)(iv) also triggers more specific interpretive concerns. By way of overview, there are three principal
components to the language of Article 8(2)(b)(iv): (1) the actual physical act - or actus reus - which consists of launching
an attack which causes “widespread, long-term and severe damage” to the natural environment; (2) a second material
element, namely that the damage must be “clearly excessive” in relation to the “concrete and direct overall military
advantage anticipated”; and (3) even if both material elements are found, the mental element - or mens rea - must be
demonstrated, thereby entailing proof that the attack was launched intentionally and in the knowledge it will cause
“widespread, long-term, and severe damage” to the natural environment.
A. The Physical Act: Widespread, Long-term and Severe Damage
A successful prosecution under the Rome Statute will, first and foremost, have to show that the accused launched an
attack39 which caused “widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the natural environment.” Of great importance is
that all three elements must conjunctively be proven. The language of “widespread, long-term and severe” has woven its
way into the handful of other international humanitarian conventions which address the use of the environment in times of
war, for example the 1977 United Nations Convention on the Prohibition of Military or Any Other Hostile Use of
Environmental Modification Techniques (hereinafter “ENMOD Convention”),40 and the 1977 Additional Protocol I to the
1949 Geneva Convention (Protocol I).41 However, by providing that all three elements must be conjunctively shown to
exist, the language of the Rome Statute regresses from the wording of the ENMOD Convention which bases fault
disjunctively on proof of only one of these three characteristics.
What exactly do “widespread,” “long-term,” and “severe” mean? The Rome Statute is silent on this point. The
International Law Commission (hereinafter “ILC”) has concluded that “widespread, long-term and severe” describes the
“extent or intensity of the damage, its persistence in time, and the size of the geographical area affected by the
damage.”42 However, the International Committee of the Red Cross (hereinafter “ICRC”) recognizes that the more
specific question “as to what constitutes ‘widespread, long-term, and severe’ damage ... to the environment is open to
interpretation.@43 In this regard, some interpretive guidance can be provided by the work of the Geneva Conference of
the Committee on Disarmament Understanding (hereinafter “CCD Understanding”) regarding the application of these
terms under the ENMOD Convention.44 This additional work was necessary since the ENMOD Convention does not
itself define these terms. The CCD Understanding provides as follows:
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (4 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
1. “Widespread” encompassing an area on the scale of several hundred square kilometers;
2. “Long-term” lasting for a period of months, or approximately a season;
3. “Severe” involving serious or significant disruption or harm to human life, natural and economic resources
or other assets.
Regrettably, the interpretive value of the CCD Understanding is curtailed by the fact that it stipulates that its use is limited
to the ENMOD Convention and is not intended to prejudice the interpretation of similar terms if used in another
international agreement.45 As the ENMOD Convention deals with “extraordinary manipulations of the natural
environment for military purposes, such as creating floods, it is unclear what weight, if any, it would be given by the
[ICC].”46 As it turns out, greater interpretive guidance may be obtained from commentaries on Protocol I, especially
since its language is, like the Rome Statute’s, conjunctive in nature. From an environmental perspective, the prohibitions
in Protocol I are more circumscribed than those of ENMOD. For example, “long-term” has been interpreted by the ICRC
as meaning lasting for “decades rather than months.”47
The “widespread” and “long-term” principles attempt to ascribe temporal and geographic limitations to environmental
harm which, for the most part, does not know such boundaries. As the planet constitutes one single ecosystem,
environmental degradation of one part of the earth ultimately affects the entire planet.48 The “severe” requirement could
mean that damage to an isolated section of the global commons whose natural resources have not yet been valued by
global financial markets could escape punishment; and this notwithstanding its biodiversity or species-importance. The
anthropocentric limitation of “severe” damage to that which affects human life and human consumption of natural
resources underscores a more general shortcoming with much of the existing framework of environmental protection
during wartime - namely that this protection is not geared to protecting the environment per se, but, rather, humanity’s
need to make use of it. More troubling is that state practice in some of the signatories to the Rome Statute ascribes the
anthropocentric limitation to the totality of the material element of Article 8(2)(b)(iv). For example, the German Military
Manual states that: “’Widespread’, ‘long-term’, and ‘severe’ damage to the natural environment is a major interference
with human life or natural resources.”49
An additional phrase that requires definition is “natural environment.” In its report detailing the work of its 43
rd
Session,
the ILC offered a broad definition of “natural environment.”50 This definition focused both on the human environment as
well as on the natural environment per se.51 Having such a broad definition is necessary for Article 8(2)(b)(iv) to fully
encompass environmental security as opposed to only covering the protection of human environments (e.g. cities,
dwellings, private property) from destruction. The ILC definition of the “natural environment” is as follows:
The words “natural environment” should be taken broadly to cover the environment of the human race and where the human race develops, as well as areas the
preservation of which is of fundamental importance in protecting the environment. These words therefore cover the seas, the atmosphere, climate, forests and
other plant cover, fauna, flora and other biological elements.52
It will be important to develop a memorandum of understanding under the Rome Statute in which the scope of “natural
environment,” “widespread,” “long-term,” and “severe” is spelled out. The ongoing Preparatory Commission sessions
provide an appropriate forum for such discussions. In fact, the Preparatory Commission intends to “ensure the
formulation of generally acceptable elements of crimes on Article 8, as part of a complete set of elements of crimes for all
crimes, laid down in the [Rome] Statute.”53 Unfortunately, thus far specific discussion of the environmental war crime
provision has been very limited.54 Nonetheless, it is essential to the viability of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) that the definition of
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (5 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
the elements it contains is not pitched at such a high level so as to strip the provision of any practical effect. This may
well require the threshold of responsibility to be relaxed from the international community’s current understanding of the
meaning of “widespread,” “long-term,” and “severe” harm.
B. Exculpatory Effects of Military Advantage
Even if there is proof of widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment, liability is only found if
this damage is “clearly excessive” in relation to the “concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated.”
This second material element permits “military objectives [to be] offered as a defense against charges of environmental
damage, even intentional damage, as long as that damage is outweighed by the expected military gain.”55 The
exculpating force of “proof of military advantage” traces its roots to the doctrine of “military necessity.” This doctrine has
historically been used to mitigate or eliminate responsibility often for grievous breaches of humanitarian standards. In
short, “military necessity” is a principle of customary international law56 “which ‘authorizes’ military action when such
action is necessary for the overall resolution of a conflict, particularly when the continued existence of the acting state
would otherwise be in jeopardy.”57 At the Nuremberg trials, the doctrine of military necessity was applied to the
destruction of property (the closest the international community has yet come to an environmental war crimes proceeding)
in the following manner:
The destruction of property to be lawful must be imperatively demanded by the necessities of war. Destruction as an end in itself is a violation of international
law. There must be some reasonable connection between the destruction of property and the overcoming of the enemy forces.58
“Military advantage” may bear an even lower threshold of proof than “military necessity.” As a result, the prohibition in
Article 8(2)(b)(iv) may be narrower than its antecedents at customary international law. In the case of Article 8(2)(b)(iv),
the ambit of “military advantage” is limited by the fact that only “concrete and direct overall military advantage
anticipated” can justify the environmental damage. Nonetheless, “concrete and direct overall military advantage
anticipated” still seems easier to prove than “military necessity.” In addition, although the “military necessity” defense
may in fact form part of customary international law, it is noteworthy that Protocol I, in its prohibition of “widespread,
long-term and severe” harm, did not permit proof of any military advantage or necessity to eliminate wrongdoing.59 As a
result, Article 8(2)(b)(iv)’s prohibition is but a diluted version of that in Protocol I.
There are other concerns with “military advantage” in Article 8(2)(b)(iv). First, although a “proportionality test” (i.e. the
environmental damage must be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage) is
established, no guidelines, definitions or examples of “clearly excessive” are provided. In fact, “the addition of the word[
] ‘clearly’ ... in the definition of collateral damage is not reflected in any existing legal source.”60 To this end,
memoranda of understanding of the Parties to the Rome Statute or initial decisions by the ICC will be important in setting
the scope for “clearly” excessive.
Second, the factual element of the proportionality test is also unclear: since proof of “clearly excessive” is required in
order to find someone guilty, and since the burden of proof rests with the Prosecutor, what type of research and data will
have to be marshaled? In addition, adjectival terms such as “concrete” and “direct” and “overall” military advantage are
somewhat vague and have not yet been comprehensively defined by international law. Nor does the Rome Statute provide
more particularized definitions of the meaning of these terms. As for “overall,” the ICRC has suggested that it indicates
“that a particular target can have an important military advantage that can be felt over a lengthy period of time and affect
military action in areas other than the vicinity of the target itself.”61 In the end, the extent to which these adjectives
qualify or extend the exculpating effect of military advantage will bear heavily on the ability of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) to
punish environmental crimes.
Finally, the military advantage needs simply to be “anticipated.” What does this term signify? Some clarification as to the
meaning of “anticipated” can emerge from a consideration of state declarations made to the use of “military advantage”{
in prior international conventions. It is reported that:
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (6 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
A number of [s]tates expressed their understanding that the military advantage anticipated from an attack is intended to refer to the advantage anticipated from
the attack considered as a whole and not from isolated or particular parts of the attack.62
On a related note, it is unclear by whom and according to what standards the “anticipation” is to be judged. Does there
have to be an objective element to the anticipation, or can the belief be subjectively held yet unrealistic? If the notion of
military advantage remains subjective in the mind of the military or political leader under the circumstances in which the
tactical decision was made, then the defense could be too widely available. In order to curtail misuse of the defense, it
will be important to establish some objective standards as to when the military advantage of an attack may justify
widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the environment.
The difficulties which inhere in giving appropriate meaning to the defense of military advantage raise more penetrating
questions. These questions militate in favor of reconsidering the interaction between international environmental law and
international humanitarian law. Certain practices - such as genocide and torture - have been sanctioned as illegal by the
international community to the extent that they can never be undertaken even if essential to defend national sovereignty.
Why should intentional environmental desecration not be similarly proscribed?
C. The Mental Element: Strict Intentionality
In the case of Article 8(2)(b)(iv), criminal sanction will only fall upon an individual who knows his or her behavior will
cause widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the environment which is clearly excessive in relation to the overall
military advantage anticipated and, notwithstanding proof of this knowledge, still commits the act with the full intention of
causing the environmental damage. More concisely, the perpetrator must be found to have acted wil1fully and in the
knowledge that the attack will cause the prohibited environmental damage.63 The Rome Statute therefore “presupposes
that the attack was launched in the knowledge that [the] consequences listed occur.”64 The ICRC has interpreted the
phrase “in the knowledge” as requiring “the person committing the act [to know] with certainty that the described results
would ensue, and this would not cover recklessness.”65 The fact that there is no liability for negligently or carelessly
inflicting widespread, long-term, and severe damage to the environment means that persons who are found to act
negligently will not face any sanction at all. The provision therefore covers only the most invidious offender. It goes
without saying that proving this very onerous intentionality requirement will not be easy.
As a result, a more proactive approach may be required. Military and political officials in both developing and developed
nations should be educated on the environmentally harmful effects of certain types of warfare, and be informed of the
technologies to avoid reliance on such strategies in the first place. In this regard, the work of the ICRC can play a pivotal
role. The ICRC has published a document entitled Guidelines for Military Manuals and Instructions on the Protection of
the Environment in Times of Armed Conflict (Guidelines), which are:
Intended as a tool to facilitate the instruction and training of armed forces in an often neglected area of international humanitarian law: the protection of the
natural environment. The Guidelines[‘] ... sole aim is to contribute in a practical and effective way to raising awareness ... [T]hey are an instrument for
dissemination purposes.66
The Guidelines state that they are drawn from existing international legal obligations and, as such, constitute a baseline of
jus commune among nations.67 Many detailed rules are provided in Article III(9) of the Guidelines, which cover
numerous issues ranging from barring incendiary weapons in forested regions to precluding the use of naval mines.
Ultimately, it is hoped that the Guidelines could constitute the specific level of objective knowledge imputed to all
military and civilian leaders and agents for purposes of culpability under Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Rome Statute. It is also
hoped that they will be taken into account as new weaponry is developed. In this latter regard, Article IV(18) of the
Guidelines is particularly important:
In the study, development, acquisition or adoption of a new weapon, means or method of warfare, states are under an obligation to determine whether its
employment would, in some or all circumstances, be prohibited by applicable rules of international law, including those providing protection of the environment
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (7 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
in times of armed conflict.68
In conclusion, unless some level of objective knowledge is read into the intentionality requirement, individuals who
choose not to inform themselves that what they are doing is destructive of the environment might be able to use their
ignorance as a full defense. A failure to incorporate an objective element into the Rome Statute’s environmental war
crimes also represents a step backwards insofar as Protocol I had, as early as 1977, grounded responsibility not in
intentional environmental harm, but simply when there was a reasonable expectation that environmental damage would
occur.69
IV. Is it Worth Greening the ICC?
International lawyers need to consider whether the interests of the global environment are in fact well-served by collapsing
environmental crimes within an overarching multilateral mechanism. If so, then an important subsidiary question
emerges: is the ICC the appropriate mechanism or should a new environmentally specific entity be created? The most
immediate countervailing option to proceeding multilaterally would be to address environmental crimes within the rubric
of independently negotiated regional agreements. In such cases, domestic courts, regional tribunals, or either domestic or
regional regulatory agencies could serve as enforcement mechanisms.
Efforts at the regional level may prove effective in combating environmental crimes within and outside the context of
armed conflict. By way of example, in March, 1999, six African countries established an “African Interpol” to fight
wildlife crime.70 More sweeping is the Council of Europe’s Convention on the Protection of the Environment Through
Criminal Law.71 The motivation behind the Convention is that signatories should take effective measures to ensure that
the perpetrators of environmental hazards having serious consequences escape neither prosecution nor punishment.72
This Convention obliges signatories to criminalize certain intentional or negligent forms of environmental offenses
(although the negligence may be limited by declaration to acts of gross negligence only).73 Specific examples are
provided. For instance, the intentional discharge of ionizing radiation into the air, soil, or water which causes a
“significant risk” of death or serious injury is to be prohibited.74 So, too, is the unlawful disposal or transport of
hazardous waste which causes or is likely to cause death, serious injury, or “substantial damage to the quality of air, soil,
water, animals, or plants.”75 This latter provision is important for it goes beyond the anthropocentric approach to
assessing environmental harm which often characterizes current conventions and laws.
However, these successful regional initiatives should not obscure the importance of multilateral efforts. The two levels can
in fact operate contemporaneously. As for the ICC, in order for it to capture environmental crimes outside of the context
of war, its jurisdiction would have to be broadened. In this vein, some commentators have suggested making it a crime
recklessly or intentionally to harm the environment.76 This could permit the behavior of armed forces not engaged in
hostilities to be regulated, together with corporations and governments who may implement policies which promote
insecurity through environmental modification. This crime has been named “geocide” or “ecocide.” Literally, this
constitutes the environmental counterpart of genocide - a killing of the earth. The logic of ecocide is as follows:
significantly harming the natural environment constitutes a breach of a duty of care, and this breach consists, in the least,
in tortuous or delictual conduct and, when undertaken with willfulness, recklessness or negligence, ought to constitute a
crime.77
Although some international environmental lawyers may find the criminalization of ecocide to be intellectually attractive,
it seems fair to say that its chances of being negotiated into the jurisdiction of the ICC are slim at best. And yet
environmental crimes outside armed conflict do occur and, when they do, certainly inflict “widespread, long-term, and
severe” damage to the natural environment. Examples of such crimes could include reckless misconduct at nuclear power
facilities78 or intentional dumping of oil and chemical wastes from ships (often cruise ships) at sea.79 Trade in
endangered species, hazardous wastes and ozone-depleting substances constitutes an underground market estimated at
$U.S. 20 billion annually.80 Another particularly troubling example of what is arguably an environmental crime which is
essentially unregulated at the international level notwithstanding its transnational effects is the setting of forest fires in the
Amazon basin and in Indonesia. In both cases, there is compelling evidence that these fires had been deliberately set by
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (8 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
businesses seeking to clear the forests for economic development.81
Nonetheless, even if negotiators had the willingness and succeeded in according the ICC jurisdiction over ecocide as a
“most serious crime[ ] of concern to the international community as a whole,”82 concerns would remain as to the ICC’s
effectiveness in terms of being able or suited to enforce such a prohibition. As a result, collapsing environmental crimes
within the ICC might not be the most effective way to sanction such crimes. This Article identifies five reasons why this
might be so: (1) environmental crimes may become lost amid the hurly-burly of the ICC’s activities; (2) ICC personnel
may have low environmental expertise and there may consequently be very high transaction costs involved in “getting up
to speed” on environmental issues; (3) the sanctions which the ICC can order are not appropriate to correcting
environmental desecration; (4) there is limited scope under the Rome Statute to integrate preexisting international law in
the area of environmental crimes; and (5) environmental harm may well be best deterred by a negligence standard which is
essentially incompatible with the mandate of a permanent international court designed to punish the most serious crimes of
concern to humanity. This Article will now consider each of these in turn.
A. Environmental Concerns Lost in the Shuffle
Clearly, one of the major successes of the Rome Statute is that it creates an institution to actually punish the conduct it
prohibits. Nonetheless, from the environmental point of view, the extent to which “environmental crimes” will receive the
ICC’s attention is uncertain given the broad array of other crimes to which it will have to direct its energies. The
environmental war crime constitutes only one provision out of dozens in Part 2 of the Rome Statute. And A[t]his
provision has largely escaped notice amid the larger debate about the creation of the court and the scope of its
jurisdiction.@83 Article 8(2)(b)(iv) remains peripheral to the ongoing discussions of the Working Group on the Elements
of Crimes held at the Preparatory Commission sessions.84 As a result, there is no indication that, as work on the
establishment of the ICC progresses, the environmental war crime will be able to attract the attention it requires in order to
be effectively implemented.
B. Low Environmental Expertise of the Judges and Prosecutors
Judges and prosecutors on the ICC will likely not have expertise in the area of environmental law, policy or science. This
can heighten the transaction costs of proceeding judicially,85 as well as produce ineffective jurisprudence. Were
environmental crimes to be litigated in a separate forum or before a specialized agency, there could be a greater guarantee
of some level of scientific expertise.
C. Inappropriate Sanctions
Part 7 of the Rome Statute offers the most contemporary compilation of the international community’s thinking on how
international crimes ought to be punished. The punishment provisions of the Rome Statute contain two limitations on the
effectiveness of Article 8(2)(b)(iv).
First, the jurisdiction of the ICC is limited to natural persons. This makes it impossible to find any institutional or state
liability should it be difficult to prove that the actions of one or some individuals accounted for the environmental
desecration. This is unlike the Council of Europe’s Convention on the Protection of the Environment Through Criminal
Law, Article 9 of which establishes jurisdiction over corporate offenders together with natural persons.86
Second, sentencing is limited to imprisonment, fines, and forfeiture of the proceeds of the crime.87 There does not
appear to be much room to compel restitution, remediation of blight, establish civil liability or, simply put, to clean up the
environmental harm. This is again unlike the Council of Europe’s Convention on the Protection of the Environment
Through Criminal Law, Article 6 of which provides that sanctions include imprisonment, fines, as well as reinstatement of
the environment.88 This is also unlike the UNCC’s approach to remedying environmental crimes committed during the
Gulf War.89 Nor does the ICC have injunctive powers to stop violations from occurring.
Without the ICC being able to order restorative or injunctive remedies, the curative nature of the punishment for causing
“widespread, long-term, and severe” damage to the natural environment is limited at best. It is true that the Rome Statute
permits fines and assets collected to be transferred to a Trust Fund for the benefit of victims of the crime.90 Access to this
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (9 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
Trust Fund is provided for in Article 75, which permits the ICC to make an order specifying reparations to victims for
purposes of restitution, compensation, and rehabilitation. However, the Trust Fund does not address a situation where it is
the natural environment directly, and humanity only indirectly, which bears the burden of the damage. In addition, the
magnitude of wartime environmental harm may be so vast that resources transferred from individual defendants simply
cannot go very far in terms of remedying that harm. By way of example, in the Gulf War alone Kuwait’s environmental
claims filed with the UNCC total over $15 billion.91 Another concern is that “to the extent that charges of environmental
war crimes are ancillary to other serious charges, the concern for using the trust fund to aid human victims doubtless will
take priority over addressing environmental harms.”92 This, once again, returns us to the problem of pursuing
environmental goals in a regime principally designed to address genocide, persecution, and murder.
As a result, there is cause for concern that environmental crimes will not only be poorly cognizable under the ICC, but
also that the punishment for wrongdoing will not address the unique nature of these crimes.
D. Limited Scope of Judicial Interpretation
The list of enumerated war crimes under Article 8(2)(b) appears to be exhaustive. After all, the use of the term “namely”
implies that the ICC is not to have jurisdiction over serious violations of the laws and customs of war which are not listed
in Article 8(2)(b). There is thus little opportunity for judicial interpretation to reach beyond the enumerated environmental
war crime. To this end, it might be difficult for the ICC to use Article 2193 to incorporate in its jurisdiction the very
small number of international legal materials which may provide more proactive sanction of environmental war crimes
than that found in Article 8(2)(b)(iv).94 This constitutes further evidence of the limited ability of the ICC to
accommodate environmental protection concerns. After all, without the flexibility to go beyond the words of the Rome
Statute notwithstanding developments in international environmental law, the ICC may not be able to do justice to any
such developments.
E. No Room for Negligence or Recklessness
The ICC is designed to deter criminal behavior. Unlike direct humanitarian abuses, environmental crimes during warfare
may often involve conduct which tends more to the negligent, reckless, or willfully blind than to the intentional. Intention
is always difficult to prove. So, too, is causation. Consequently, in order for the ICC to remain within its present mandate
it will have to let go all but the most flagrant incidents of deliberate environmental desecration.
As a result, some of the recommendations suggested in this Article to enhance the effectiveness of Article 8(2)(b)(iv) may
simply not be able to be accommodated by the present mandate of the ICC.95 Two commentators have offered the
following well-placed remarks regarding two of these recommendations:
[I]t is difficult to imagine how the [ICC] could relax both the threshold of damage and the intent requirement while remaining within its existing mandate. The
countries that acceded to the Rome Statute simply could not have intended to let their military officers be prosecuted for any action, committed with any state of
mind, that causes any environmental damage.96
If only the most egregious form of environmental insecurity has been caught by the ICC, does this augur well for the
future promotion of environmental security within the structures of international criminal or humanitarian law? In the end,
these structures may only be able to address environmental insecurity in a very limited fashion. The question thus arises
whether encouraging remediation as a “punishment” (instead of individual imprisonment, fines, and the resultant
stigmatization) might bring more nations on board in terms of sanctioning less egregious (yet, when aggregated, likely
more destructive) forms of environmental destruction during armed conflict. If so, then an organization supervising a
strict liability regime supplemented by a remediation fund might be a preferable institutional device. Such an organization
could be established on a regional or ad hoc basis (such as the UNCC). On the other hand, such an institution may be
capable of development as a permanent multilateral entity which could minister to the remediation of global
environmental harm. If the fund were to operate on an “at-fault” basis, then it could be financed by the international
community yet retain subrogation rights against perpetrators of environmental harm. If the remediation fund were to
operate on a “no-fault” basis, it could be capitalized by international contributions assessed by the size and nature of a
nation’s armed forces (based on the capacity of those forces to create environmental harms).97
Capitalization can also be sought from the private sector, namely manufacturers of weapons. In this latter regard, the
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (10 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
International Fund for the Compensation for Oil Pollution Damage can serve as a precedent, as it is in part capitalized by
“fees imposed on oil transported on the high seas, and supplemented by contributions from tanker owners, oil producers,
refiners, and marketers.”98 In the least, such funds can assist immediate mitigation efforts which will usually reduce the
long-term costs of remediation. In this latter regard, Austin and Bruch recommend the creation of an “emergency
response task force” which would be financed by the fund and could spearhead initial mitigation efforts.99
V. Punitive sanction, Proactive Protection, or Environmental Justice?
A more fundamental question lurks beneath any evaluation of the ICC as a mechanism to promote environmental
security. Essentially, the ICC represents a punitive, retributive justice paradigm in which certain serious crimes against
the international community are to be redressed through the prosecution and imprisonment of selected individuals. The
foundational question for international environmental lawyers is whether a punitive methodology will actually promote
environmental security.
It is clear that considerable symbolic and precedential value can emerge from the criminal punishment of invidious
perpetrators of intentional environmental desecration. However, what about the practical effect? Cases of intentional
environmental destruction do not, when aggregated, constitute the most significant source of harm to the environment.
Since the ICC can only capture the intentional infliction of environmental harm, it leaves undeterred the activities which
cause the greatest amount of environmental harm - negligent or reckless conduct. As a result, the question arises whether
a greater level of deterrence can be achieved through preventative measures as opposed to the threat of criminal
punishment. This is a question that environmental advocates at the domestic level have long considered. At the domestic
level, there has been much discussion regarding the limits of punitive ex post punishment as a device to promote
environmentally respectful behavior. Many advocates prefer a focus on including as policy devices incentive-based
regulation and proactive ex ante prevention. Is there any reason why such a methodology might not prove beneficial at the
international level?
Implementing this second approach - proactive protection - will entail linkages beyond the legal context. Examples
include the creation of economic disincentives to producing environmentally destructive weaponry, technology transfers
to assist developing countries to pursue national security interests in more of an environmentally friendly manner, and
financial assistance mechanisms, for example for the safe decommissioning of nuclear weapons. Linkages to trade and
investment should be developed so as to create disincentives to export and sell the more environmentally injurious military
technology. One final linkage which is of considerable importance involves international peace-keeping or
peace-enforcement forces. These could be mandated to ensure environmental, along with humanitarian, protection.
Allotting these international forces a “green-keeping” mandate could help integrate international environmental norms into
internecine conflict. By way of example, were United Nations involvement in Somalia to have had a “green-keeping”
mandate, then practices of deforestation and assaults on water purity - which were commonplace in the conflict - could
have been much better addressed. Ultimately, the prevention of environmental crime cannot be disaggregated from the
fact that environmental scarcity and resource depletion are often the cause of military conflict.100 As a result, equipping
nations (through technology transfers, transparency of information or financial assistance) to engage in proper
environmental management and sustainable development could have the collateral benefit of mitigating military
aggression.
A relatively new wave of litigation in the United States reveals a third approach to attaining environmental security:
environmental justice claims under the United States Constitution101 or under Title VI of the Civil Rights Act.102 These
claims meld environmental protection and civil rights. The nub of these claims stems from the factual observation that
“environmental degradation often has a distinctly racist aspect.”103 More specifically:
[R]eports generally indicate that people with relatively low incomes and/or people of color are more likely to have hazardous waste treatment facilities sited in
their neighborhoods than are members of the population in general. [M]embers of politically less powerful groups are exposed to greater risks from hazardous
waste related problems than the overall population of the United States, and are thus disproportionately carrying certain environmental burdens of modern
society.104
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (11 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:22 PM]
In response to this difficult situation, the environmental justice paradigm attempts to create “equal protection from
ecological hazards for all communities.”105 Aggrieved parties have argued that the uneven distribution of environmental
burdens on disempowered minority groups infringes the Equal Protection Clause.106 Others have submitted that
decisions to locate environmental facilities in certain regions of the country evidence discrimination in the expenditure of
federal funds.107 The argument has also been raised that Environmental Protection Agency (hereinafter “EPA”)
regulations promulgated to implement Title VI provide an enforceable cause of action should the exercise of the EPA’s
authority to manage environmental policy subject individuals to discrimination.108
Environmental justice litigation has only had limited success. No court has found a violation of the Equal Protection
Clause.109 Courts have held that Title VI prohibits intentional discrimination only.110 Intentional discrimination, as
opposed to disparate impact, can be very difficult to prove in environmental justice cases.111 As for the claim alleging
violation of the EPA regulation, some courts have expressed doubt as to the existence of a private right of action to
enforce such a claim.112 The highest profile environmental justice case thus far, Seif v. Chester Residents Concerned for
Quality Living, involved a claim brought under the EPA regulations.113 The challenge was to the issuance of a permit to
construct and operate a waste treatment facility, more specifically a soil incinerator. The factual underpinnings to this
dispute are typical of many environmental justice claims. Chester is a city of 42,000 inhabitants located in Delaware
County, Pennsylvania.114 Although Delaware County’s 500,000 residents are overwhelmingly white (91%), Chester’s
population is two-thirds African-American.115 The complainants allege that five of Delaware County’s waste treatment
facilities are located in Chester; the remaining two facilities are located in predominantly white areas.116 The fact that the
state permitted the new treatment facility to be located in Chester notwithstanding this pre-existing disproportionality117
prompted residents to sue the state, alleging “environmental racism” in the administrative decisions to allocate permits.
The District Court dismissed the lawsuit.118 The Third Circuit Court of Appeals reversed, finding the complainants
entitled to an implicit private right of action under the EPA regulations and thus permitting the claim to proceed.119 On
June 8, 1998, the United States Supreme Court accorded itself its first opportunity to consider environmental justice by
granting certiorari to review this dispute.120 However, on August 17, 1998, the Supreme Court dismissed its grant of
certiorari, vacated the Chester Residents judgment, and remanded the case back to the Third Circuit with instructions to
dismiss.121 The vacatur was based on the fact the dispute had become moot: on April 30, 1998, before the Supreme
Court granted certiorari, the soil incinerator permit expired and was revoked as the applicant indicated it no longer planned
to site a waste treatment facility in Chester.122 The vacatur of the Third Circuit decision in Chester Residents removes an
important precedent to support environmental justice claims. However, this vacatur does not mean that the Third Circuit
decision is bad law.123 The Supreme Court has not yet spoken on this issue.124 As a result, the legal future of
environmental justice claims in the United States may still carry promise.125 In fact, notwithstanding the procedural
hurdles inherent in having an environmental justice claim heard by a court, the possibilities of facing an environmental
justice lawsuit have influenced government policy in the United States126 Concerns over lawsuits and fears regarding
their perceived effects have also affected the practice of environmental management.127
Might the fertile basis of internationally-negotiated anti-discrimination and human rights conventions not provide solid
ground for environmental justice claims? Prohibitions against discrimination are found in the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights,128 the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights,129 and the International Convention on All
Forms of Racial Discrimination.130 Important regional agreements prohibiting discrimination are found in the European
Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms131 as well as the American Convention on
Human Rights.132
Notwithstanding the fact these conventions may permit international environmental justice claims, thus far there has been
very little literature exploring the use of international human rights as a device to propound environmental security. This
is unfortunate since internationalizing environmental justice recognizes that “environmental security may be ... a global
idea, only fully achievable as part of a universalization of environmental responsibility.”133 For international lawyers,
environmental justice may be attractive in two types of situations: (1) the equal treatment of individuals within a state; and
(2) the equal treatment of individuals between states.
First, environmental justice can help combat “environmental cleansing” B the deliberate misuse of the natural
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (12 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
environment as a tool to promote the politics of racial, ethnic, or class hegemony within a nation-state.134 Environmental
cleansing can deny individuals, groups and communities the “minimum quality of environment”135 needed to sustain
ways of living or even lives and, as such, further political goals such as forced relocation, subjugation, assimilation, or
internal colonialism. In this regard, the creation of environmental insecurity may well “reflect the governing body’s
discriminatory use of power.”136 When the courts and legislatures of the nation-state in question offer no recourse,
individually enforceable remedies under international conventions or political pressure applied internationally may
constitute the best available options to redress the wrongs.
Second, environmental justice can address situations in which developing countries and people of color disproportionately
bear the environmental externalities of the world’s industrialization. One important example is the export of hazardous
waste from the developed world, where it is produced, to the developing world, where it is to be disposed.137 Although
developing countries may be paid to receive these wastes (often quite generously), they often lack the technology to safely
and adequately dispose of them upon receipt; they may also lack the regulatory and scientific infrastructure to supervise
such disposal.138 This then creates profound environmental insecurity in local communities. One commentator has
argued that “the shipment of hazardous waste from developed to developing countries is environmental racism on an
international scale.”139 Although certain recently negotiated conventions140 provide disincentives to and in some cases
even prohibit the shipment of certain wastes from developed countries to developing countries, the characterization of
these shipments as infringing environmental justice allows nations not signatories to these agreements to be held to similar
standards. Embedding the prohibition against such shipments in the discourse of human rights also allows a broader range
of exported substances to be subject to review: for example, the adverse environmental impacts caused by the export of
dangerous or environmentally risky products to the developing world. Should these products not constitute “hazardous
wastes,” then they fall outside the scope of the international conventions. However, the distributional implications of such
exports could well be caught by international anti-discrimination standards applied to the environmental context.
Elevating environmental justice to the international level will require the creation of new institutions. What tribunals,
courts, or agencies can determine the existence of environmental injustice? Are domestic courts or existing international
human rights commissions (for example the United Nations Commission on Human Rights) sufficient? Or will new
international human rights tribunals need to be created? On a related note, elevating environmental justice to the
international level will also require the establishment of new rights. For example, is there an internationally recognized
right to public health or security of the person?141 Such a right must exist in order for there to be a remedy for its
infringement by discriminatory environmental mismanagement or insecurity. In bridging this particular gap, advocates for
environmental justice should be encouraged by the Stockholm Declaration, which as early as 1972 contemplated the
linkages between justice, equality, and environmental well-being:
Man has the fundamental right to freedom, equality and adequate conditions of life, in an environment of a quality that permits a life of dignity and well-being,
and he bears a solemn responsibility to protect and improve the environment for present and future generations.142
A subsidiary question which arises (and has been particularly pivotal in the United States jurisprudence) is whether the
discrimination must be intentional or whether proof of discriminatory impact suffices to justify a complaint.
In sum, the opportunities for environmental justice claims as a device to promote transnational environmental security
remain inchoate and unexplored. It remains, though, that environmental justice claims at the intra-state level may provide
important linkages to the political right of self-determination. Such claims recognize that maintenance of a “minimum
quality of the environment” is a prerequisite to the existence (and enjoyment) of civil and political rights, as well as the
dignity of the individual. Environmental justice claims can also promote democratization by encouraging local and citizen
group involvement in the political process.143 By “permitting individual victims to activate international enforcement
procedures,” these claims increase political participation together with transparency of information.144 Environmental
justice claims at the macro, inter-state level may help link environmental protection with socio-economic rights, such as
the right to development. Opportunities for development may be hindered when the developed world passes the costs of
its industrialization onto developing nations. Ultimately, a macro, transnational conception of environmental justice can
constitute a theoretical justification for the promotion of equality in the sharing the benefits and burdens of environmental
management globally. As for the burdens, environmental justice may justify distributive equality in terms of shouldering
the responsibilities of dealing with global environmental problems (e.g. climate change, protecting the ozone layer). True
distributive equality in this regard would require the developed world to bear a considerably larger burden of assuming
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (13 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
these costs and responsibilities. This, in turn, feeds into the discourse of “common but differentiated responsibilities”
between developed and developing countries which is growing into a principle of international environmental law.145
In the end, the question is not really whether punitive sanction or proactive protection or environmental justice should
constitute the dominant approach to promote environmental security. Instead, a polycentric approach blending all three
paradigms might maximize policy results. Such a multifaceted approach could promote environmental security by
criminally punishing the most invidious offender, dissuading the negligent offender through incentive-based schemes,
cleaning up blighted communities, according individuals a medium to air grievances, and encouraging the global
community to equally shoulder the environmental externalities of industrialization.
VI. Conclusion
Article 8(2)(b)(iv) of the Rome Statute criminalizes the willful infliction of “widespread, long-term and severe damage to
the natural environment.” The inclusion of this crime within the jurisdiction of the ICC is cause for limited celebration and
some disappointment. The disappointment flows from the fact that such conduct is already “prohibited” by virtue of
Protocol I and the ENMOD Convention. Nonetheless, the Rome Statute does provide a significantly more viable
mechanism to sanction this illegal conduct. It will, however, be very difficult to prove “widespread, long-term, and severe
damage;” proof will be rendered more problematic owing to the conjunctive nature of these terms. Additionally, the
environmental war crime requires a very significant level of knowledge and intentionality. Criminal behavior is not
sanctioned on an objective basis and, consequently, ignorance of the law might serve as a defense. This would be less than
desirable as environmental education and transparency of knowledge would then be discouraged. The availability of
military advantage as a defense to the intentional infliction of widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural
environment may further denude the practical effect of Article 8(2)(b)(iv).
The inclusion of environmental crimes within the Rome Statute should also give rise to considerable reflection. The
principle point of contemplation is the usefulness of the ICC as a device to promote environmental security. Ultimately
some of the foundational limitations of the ICC as a device to promote such security flow not only from its structure, but
also from the punitive paradigm it embodies. As a result, this Article suggests that proactive protection and environmental
justice be woven into the international legal response to environmental crimes. Proceeding with this blended approach
allows environmental security to serve as a lightning-rod uniting disparate fields such as international criminal law, the
law of war, international trade law, international humanitarian law, and international anti-discrimination law. Only
through such a polycentric approach can environmental security be promoted outside of the narrow confines of
widespread long-term and severe damage intentionally inflicted during an international armed conflict.
* Assistant Professor, School of Law, University of Arkansas at Little Rock. E-mail address: madrumbl@ualr.edu. This
Article was presented at the International Law Association International Law Weekend (November 4-6, 1999), for a panel
entitled “Evolving Law: International Human Rights in Flux.” Parts III and IV of this Article expand upon concerns
raised in my essay Waging War Against the World: The Need to Move from War Crimes to Environmental Crimes, 22
Fordham Int=l L.J. 122 (1998).
1. Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, U.N. Doc. A/CONF. 183/9 (1998) [hereinafter “Rome Statute”].
2. Id. at art. 5(1).
3. See comments of Professor Theodor Meron at the Opening Session of the International Law Association
International Law Weekend (November 4-6, 1999) (notes on file with the author).
4. See, e.g., Bernard A. Weintraub, Environmental Security, Environmental Management, and Environmental Justice,
12 Pace Envtl. L. Rev. 533, 546 (1995) (“environmental security ... refers to a community’s state of assurance that its
stability as a community will not be threatened by a lack of proper management of the natural resources it deems to be
necessary parts of its identity”).
5. See, e.g., 1949 Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick in Armed Forces
in the Field, August 12, 1949, 75 U.N.T.S. 31; 1949 Geneva Convention II for the Amelioration of the Condition of
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (14 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
Wounded, Sick and Shipwrecked Members of the Armed Forces at Sea, August 12, 1949, 75 U.N.T.S. 85; 1949 Geneva
Convention III Relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War, August 12, 1949, 75 U.N.T.S. 135; 1949 Geneva
Convention IV Relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War, August 12, 1949, 75 U.N.T.S. 287. The
Security Council=s creation of ad hoc International Criminal Tribunals in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda also evinces
the international community’s concern for the humanitarian consequences of war. See also Rome Statute, supra note 1.
7. Seth Mydans, Vietnam Sees War=s Legacy in Its Young, N.Y. Times (May 16, 1999), at 12. Two commentators have
argued that the Vietnam War=s “environmental damages offered a rallying point for opponents of the conflict and
catalyzed political animus against the war.” See Peter J. Richards and Michael N. Schmitt, Mars Meets Mother Nature:
Protecting the Environment During Armed Conflict, 28 Stetson L. Rev. 1047, 1053 (1999).
8. Id.
9. See Oscar Arias, Responsibility of Nations to the Environment, in Proceedings of the First International Conference
on Addressing Environmental Consequences of War: Legal, Economic and Scientific Perspectives (June 10-12, 1998).
10. Mydans, supra note 7.
11. There is evidence that dioxin, the poisonous residue of Agent Orange, contributes to the types of birth defects found
in Vietnam. However, much of this evidence is “anecdotal” and is disputed by the United States, which persists in
refusing to take responsibility. Id.
12. Richards and Schmitt, supra note 7, at 1055.
13. See Public Authority for Assessment of Compensation of Damages Resulting from Iraqi Aggression, Oil and
Environmental Claims Bulletin (Aug. 1997). Independent of the damage to Kuwait and to the Persian Gulf waters, it is
estimated that the oil well fires set by Iraqi soldiers expelled one to two million tons of carbon dioxide, which in 1991
represented one percent of total global carbon dioxide emissions. Id. at 8. One commentator has estimated that over 700
oil wells were ignited. See Weintraub, supra note 4, at 536.
14. Created by virtue of Security Council Resolution 687, U.N. SCOR, 2981st mtg. at 7, U.N. Doc. S/RES/687 (1991).
15. Jay Austin and Carl Bruch, The Greening of Warfare, 15:6 Environmental Forum 32, 33 (1998).
16. Id.
17. One scholar has in fact argued that the patterns of the NATO bombings trigger important international humanitarian
law concerns. See comments of Professor Julie Mertus, “The Imprint of Kosovo on International Law” Panel, International
Law Weekend (November 4-6, 1999) (notes on file with the author).
18. Tom Walker, Missile Strikes Pollute Danube, Globe and Mail (April 19, 1999) at 1.
19. Id.
20. Id.
21. Marlise Simons, Hungary Says Danube’s Bombed-Out Bridges May Cause Floods, N.Y. Times (October 24, 1999).
One hurdle which will have to be overcome in the repair of the bridges is that the FRY government maintains there are
still unexploded missiles and other ordnance in the Danube. Id.
22. Id.
23. Richards and Schmitt, supra note 7, at 1051. See also Neil A. F. Popovic, Humanitarian Law, Protection of the
Environment, and Human Rights, 8 Geo. Int=l Envtl. L. Rev. 67, 69 (1995) (providing examples of deliberate dam-busting
by armed forces during the Second Sino-Japanese War of 1937-1945, World War II, and the Korean War).
24. Mobilization should also include the day-to-day maintenance of military bases. It is reported that it would take
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (15 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
“enormous diversions of money and effort to remediate the numerous hazardous waste sites that the United States military
has created at its many military bases.” See Weintraub, supra note 4, at 582. Should military bases not be run in an
environmentally sensitive manner, the threat of environmental degradation and contamination increases.
25. Symposium Rationale, Arms and the Environment: Preventing the Perils of Disarmament, University of Tulsa (Dec.
9B10, 1999) (“Many of the past and potentially adverse future global environmental impacts on the Arctic caused by
Russian nuclear dumping have obstructed and delayed the implementation and multiplied the costs of implementing
START 1 [n.b. the Strategic Arms Reduction Treaties]. The United States, Norway, and the international community are
trying, ex post, to address and prevent these unforeseen problems, but might have done so more effectively and efficiently
ex ante.”).
26. See, e.g., German General Rendulic was acquitted of charges he perpetrated a Ascorched earth@ policy as his forces
evacuated Norway. See The Hostage Case (U.S. v. List), 11 T.W.C. 759 (1950). Rendulic alleged he believed his forces
were being chased by Soviet forces. As a result, he maintained that the environmental destruction was militarily
necessary. As it turned out, Rendulic’s forces were not being chased by Soviet forces. However, it was held that
Rendulic’s belief, although mistaken, was reasonably held. Id. The Rendulic case is a classic example of the operation of
military necessity as a defense to environmental crimes. See Ensign Florencio J. Yuzon, Deliberate Environmental
Modification through the Use of Chemical and Biological Weapons: ‘ Greening’ the International Laws of Armed Conflict
to Establish an Environmentally Protective Regime, 11 Am. U. J. Int’l L. & Pol’y 793, 815 (1996).
27. U.N. SCOR 827, U.N. Doc. S/RES/827 (May 25, 1993), Annex [hereinafter Statute of the ICTY].
28. U.N. SCOR 955 S.C. Res. 955, U.N. SCOR, 3453d mtg., (Nov. 8, 1994), Annex [hereinafter Statute of the ICTR].
29. The ICTY has jurisdiction over a series of war crimes. See Statute of the ICTY, supra note 27, art. at 3.
Environmental desecration does not figure among the listed crimes. There is, however, jurisdiction over a series of war
crimes which bear an incidental relationship with environmental insecurity. See id. These include: employment of
poisonous weapons (art. 3(a)); wanton destruction of cities, towns or villages, or devastation not justified by military
necessity (art. 3(b)); attack, or bombardment, by whatever means, of undefended towns, villages, dwellings, or buildings
(art. 3(c)); and plunder of public property (art. 3(e)). The ICTY can also prosecute as a war crime the extensive destruction
and appropriation of property, not justified by military necessity and carried out unlawfully and wantonly (art. 2(d)).
However, these crimes do not involve environmental destruction as a crime per se. Instead they focus on damage to
human environments and property. Without the immediate causal link to human harm there can be no liability. This
provides no jurisdiction to hold individuals accountable for wanton environmental destruction, regardless of the long-term
effects of that destruction on human life or environmental security. The ICTY’s jurisdiction over war crimes is not limited
to those enumerated in the Statute of the ICTY. Id. at art. 3. However, so far no one has been prosecuted for
environmental war crimes. See Preparatory Commission Request, infra note 39, at 29. As a result, the ICTY has not been
called upon to decide whether it has the discretionary jurisdiction to address such crimes. Id.
30. Statute of the ICTR, supra note 28, at art. 4. One crime over which the ICTR has jurisdiction that bears a remote
relationship to the environment is “pillage.” Id. at art. 4(f). Jurisdiction can also be exercised over “violence to health of
persons” and “acts of terrorism.” Id. at arts. 4(a) and 4(d). Both of these crimes have an even more remote relationship
with the protection of the natural environment. However, there have been no charges involving these war crimes. Given
the profound environmental insecurity arising out of the Rwandan conflict, the lack of jurisdiction over environmental war
crimes is disappointing. The Rwandan conflict has seen two national parks (Parc national des volcans and Parc national de
l=Akagéra) landmined, endangered species (the mountain gorillas) poached, agricultural lands rendered barren in order to
coerce the migration of persecuted peoples, and systemic resettlement exhausting moderate lands B specifically in eastern
Congo B of their agricultural capacities. See Mark Drumbl, Rule of Law Amid Lawlessness: Counseling the Accused in
Rwanda’s Domestic Genocide Trials, 29 Colum. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 545 (1998). The domestic war crimes prosecutions
which are occurring in Rwanda have also been completely reticent in the area of environmental crimes.
31. Rome Statute, supra note 1, at art. 5(1)(c) (vesting the ICC with jurisdiction over war crimes). Articles 5(1)(d) and
5(2) create jurisdiction over “crimes of aggression.” However, the definition of this term is not provided; in fact, the
Rome Statute leaves it to the parties to define this term in the future. Id. Those concerned with environmental issues may
view the open-ended nature of Acrimes of aggression@ as a potential device to expand the ICC=s jurisdiction over
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (16 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
environmental matters.
32. Id. at art. 8(2)(b)(iv)(emphasis added).
33. Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court, U.N. Doc. A/AC.249/1998/CRP.8
(2 April 1998), section B(b) to the “War Crimes” section of Part 2 (visited Feb. 18, 2000) <http://www.un.org/icc>
[hereinafter “Draft Rome Statute”]. The Draft Rome Statute is on file with the author.
34. Rome Statute, supra note 1, at art. 8(1). Another limitation to the effectiveness of the ICC in the area of war crimes is
the fact that any signatory state can opt out of the ICC’s jurisdiction over war crimes alleged to have been committed by
that state’s nationals or on that state’s territory. See id. at art. 124.
35. In other places, the Rome Statute prohibits as a “war crime” conduct which may be collaterally related to the
well-being of the natural environment, or have some other ancillary connection. See, e.g., id. at art. 8(2)(a)(iv) (sanctions
extensive destruction and appropriation of property not justified by military necessity and carried out unlawfully and
wantonly). Article 8(2)(b) prohibits other serious violations of the laws and customs applicable in international armed
conflict, within the established framework of international law, namely:
(ii) Intentionally directing attacks against civilian objects;
(iii) Intentionally directing attacks against ... installations, material ... involved in a humanitarian assistance or a
peacekeeping mission;
(v) Attacking or bombing ... dwellings or buildings which are undefended and which are not military objectives;
(ix) Intentionally directing attacks against ... [inter alia] historic monuments;
(xiii) Destroying or seizing the enemy’s property unless such destruction or seizure be imperatively demanded by the
necessities of war;
(xvi) Pillaging a town or place;
(xxv) Intentionally using starvation of civilians as a method of warfare by depriving them of objects indispensable to their
survival.
The Rome Statute also criminalizes the use of certain weapons with destructive effects on both humanity as well as the
natural environment. See id. at article 8(2)(b). Prohibited practices include:
(xvii) Employing poison or poisoned weapons;
(xviii) Employing asphyxiating, poisonous or other gases, and all analogous liquids, materials or devices.
Many of these weapons are already prohibited by other international agreements. See, e.g., Convention on Prohibitions or
Restrictions on the Use of Certain Conventional Weapons Which May be Deemed to be Excessively Injurious or to Have
Indiscriminate Effects, 35 U.N. GAOR, 35th Sess., U.N. Doc. A/CONF 95/15, Oct. 27, 1980, 19 I.L.M. 1523; Protocol
for the Prohibition of the Use in War of Asphyxiating, Poisonous or Other Gases, and of Bacteriological Methods of
Warfare, June 17, 1925, 26 U.S.T. 571; Convention on the Prohibition of the Development, Production and Stockpiling of
Bacteriological (Biological) and Toxin Weapons and on their Destruction, Apr. 10, 1972, 26 U.S.T. 583; Convention on
the Prohibition of the Development, Production, Stockpiling and Use of Chemical Weapons and on Their Destruction, Jan.
13, 1993, 32 I.L.M. 800.
36. See Rome Statute, supra note 1, at arts. 8(2)(c) & (e). These articles list the types of war crimes punishable within
internal armed conflicts. Intentionally inflicting widespread, long-term and severe harm to the environment is omitted
from this list. Basic principles of treaty interpretation provide that this omission is deliberate and evinces a desire not to
punish environmental desecration when committed in an internal conflict. Further limitations on the application of the
entire Rome Statute to internal conflicts are found in Article 8(2)(f), which provides.
Paragraph 2(e) applies to armed conflicts not of an international character and thus does not apply to situations of internal
disturbances and tensions, such as riots, isolated and sporadic acts of violence or other acts of a similar nature. It applies
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (17 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
to armed conflicts that take place in the territory of a State when there is protracted armed conflict between governmental
authorities and organized armed groups or between such groups. Id [emphasis added].
In sum, nations appear less willing to criminalize conduct in internal conflicts than in international conflicts. In the end,
this gives rise to concern that the protection of both humanity and the environment in internal conflicts may be inadequate.
However, even the limited jurisdiction obtained over internal conflicts represents a major step forward. After all, such
intrusion into internal affairs is one of the most jealously guarded elements of state sovereignty.
37. See discussion of the environmental effects of internal conflicts in Rwanda, supra note 30. There are other examples
of intentional environmental degradation occurring during internal conflicts. See infra note 134, for a discussion of the
effects of the El Salvadoran, Nicaraguan, and Colombian conflict. In the Colombian conflict, it is reported that a
“guerrilla group ... attempted to undermine the authority of the government by repeatedly blowing up the nation’s largest
oil pipeline, spilling more than 600,000 gallons of oil into east Andes wetlands.” See Weintraub, supra note 4, at 583,
citing James Brooke, Colombia Rebels Turn to Ecological Terrorism, N.Y. Times (Oct. 29, 1990). Insurgency and
counter-insurgency guerilla civil wars have a particularly devastating effect on local environments. Insurgents often use
tropical forests as home bases and hiding grounds; counter-insurgency forces often respond by slashing and burning
forests, together with polluting rivers. The Cambodian conflict reflects a different, yet equally destructive, misuse of the
environment during an internal armed conflict. It is reported that “the Khmer Rouge has survived in the rainforests on the
Thai-Cambodian border by decimating the forests there and selling concessions to log the timber and mine whatever
minerals can be found in that region. This abuse of Cambodia’s natural resources can be understood to be a threat not
only to Cambodia’s environmental security ... but also to the environmental security of all those who rely on, or support,
the protection of the Cambodian rainforests.” See id. at 602-03.
38. Supra note 25 (“disarming nuclear and chemical weapons and weapon systems does ... create environmental
impacts”).
39. “Attack” has been defined as an Aact of violence against the adversary, whether in offence or defense.” See Protocol
I on the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts, opened for signature Dec. 12, 1977, 1125 U.N.T.S. 3
(entered into force Dec. 7, 1978) [hereinafter Protocol I], art. 49(1). See also Preparatory Commission for the International
Criminal Court, Proposal submitted by Japan, U.N. Doc. PCNICC/1999/WGEC/DP.12 (July 22, 1999). The attack cannot
be isolated or sporadic, but must involve the Ause of armed force to carry out a military operation during the course of an
armed conflict.” See Request from the Governments of Belgium, Costa Rica, Finland, Hungary, the Republic of Korea,
South Africa and the Permanent Observer Mission of Switzerland to the United Nations regarding the text prepared by the
International Committee of the Red Cross on article 8, ? 2(b), (i), (ii), (iii), (iv), (v), (vi), (vii), (ix), (xi) and (xii) of the
Statute, UN Doc. PCNICC/1999/WGEC/INF.2/Add.1 (July 30, 1999) 29 [hereinafter Preparatory Commission Request].
40. United Nations Convention on the Prohibition of Military or Any Other Hostile Use of Environmental Modification
Techniques, May 18, 1977, 31 U.S.T. 333 (entered into force Oct. 5, 1978) [hereinafter ENMOD Convention], which
prohibits engagement “in military ... environmental modification techniques having widespread, long-lasting or severe
effects as the means of destruction, damage, or injury to any other State Party.” The ENMOD Convention focuses on the
use of the environment as a weapon - as a result, wanton destruction of the environment occurring as a byproduct of a
military campaign might not fall within its parameters. See Richards and Schmitt, supra note 7, at 1063 (“[T]he 1977
ENMOD Convention ... merely limits the use of modification of the environment as a tool or weapon of warfare.”).
Environmental damage per se is for the most part not a concern of the ENMOD Convention. See Richards and Schmitt,
supra note 7, at 1063. Some of the activities prohibited by the ENMOD Convention amount to outrageous behavior not
within the military capability of most nations. for example: inducing earthquakes and tidal waves, or activating quiescent
volcanoes.
41. Protocol I, supra note 39, at art. 35(3) (prohibits “methods or means of warfare which are intended, or may be
expected, to cause widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment”). Id. at art. 55 states that:
Care shall be taken in warfare to protect the natural environment against widespread, long-term and severe damage. This
protection includes a prohibition on the use of methods or means of warfare which are intended or may be expected to
cause such damage to the natural environment and thereby to prejudice the health or survival of the population. Attacks
against the natural environment by way of reprisals are prohibited.
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (18 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
See also id. at arts. 54, 56 (which provide for the protection of property, which has ancillary benefits for the
environment.) The United States has not yet ratified Protocol I, in part owing to objections over its environmental
provisions. See Richards and Schmitt, supra note 7, at 1054.
42. UN Doc. A/CN.4/SR.2241, 22 August 1991, pp. 15, 18, cited in Preparatory Commission Request, supra note 39, at
33.
43. UN Doc. A/48/269, p. 9. See also Doc. A/47/328, 31 July 1992, paras. 20, 63, cited in Preparatory Commission
Request, supra note 39, at 34.
44. Understanding I of the Conference of the Committee of Disarmament, reprinted in Convention on the Prohibition of
Military or Any Other Hostile Use of Environmental Modification Techniques: Hearing Before Senate Comm. On Foreign
Relations, 95th Cong. 2d Sess. (1978) [hereinafter CCD Understanding].
45. Id. (It is further understood that the interpretation set forth above is intended exclusively for this Convention and is
not intended to prejudice the interpretation of the same or similar terms of used in connection with any other international
agreement.). See also Richards and Schmitt, supra note 7, at 1065.
46. Austin and Bruch, supra note 15, at 38.
47. UN Doc. A/48/269, p. 9. See also Jozef Goldblat, The Mitigation of Environmental Disruption by War: Legal
Approaches, in Environmental Hazards of War: Releasing Dangerous Forces in an Industrialized World 52 (Arthur
Westing ed. 1990). The ILC has concluded that Along-term@ should be taken to “mean the long-lasting nature of the
effects and not the possibility that the damage would occur a long time afterwards.” See UN Doc. A/CN.4/SR.2241, 22
August 1991, pp. 15, 18, cited in Preparatory Commission Request, supra note 39, at 33.
48. Lynn Berat, Defending the Right to a Healthy Environment: Toward a Crime of Geocide in International Law, 11
B.U. Int=l L.J. 327, 347 n.102 (1993).
49. Humanitarian Law in Armed Conflicts Manual (Germany), No. 403, 37 (1992), cited in Preparatory Commission
Request, supra note 39, at 34. More broadly, the fact that the environmental war crimes is clustered by the Working Group
on the Elements of Crimes with provisions entirely focused on damage to the human environment gives further credence
to the concern that the delegates to the Preparatory Commission may not see Article 8(2)(b)(iv) operating beyond these
anthropocentric limitations. See Preparatory Commission for the International Criminal Court, Second Session, 26 July to
13 August 1999, <http://www.un.org/law/icc/prepcpmm/prepjul.htm> (visited October 18, 1999) [hereinafter Preparatory
Commission for the International Criminal Court, Second Session].
50. GAOR, 46th session, suppl. No. 10 (U.N. Doc. A/46/10), p. 276, cited in Preparatory Commission Request, supra
note 39, at 33.
51. Id.
52. Id.
53. See Preparatory Commission for the International Criminal Court, Second Session, supra note 49.
54. The Working Group on the Elements of Crimes regularly meets during the Preparatory Commission sessions. See id.
So far, it has considered the elements of some of the war crimes enumerated in the Rome Statute. It has divided the war
crimes provisions into nine clusters based on “the possible commonality of their elements.” Id. at Art. 8(2)(b)(iv) is
clustered with arts. 8(2)(b)(v) [attacking or bombarding, by whatever means, towns, villages, dwellings or buildings which
are undefended and which are not military objectives], (ix) [intentionally directing attacks against buildings dedicated to
religion, education, art, science or charitable purposes, historic monuments, hospitals and places where the sick and
wounded are collected, provided they are not military objectives], and (xxiv) [intentionally directing attacks against
buildings, material, medical units and transport, and personnel using the distinctive emblems of the Geneva Conventions
in conformity with international law]. Id. So far, several discussion papers have been proposed by the Working Group on
the Elements of Crimes. No discussion paper has been prepared for Article 8(2)(b)(iv). Id. The official website for the
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (19 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
Preparatory Commission addresses this gap in the following manner: “there was not sufficient time for the Coordinator to
prepare discussion papers on the elements of all the provisions of war crimes.” Id. Of the 23 national government
proposals submitted to the Working Group on Elements of Crimes, only a handful made mention of Article 8(2)(b)(iv).
See Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, List of documents issued at the second session of the Preparatory
Commission, <http://www.un.org/law/icc/prepcomm/julaug/docs2nd.htm> (visited October 19, 1999). Only one of these
proposals gave thorough treatment to Article 8(2)(b)(iv). See Preparatory Commission Request, supra note 39. The fact
that little individualized attention is given to the environmental war crimes provision notwithstanding its fundamentally
different nature than the other war crimes may foreshadow the possibility that the environmental war crime is simply not
taken particularly seriously within the spectrum of offenses contained within the Rome Statute.
55. Austin and Bruch, supra note 15, at 39.
56. See Preparatory Commission Request, supra note 39, at 28, nn. 32-33.
57. Mark J.T. Caggiano, The Legitimacy of Environmental Destruction in Modern Warfare: Customary Substance over
Conventional Form, 20 B.C. Envtl. Aff. L. Rev. 479, 496 (1993).
58. The Hostage Case, supra note 26, 11 T.W.C. at 1254.
59. See Protocol I, supra note 39, at arts. 35, 55. See also Richards and Schmitt, supra note 6, at 1062 (“No other
considerations, such as the military advantage offered by the prohibited act, the possibility that alternative operations will
result in greater incidental injury to civilians or collateral damage to civilian property, or the overall impact of the action in
context, can trump the principle of environmental protection”). Protocol I did use the military advantage limitation for
other violations (e.g., the safety of civilians). See Protocol I, supra note 39, at arts. 51, 52, 57. As a result, interpretive
assistance of the meaning of “military advantage” in the Rome Statute can flow from the use of the term “military
advantage” in Protocol I. Any such assistance is, of course, limited by the fact that “military advantage” in Protocol I does
not figure into its treatment of the environmental war crime.
60. See Preparatory Commission Request, supra note 39, at 29.
61. See U.N. Doc. A/CONF.183/INF/10 (July 13, 1998).
62. Preparatory Commission Request, supra note 39, at 30. This is the position taken by the governments of Belgium,
Canada, Germany, Italy, the Netherlands, Spain, and the United Kingdom in regard to Protocol I. Australia and New
Zealand have declared that military advantage anticipated refers to the Abona fide expectation that the attack will make a
relevant and proportional contribution to the objective of the military attack involved.” Id. Commentators have also linked
the military advantage of the specific attack in question to the purposes of the military operation taken as a whole. Id. at
31.
63. Id. at 27.
64. Id. at 34.
65. Zimmermann, in Commentary on the Additional Protocol I, art. 85, No. 3479, at 996, cited in Preparatory
Commission Request, supra note 39, at 34.
66. Follow-up to the International Conference for the Protection of War Victims, Guidelines for Military Manuals and
Instructions on the Protection of the Environment in Times of Armed Conflict, International Review of the Red Cross, No.
311, 230-237 (March 1, 1996); published as an annex to U.N. Doc. A/49/323 (1994)
<http://www.icrc.org/unicc/icrcnews.nsf/8> [hereinafter Guidelines]. The United Nations General Assembly invited all
states to widely disseminate these Guidelines and to give due consideration to the possibility of incorporating them into
their military manuals. See GA Res. 49/50 (Dec. 9, 1994), art. 11. See also San Remo Manual on International Law
Applicable to Armed Conflicts at Sea (Louise Doswald-Beck, ed.) (Cambridge University Press, 1995) for a restatement
of the law applicable to armed conflicts at sea. Many of the principles in the San Remo Manual are encapsulated in the
general provisions of the Guidelines.
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (20 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:23 PM]
67. Guidelines, supra note 646, at art. I(1).
68. Id. at art. IV(18).
69. Background Paper, in Proceedings of the First International Conference on Addressing Environmental Consequences
of War: Legal, Economic and Scientific Perspectives (June 10-12, 1998) 5; See also Preparatory Commission Request,
supra note 39, at 34.
70. IRIN News Update (March 18, 1999). The countries are: Democratic Republic of Congo, Kenya, Lesotho, Tanzania,
Uganda and Zambia. The headquarters of the African Interpol will be in Nairobi, Kenya. Negotiators indicated that the
arrangement was required owing Ato the need for international cooperation to fight wildlife crimes successfully.” Id.
71. Council of Europe, Convention on the Protection of the Environment Through Criminal Law, ETS No. 172
(November 4, 1998).
72. Id. at pmbl.
73. Id. at arts. 2, 3.
74. Id. at art. 2.
75. Id.
76. This crime would operate within and outside the context of war. See, e.g., Richard A. Falk, Environmental Disruption
by Military Means and International Law, in Environmental Warfare: A Technical, Legal and Policy Appraisal 33-51
(1984); Jesica E. Seacor, Environmental Terrorism: Lessons from the Oil Fires of Kuwait, 10 Am. U. J. Int=l L. & Pol=y
481 (1994); Mark Allan Gray, The International Crime of Ecocide, 26 Cal. W. Int=l L.J. 215 (1996); Berat, supra note 48;
Caggiano, supra note 57; Yuzon, supra note 26.
77. See Mark A. Drumbl, Waging War Against the World: The Need to Move From War Crimes to Environmental
Crimes, 22 Fordham Int=l L.J. 122, 142 (1998).
78. A case in point could be the 1986 meltdown at the Chernobyl plant in the former Soviet Union. See Berat, supra note
48, at 345 (There is substantial evidence that although Soviet scientists and governmental officials were aware that the
Soviet nuclear power plant design was flawed and had the potential for causing unmitigated disaster, they persisted in
maintaining old plants and built new ones without design modification.).
79. See Douglas Frantz, Sovereign Islands: Gaps in Sea Laws Shield Pollution by Cruise Lines, N.Y. Times, January 3,
1999, at Al. (documenting pollution activities by the Royal Caribbean Cruise Lines, proof of which induced United States
courts to order a $9 million fine and a promise that the dumping practices would cease); See Matthew L. Wald, Cruise
Line Pleads Guilty to Dumping of Chemicals, N.Y. Times, July 22, 1999, (documenting further pollution activity by Royal
Caribbean after the original fine, which lead to a guilty plea to an additional $18 million fine). Although United States
authorities were ultimately successful in asserting jurisdiction over the cruise ships and subjecting them to United States
law, this was not an easy process. “The ships fly foreign flags and the parent companies are registered in foreign countries,
often putting them outside the reach of the authorities in this country.” See Wald, supra note 79.
80. Eight Countries Agree to Fight Environmental Crime, N.Y. Times, April 6, 1998, at A4.
81. John Klotz, 20:12 National L.J., (November 17, 1997) at A18 (col. 3). For the Indonesian context alone, see Randy
Lee Loftis, The Tropics Are on Fire, Toronto Star, June 6, 1998, at C6 (“evidence shows that settlers were being paid by
large corporations to burn forests to convert land into corporate-owned palm or rice plantations”). “The Indonesian
Environmental Forum estimates that at least two million hectares of forests and other land were burned in 1997.” See
Oran R. Young, Institutional Dimensions of Global Environmental Change: Science Plan 31 (1999). The effects on the
environment are clear: immediate destruction, an inability of ecosystem regeneration, as well as contribution to global
warming. In the end, this destruction comes full circle to affect humanity: through death and disability owing to the
effects of asthma and smog-related illnesses, and, in the case of the Indonesian fires, creating smoke and haze which may
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (21 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]
have induced a plane crash in Sumatra which took the lives of 234 people. See Loftis, supra note 81.
82. Rome Statute, supra note 1, at art. 5(1).
83. Austin and Bruch, supra note 15, at 32.
84. See Preparatory Commission for the International Criminal Court, Second Session, supra note 49; See also supra
note 54.
85. For example, in the recent International Court of Justice’s decision in Case Concerning the Gabcíkovo-Nagymaros
Project (Hungary/Slovakia) (Sept. 25, 1997, No. 92 General List,
<http://www.icj-cij.org/idocket/ihs/ihsjudgement/ihsjudcontent.html>), the judges had to be educated in the environmental
science aspects of the dispute. Although there is much to be gained from educating lay people on environmental issues,
this can involve significant time as well as financial costs. A specialized tribunal could avoid some of these. Making
mention of the International Court of Justice begs the question whether it could serve as an adjudicator of environmental
crimes. In the past, the International Court of Justice has had limited experience with environmental matters, although it
has taken some very important decisions, such as the Nuclear Tests Cases (Australia v. France) 1974 I.C.J. 253; Military
and Paramilitary Activities In and Against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. United States) 1986 I.C.J. 16; and most recently in
Fisheries Jurisdiction Case (Spain v. Canada) (Dec. 4, 1998). It has also recently created an Environmental Chamber with
a view to playing a more proactive role in resolving environmental disputes. Nonetheless, the impediments to the
effectiveness of the International Court of Justice to adjudicating environmental crimes are significant: (1) the requirement
that both litigants consent to the jurisdiction of the court, which is impractical in any criminal context where it is
inexorable that one litigant will unwillingly be dragged into court; and (2) there is simply no jurisdiction to hear disputes
involving individuals or non-natural legal persons.
86. Council of Europe, Convention on the Protection of the Environment Through Criminal Law, supra note 71.
87. Rome Statute, supra note 1, at art. 77.
88. Council of Europe, Convention on the Protection of the Environment Through Criminal Law, supra note 71.
89. See supra note 14. The UNCC is only beginning to turn to the environmental claims which have been filed.
Nonetheless, initial decisions by the UNCC in other areas may reveal limitations on its effectiveness to assess
compensation for environmental harms. For example, in its decision on contractual claims issued on July 1, 1998, the
UNCC limited many of the asserted losses on the basis that the claimants had not established a sufficiently direct causal
link to Iraqi aggression: more particularly, the UNCC required “specific proof that the failure to perform was the direct
result of Iraq=s invasion and occupation of Kuwait.” See Austin and Bruch, supra note 15, at 32, 35. In the end, the
contractual claimants received less than one-tenth of the damages they had asserted. Id. at 32. Rigorous requirements of
causality and directness of damage may make it difficult for environmental and public health claims to succeed.
90. Rome Statute, supra note 1, at art. 79.
91. Austin and Bruch, supra note 15, at 33.
92. Id. at 39.
93. Rome Statute, supra note 1, at art. 21(1), which states that the Court shall apply:
(a) In the first place, this Statute, Elements of Crimes and its Rules of Procedure and Evidence;
(b) In the second place, where appropriate, applicable treaties and the principles and rules of international law, including
the established principles of the international law of armed conflict.
94. In addition to the ENMOD Convention and Protocol I, these fragments include the International Law Commission
Draft Articles on State Responsibility (provides that an international crime may result from, inter alia, a serious breach of
an international obligation of essential importance for the safe-guarding and preservation of the human environment, such
as those prohibiting massive pollution of the atmosphere or of the seas). See International Law Commission’s Draft
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (22 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]
Articles on State Responsibility, art. 19(3)(d) (Shabtai Rosenne ed., 1991). This is one of the few international legal
documents prior to the Rome Statute which demonstrated a willingness to criminalize environmental degradation. The
International Law Commission Draft Code of Crimes Against the Peace and Security of Mankind recognizes as Awar
crimes:” (i) extensive destruction ... of property, not justified by military necessity and carried out unlawfully and
wantonly; (ii) employment of poisonous weapons or other weapons calculated to cause unnecessary suffering; (iii) wanton
destruction of cities, towns or villages, or devastation not justified by military necessity; and (iv) in the case of armed
conflict, using methods or means of warfare not justified by military necessity with the intent to cause widespread,
long-term and severe damage to the natural environment and thereby gravely prejudice the health or survival of the
population and such damage occurs. See International Law Commission Draft Code of Crimes Against the Peace and
Security of Mankind, art. 20, G.A. Res. 97, U.N. GAOR, 33d Sess., Supp. No. 45, at 220, U.N. Doc. A/33/45 (1978);
amended by G.A. Res. 151, U.N. GAOR, 42d sess., Supp. No. 49, at 292, U.N. Doc. A/42/49 (1987). Some of these
crimes were incorporated into the Rome Statute. See, e.g., Rome Statute, supra note 1, at arts. 8(2)(a)(iv), 8(2)(b)(xvii),
8(2)(b)(xviii), 8(2)(b)(xx). The 1907 Hague Regulations deem it prohibited to destroy or seize the enemy’s property,
unless such destruction or seizure be imperatively demanded by the necessities of war. See Regulations Respecting the
Laws and Customs of War on Land, annexed to the Convention Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land, art.
23(g), Oct. 18, 1907, 36 Stat. 2277. Although not explicitly mentioned, the natural environment can be considered to
constitute “property;” however, it is unclear whether the natural environment within the global commons would fall within
the notion of “property” since it is neither privately nor nationally owned. For a review of other internationally negotiated
provisions which might provide ancillary protection to the environment during wartime, see Richards and Schmitt, supra
note 7, at 1067-73. There are also some soft law agreements which may inform the content of international standards.
See World Charter for Nature, G.A. Res. 37/7 U.N. GAOR, 37th Sess., 48th plen. mtg. (1982), Principle 5 (“Nature shall
be secured against degradation caused by warfare or other hostile activities.”). See also Rio Declaration on Environment
and Development, UN Doc. A/CONF.151/5Rev.1, reprinted in 31 I.L.M. 874 (1992), Principle 24 (“Warfare is inherently
destructive of sustainable development. States shall therefore respect international law providing protection for the
environment in times of armed conflict and cooperate in its further development, as necessary.”). See also U.N. General
Assembly Resolution on the Protection of the Environment in Times of Armed Conflict, G.A. Res. 47/37 (November 25,
1992) (environmental considerations constitute one of the elements to be taken into account in the implementation of the
principles of the law applicable in armed conflict). The International Court of Justice has ruled that states “must take
environmental considerations into account when assessing what is necessary and proportionate in the pursuit of legitimate
military objectives.” See International Court of Justice, Legality of the threat or use of nuclear weapons, Advisory
Opinion (July 8, 1996), at & 30.
95. See also Drumbl, supra note 77, at 129-30, 133 (provides a more detailed discussion of these recommendations).
96. Austin and Bruch, supra note 15, at 39.
97. Id. at 41.
98. Environmental funds in the United States have also been proffered as potential precedents. These include Superfund,
the Oil Spill Liability Trust Fund, the Abandoned Mine Reclamation Fund, the Leaking Underground Storage Tank Trust
Fund, and the Black Lung Disability Trust Fund. Id.
99. Id. at 42.
100. By way of example, the Rwandan conflict was partly precipitated by demand for arable land. Over the past three
decades, average farm size has declined from two hectares per family to 0.7 hectares. On the relationship between
agricultural land-use and the Rwandan genocide. See Guenthar Baechler, Rwanda: The Roots of Tragedy, Battle for
Elimination on an Ethno-political and Ecological Basis, in Environmental Degradation as a Cause of War, Volume II,
461-502 (1996).
101. U.S. Const. amends. V, XIV ' 1.
102. 42 U.S.C. ' 2000(d) (1994).
103. Anthony D. Taibi, Comment, Environmental Justice, Structural Theory, and Community Economic Empowerment,
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (23 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]
9 St. John’s J. 491, 492 (1994).
104. Weintraub, supra note 4, at 568-69.
105. Lincoln L. Davies, Working Towards a Common Goal? Three Case Studies of Brownfields Redevelopment in
Environmental Justice Communities, 18 Stan. Envtl. L.J. 285, 287 (1999). A[L]ow-income and minority communities bear
the brunt of the industrialized world’s environmental contamination and are often the last groups to receive funding for
cleanups.” Id. at 288.
106. U.S. Const. Amends. V, (“[n]o person shall ... be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law;”
XIV ' 1 (applies to discriminatory actions taken by the states).
107. Civil Rights Act of 1964, Title VI, 42 U.S.C. ' 2000(d), ' 601 (“No person in the United States shall, on the ground
of race, color, or national origin be excluded from participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to
discrimination under any program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance”). See also Civil Rights Act of 1964,
Title VI, 42 U.S.C. ' 2000(d)(1), ' 602 (“Each Federal department and agency which is empowered to extend Federal
financial assistance to any program or activity ... is authorized and directed to effectuate the provisions of section 2000(d)
of this title ... by issuing rules, regulations, or orders of general applicability.”).
108. Pursuant to Civil Rights Act of 1964, Title VI, 42 U.S.C. ' 2000(d)(1), ' 602, the EPA adopted regulations which
state: AA recipient shall not use criteria or methods of administering its program which have the effect if subjecting
individuals to discrimination because of their race, color, national origin, or sex.” See 40 C.F.R. ' 7.35(b). This
prohibition would thus prevent intentional as well as disparate impact discrimination.
109. See Bean v. Southwestern Waste Management Corp., 482 F. Supp. 673 (S.D. Tex. 1979); Terry Properties, Inc. v.
Standard Oil Co., 799 F.2d 1523 (11th Cir. 1986); East Bibb Twiggs Neighborhood Ass’n v. Macon-Bibb County
Planning and Zoning Commission, 706 F. Supp. 880 (M.D. Ga. 1989); R.I.S.E., Inc. v. Kay, 768 F. Supp. 1144 (E.D. Va.
1991). The requirement to prove the defendant acted with discriminatory intent has been a major stumbling-block for
such claims. See Alice Kaswan, Environmental Laws: Grist for the Equal Protection Mill, 70 U. Colo. L. Rev. 387, 432
(1999).
110. Guardians Ass’n v. Civil Serv. Comm’n, 463 U.S. 582 (1983); New York City Environmental Justice Alliance v.
Giuliani, 50 F. Supp. 2d 250 (S.D.N.Y. 1999).
111. See Bradford C. Mank, Is There a Private Cause of Action Under EPA’s Title VI Regulations? The Need to
Empower Environmental Justice Plaintiffs, 24 Colum. J. Envtl. L. 1, 10-13 (1999).
112. New York City Environmental Justice Alliance v. Giuliani, supra note 110; South Bronx Coalition for Clean Air,
Inc. v. Conroy, 20 F. Supp. 2d 565 (S.D.N.Y. 1998).
113. 944 F. Supp. 413 (E.D. Pa. 1996), rev’d 132 F.3d 9925 (3d Cir. 1997), vacated, No. 97-1620, 524 U.S. 974 (1998).
114. Id. at 927.
115. Id.
116. The two permits granted for white areas covered facilities with a combined waste capacity of 1,400 tons per year,
whereas the five permits granted in African-American areas were for facilities with a combined waste capacity of over
2,100,000 tons per year. Id.
117. Id. at 415.
118. Id.
119. Chester Residents, 132 F.3d at 925.
120. Seif, 524 U.S. 915 (1998).
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (24 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]
121. Id. at 974 (1998).
122. Mank, supra note 111, at 50. In situations where the underlying controversy is independently removed, the normal
practice of the Supreme Court is to vacate the decision under appeal. Id. at 51-2.
123. Recent decisions have affirmed the existence of a private right of action to challenge administrative regulations on
the grounds of disparate impact. See, e.g., Powell v. Ridge, 1999 U.S. App. LEXIS 20092 (3rd Cir. 1999); Burton v. City
of Belle Glade, 178 F.3d 1175 (11th Cir. 1999); Sandoval v. Hagan, 7 F.Supp.2d 1234 (M.D. Ala. 1998).
124. One commentator has suggested that “[t]he Supreme Court seems likely to decide this vital issue.” See Mank, supra
note 111, at 6. Nonetheless, “environmental justice plaintiffs may not rely on the [Chester Residents] decision as
precedent in the Third Circuit or even cite it as a valid judgment in other circuits.” Id. at 51.
125. However, a recent decision of the Fourth Circuit Court of Appeals may dampen this promise. See Goshen Road
Environmental Action Team v. United States Department of Agriculture, 1999 WL 187264 (4th Cir. 1999) (siting a
wastewater treatment facility in a predominantly African-American neighborhood did not violate environmental justice
policy concerns).
126. See Exec. Order No. 12,898, 59 Fed. Reg. 7629 (1994). The Order provides that “each Federal agency shall make
achieving environmental justice part of its mission by identifying and addressing ... disproportionately high and adverse
human health or environmental effects of its programs, policies, and activities on minority populations and low-income
populations in the United States.” Id. Agencies are required to conduct programs which “substantially affect human health
or the environment” so as not to “subject[ ] persons to discrimination because of their race, color, or national origin.” Id.
However, the Order states that it is not intended to create a right of judicial review against the United States. Id.
127. By way of example, a “broad” civil rights investigation has been launched in response to claims that the
concentration of dozens of garbage transfer stations in the South Bronx discriminates against minority residents. See Paul
Zielbauer, Garbage Transfer Stations Face Civil Rights Inquiry, N.Y. Times (March 7, 1999) at A1. More specifically, the
investigation will Aseek to determine whether dozens of garbage transfer stations, and the hundreds of trucks that feed
them, have spawned widespread respiratory and other health problems that violate the civil rights of South Bronx
residents, the vast majority of whom [n.b. 95%] are black or Hispanic.” Id. Similar investigations had previously been
initiated in Michigan and Louisiana. Id.
128. Universal Declaration of Human Rights, U.N. G.A. Res. 217 (Dec. 10, 1948), art. 7 (“All are equal before the law
and are entitled without any discrimination to equal protection of the law. All are entitled to equal protection against any
discrimination in violation of this declaration and against any incitement to such discrimination.”).
129. International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 999 U.N.T.S. 171 (Dec. 16, 1966), art. 2 (“Each State Party ...
undertakes to respect and to ensure to all individuals within its territory and subject to its jurisdiction the rights recognized
in the present Covenant, without distinction of any kind, such as race, color, sex, language, religion, political or other
opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status.”), art. 26 (“All persons are equal before the law and are
entitled without any discrimination to the equal protection of the law. In this respect, the law shall prohibit any
discrimination and guarantee to all persons equal and effective protection against discrimination on any ground such as
race, color, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status.”).
130. International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, 5 I.L.M. 352 (1966), at arts. 2, 5
(State Parties guarantee the right of everyone, without distinction as to race, color, or national or ethnic origin, to equality
before the law ... in the enjoyment of the right to public health).
131. European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, 312 U.N.T.S. 221, as
amended (Nov. 4, 1950), art. 14 (“The enjoyment of the rights and freedoms set forth in this Convention shall be secured
without discrimination on any ground such as sex, race, colour, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or
social origin, association with a national minority, property, birth or other status.”).
132. American Convention on Human Rights, 9 I.L.M. 673 (November 22, 1969), art. 24 (“All persons are equal before
the law. Consequently, they are entitled, without discrimination, to equal protection of the law.”).
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (25 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]
133. Weintraub, supra note 4, at 564.
134. See, e.g., Bill Weinberg, War on the Land: Ecology and Politics in Central America 76 (1991) (A[In Nicaragua] the
rainforest was destroyed by campesinos who had been pushed from their land to make way for the ecologically disastrous
cotton industry, which relied heavily on pesticides and other inputs. While all Central American countries became a
>dumping ground= for dangerous pesticides, which are either restricted or banned in the countries where they are
produced, Nicaragua also became a testing ground for new experimental pesticides B with the Nicaraguan citizenry
serving as the guinea-pig@ [emphasis in original]). See also id. at 93; Ricardo A. Navarro, Environmental Impacts of the
Civil War in El Salvador, in Proceedings of the First International Conference on Addressing Environmental
Consequences of War: Legal, Economic and Scientific Perspectives (June 10-12, 1998); Bernard Q. Nietschmann, The
Effects of War and Peace on Nicaragua=s Environments, in Proceedings of the First International Conference on
Addressing Environmental Consequences of War: Legal, Economic and Scientific Perspectives (June 10-12, 1998)
(Abarrels of cyanide from gold mines were dumped in rivers to kill fish eaten by rebel supporters@); Alvaro José
Rodriguez, Environmental Impacts of the Internal Armed Conflict in Colombia, in Proceedings of the First International
Conference on Addressing Environmental Consequences of War: Legal, Economic and Scientific Perspectives (June
10-12, 1998) (discussing fumigation of agricultural lands where coca is allegedly grown, obliging peasants to move into
and clear-cut formerly pristine rainforest in order to cultivate subsistence crops). See also supra, note 35 (on Colombia).
135. See Weintraub, supra note 4, at 542-53. The notion of environmental cleansing recognizes how behavior directed
against the environment can readily constitute a threat to the security of people, demonstrating Athe increasingly
important role that environmental management plays in modern political relationships.” See id. at 536.
136. Id. at 564.
137. See, e.g., Rozelia S. Park, An Examination of International Environmental Racism Through the Lens of
Transboundary Movement of Hazardous Wastes, 5 Ind. J. Global Legal Stud. 659 (1998); Hugh J. Marbury, Hazardous
Waste Exportation: The Global Manifestation of Environmental Racism, 28 Vand. J. Transnat’l L. 251 (1995).
138. See Park, supra note 137, at 668-70. As a result, the cost of disposal in these developing countries for the polluter is
much lower than it would be were the disposal to occur in a developed country. See id. (“In 1989, in Africa, waste
disposal costs were about forty dollars per ton. In contrast, the cost was four to twenty-five times this amount in Europe
and in the United States, twelve to thirty-six times greater.”). See also Marbury, supra note 137, at 257-58, 260 (“Given
developing nations’ inexperience in handling hazardous waste and the large quantities of such waste generated each year,
the possibility of a major environmental disaster exists.”).
139. Park, supra note 137, at 660. See also Marbury, supra note 137, at 291 (“Hazardous waste exporting is just
environmental racism on a global scale. The main similarity between the two is who shoulders the burden of living near
and with the hazardous waste. Under each regime, the poor are forced to shoulder a disproportionate amount of national
and global burdens.”).
140. Basel Convention on the Control of Transboundary Movements of Hazardous Wastes and Their Disposal, March
22, 1989, 28 I.L.M. 657 (1989), amended by Conference Decision II/12 (March 25, 1994), adopted by the Third Meeting
of the Conference of the Parties to the Basel Convention, U.N. Environmental Programme, UNEP/CHW.3/35 (1995);
Bamako Convention on the Ban of the Import into Africa and the Control of Transboundary Movement of Hazardous
Wastes within Africa, opened for signature Jan. 29, 1991, 30 I.L.M. 773 (1991); The Fourth African, Caribbean, and
Pacific States-European Economic Community Convention of Lomé, opened for signature March 22, 1990, 29 I.L.M. 783
(1990). One problem which could be addressed by characterizing these shipments as a cognizable violation of the right to
environmental security is that the various conventions have “failed to coalesce into a single, dominant solution for the
externalities of hazardous waste exporting, which continue to be a vexing problem.” See Marbury, supra note 137, at
262.
141. See Popovic, supra note 23, at 68 (discussing the right to live as broader than the traditional concept of the right to
life).
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (26 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]
142. Declaration of the United Nations Conference on the Human Environment (Stockholm Declaration), U.N. Doc.
A/CONF.48/14, 11 I.L.M. 1416 (1972), Principle 1.
143. This has been one of the strengths of the environmental justice movement in the United States. See Taibi, supra note
103, at 491-92 (“[T]his movement comprises a number of discrete and mostly unaffiliated groups whose identity and
membership largely center on a particular location or issue. These groups are led by and draw their ranks not from
educated professionals but from the more typically politically alienated lower middle class.”). On the international level,
see Council of Europe, Convention on the Protection of the Environment Through Criminal Law, supra note 71, at art. 11
(parties may grant environmental non-governmental organizations the right to participate in criminal proceedings
concerning offenses under the Convention).
144. Popovic, supra note 23, at 89. See also id. at 88 (“A human rights mechanism would enhance the prospects for
protecting the environment because it would help the international community see the environmental impact of war from
the perspective of the most affected individuals and groups.”).
145. See, e.g., Philippe Cullet, Differential Treatment in International Law: Towards a New Paradigm of Inter-state
Relations, 10 E.J.I.L. 549, 577 (1999).
International Human Rights
http://www.nsulaw.nova.edu/student/organizations/ILSAjournal/6-2/Drumbl%206-2.htm (27 of 27) [4/16/2001 10:12:24 PM]