23 February 2004
George Norman*
Joel P. Trachtman**
Abstract
Customary international law is an enigma. It is produced by the decentralized
actions of states, and it generally lacks centralized enforcement mechanisms. Political
science realists and some rationalist legal scholars argue that customary international law
cannot affect state behavior: that it is “epiphenomenal.”
This article develops a model of an n-player prisoner’s dilemma in the customary
international law context that shows that it is plausible that states would comply with
customary international law under certain circumstances. These circumstances relate to:
(i) the relative value of cooperation versus defection, (ii) the number of states effectively
involved, (iii) the extent to which increasing the number of states involved increases the
value of cooperation or the detriments of defection, including whether the particular issue
has characteristics of a commons problem, a public good, or a network, (iv) the
information available to the states involved regarding compliance and defection, (v) the
relative patience of states in valuing the benefits of long-term cooperation compared to
short-term defection, (vi) the expected duration of interaction, (vii) the frequency of
interaction, and (viii) whether there are also bilateral relationships or other multilateral
relationships between the involved states.
One implication of this model is to lend credence to customary international law.
From a research standpoint, this model identifies a number of parameters for which data
may be developed in order to test the model. From a policy standpoint, this model shows
what types of contexts, including malleable institutional features, may affect the ability of
states to reach stable and efficient equilibria in their customary international law
relations.
* William and Joyce Cummings Professor of Entrepreneurship and Business Economics,
Tufts University.
** Professor of International Law, The Fletcher School of Law and Diplomacy, Tufts
University.
? George Norman and Joel Trachtman. All rights reserved. Preliminary draft. Please do
not cite or further circulate without the authors’ permission.
The Customary International Law Supergame:
Order and Law
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
1
1. Introduction
Customary international law (CIL) forms the infrastructure of international law,
and is also part of international law’s superstructure. It thus serves as its own foundation,
but also as the foundation for treaty law, and therefore for essentially all international
law. How firm is this foundation?
CIL seems to have fallen on hard times, as it has been overtaken by treaty as the
principal source of new rules in the international community, as it often seems to be used
by idealists to make boot-strapping arguments about the content of international law, and
as its binding force—its social effect—is often not readily apparent.1 This at a time when
the domestic analog of CIL—social norms—is the darling of legal scholarship.
CIL is under attack as behaviorally epiphenomenal and doctrinally incoherent.
By contrast, the central argument of this article is that CIL, while something of a trick of
levitation, is theoretically plausible. Our argument makes one central claim: that while
there are limits on and variations in the effectiveness of CIL, there are circumstances
where it may independently affect the behavior of states. There is no reason in theory, or
in data adduced by others, to believe CIL generally epiphenomenal. In addition, as a by-
product of the analysis supporting our central claim, we find that the CIL doctrine that
has developed in order to discriminate between valid and invalid assertions of the
existence of rules of CIL is internally coherent, and consistent with our model’s
rationalist perspective on state behavior.
1 See generally, J. Patrick Kelly, The Twilight of Customary International Law, 40 VA.
J. INT'L L. 449 (2000).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
2
This article refines and extends an emerging rationalist understanding of CIL.2
Pioneering work in this field, notably that of Jack Goldsmith and Eric Posner, has begun
to articulate a rationalist theory of CIL. Goldsmith and Posner have argued that CIL (a)
does not exogenously affect state behavior and (b) is internally incoherent, as states are
not motivated by opinio juris to comply with CIL.3 We show why the first assertion is
either tautological or incorrect as a matter of theory, and, to the extent that it purports to
rely on factual observation, is not supported by the data presented. The tautology arises
from a false dichotomy between motivation by self-interest4 and motivation by law. In a
rationalist model, behavior is assumed to be motivated by self-interest. If law is
artificially separated from self-interest, then of course a rationalist model would assume
that law has no motivating force. Yet we show how CIL rules may modify the payoffs of
behavior and therefore affect behavior through self-interest. While CIL is endogenous to
states as a group, it is an exogenous influence on the behavior of each individual state.
CIL may affect behavior even if it only does so at the margins. As to the second
assertion, our analysis provides a plausible basis to assign a discriminating role to opinio
juris, and therefore we find CIL doctrine internally coherent in at least its core dimension.
This article develops an iterated multi-player prisoner’s dilemma model of CIL.
Of course, game theory can only provide a crude representation of highly nuanced
decision-making.5 Our analysis focuses on parameters of the multi-player prisoner’s
dilemma in the CIL context: (i) the relative value of cooperation versus defection, (ii) the
number of states effectively involved, (iii) the extent to which increasing the number of
2 See, e.g., Mark A. Chinen, Afterword, 23 MICH. J. INT'L L. 201 (2001); Mark A.
Chinen, Game Theory and Customary International Law: A Response to Professors
Goldsmith and Posner, 23 MICH. J. INT'L L. 143 (2001); Vincy Fon & Francesco Parisi,
International Customary Law and Articulation Theories: An Economic Analysis, George
Mason Law and Economics Research Paper No. 02-24, available at
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=335220; Jack L. Goldsmith & Eric A.
Posner, Further Thoughts on Customary International Law, 23 MICH. J. INT'L L. 191
(2001); Jack L. Goldsmith & Eric A. Posner, A Theory of Customary International Law,
66 U. CHI. L. REV. 1113 (1999) [hereinafter Goldsmith & Posner 1999]; Andrew T.
Guzman, A Compliance-Based Theory of International Law, 90 CAL. L. REV. 1823
(2002); Francesco Parisi, The Formation of Customary Law, George Mason Law and
Economics Research Paper No. 01-06,
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=262032; Edward T. Swaine, Rational
Custom, 52:3 DUKE L.J. 559 (2002); Pierre-Hugues Verdier, Cooperative States:
International Relations, State Responsibility and the Problem of Custom, 42 VA. L. REV.
839 (2002).
3 The leading article here is Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2.
4 By “self-interest” we mean merely to refer to maximization of preferences—these
preferences could be other-regarding or altruistic.
5 See the cautions expressed in Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, and the broader
treatment in Duncan Snidal, The Game Theory of International Politics, in Kenneth A.
Oye, ed., COOPERATION UNDER ANARCHY (1986).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
3
states involved increases the value of cooperation or the detriments of defection,
including whether the particular issue has characteristics of a commons problem, a public
good, or a network, (iv) the information available to the states involved regarding
compliance and defection, (v) the relative patience of states in valuing the benefits of
long-term cooperation compared to short-term defection, (vi) the expected duration of
interaction, (vii) the frequency of interaction, and (viii) whether there are also bilateral
relationships or other multilateral relationships between the involved states.
The parameters we identify are incorporated in our model as independent
variables, but from a normative standpoint it is possible for policy initiatives to select or
manipulate these parameters. That is, by developing a positive theory suggesting the
parameters for determining whether CIL will affect state behavior, this article opens the
way to normative institutional design.6 States may determine to restructure certain
institutions in order to facilitate the formation and operation of CIL. There may be
circumstances under which it will be normatively attractive to facilitate the development
of CIL, rather than to engage in more self-conscious and static treaty-making. The
institutional dynamism and social immanence that attracts some scholars to social norms
in the domestic context may also be attractive in at least some international contexts.
This article is organized as follows. The remainder of this introduction provides a
short definition of CIL and briefly locates this article in relation to four literatures: law
and economics, social norms, international organization and industrial organization. Part
2 explains our choice of the iterated n-person prisoner’s dilemma as the basis for our
model, as well as our choice of an assumed strategy for players within this model. Part 3
explains the other assumptions and parameters of our model. Part 4 sets forth the formal
model. Part 5 presents some implications in terms of (i) the plausibility of CIL, (ii)
policy, (iii) international law doctrine, and (iv) research. Part 6 briefly concludes.
a. Customary International Law and its Doctrine
As an introductory matter, it is useful to review the fundamental definition of
CIL. Article 102 of the American Law Institute’s Restatement (Third) of Foreign
Relations Law states that “[c]ustomary international law results from a general and
consistent practice of states followed by them from a sense of legal obligation.” The
sense of obligation is referred to in Latin as “opinio juris sive necessitatis.” Article
38(1)(b) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice, listing the sources of
international law applicable by the Court, includes “international custom, as evidence of a
general practice accepted as law.”
CIL has two core doctrinal problems relating to opinio juris. First, can CIL ever
come into existence if it requires opinio juris—a sense of legal obligation—before it can
exist? The second relates to the motivation of states. Are states ever motivated by opinio
6 Daniel A. Farber, Positive Theory as Normative Critique, 68 S. CAL. L. REV. 1565
(1995).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
4
juris? The rationalist assumption of states motivated by their own preferences seems
prima facie inconsistent with the CIL requirement of motivation by opinio juris, and this
is the criticism that Goldsmith and Posner level at CIL doctrine.7 They argue that what
appears to be CIL is actually motivated by coincidence of interest, coercion, cooperation
predicated on self-interest, or coordination predicated on self-interest. We respond to this
argument in part 5.
For the social scientist studying law, the critical descriptive question relates to the
effects of legal rules on behavior. For CIL, this descriptive question is also a doctrinal
question, as CIL doctrine requires some level of generality and consistency of practice—
some quantum of state behavior. And again, at least under the Restatement formulation,
this behavior must be motivated by opinio juris. Under the Statute of the International
Court of Justice, the custom itself may serve as evidence of acceptance as law, of opinio
juris. Some commentators have suggested that opinio juris in a formal sense may not be
necessary at all, but that the requirement should be understood in terms of state consent
or acceptance.8
As we address the theory of CIL, it is useful to have in mind some examples of
CIL. CIL exists in a wide variety of fields, and coexists in many areas with treaty law.
As already noted, CIL is its own foundation. Thus, there is a CIL of CIL. In other
words, the CIL doctrine discussed above is understood as law pursuant to CIL.
Furthermore, the law of treaties came into existence pursuant to CIL, although this law is
today codified in treaty. But moving beyond these foundational areas, CIL addresses, for
example, issues of territorial integrity, jurisdiction to apply law, diplomatic immunity, the
rights of states with respect to coastal areas, human rights, cross-border pollution and the
use of force to settle international disputes.
These are diverse fields, each with its own characteristics. Our theoretical
approach calls for discrimination among these fields. The parameters for discrimination
are indicated by the model set forth below. Simply put, we would expect greater
possibility for formation of and compliance with CIL in some fields than in others. Of
course, this is an area in which empiricism would require analysis of areas in which CIL
has not developed: the dog that did not bark. Thus, we might ask, why is there no CIL
rule that prohibits over-fishing in international waters? Why is there no CIL rule that
requires extradition of criminals?
Our theoretical approach also accepts the possibility of linkage among diverse
fields, integrating and therefore homogenizing the behavioral effect of each rule of law.
b. Four Literatures
7 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2.
8 Maurice H. Mendelson, The Formation of Customary International Law, 272
RECUEIL DES COURS 155, 268-293 (1998).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
5
This article draws on four semi-autonomous literatures. First, as noted above,
there is an emerging rationalist, law and economics-based literature of CIL. The leading
work in this area is by Goldsmith and Posner, but there are other important contributions.
Second, this article draws on a burgeoning literature on social norms in the law, although
social norms are studied by all manner of social scientists. Third, this article draws from
the economics field of industrial organization analogies to game theory-based insights
about collusion among competitors in markets. Fourth, this article draws from the
political science literature of international organization, which has addressed in detail the
game theoretic analysis of cooperation among groups of states.
i. Law and Economics of CIL
Goldsmith and Posner provide a game theoretic analysis of CIL. They examine a
variety of CIL circumstances, and argue that they can be categorized into four game
types: (i) coincidence of interest, (ii) coercion, (iii) bilateral cooperation, and (iv)
coordination. This is a useful exercise, as it invites us to consider the motivation of
states, and the degree to which CIL affects behavior. In the perhaps hypothetical cases of
pure coincidence of interest and coercion, Goldsmith and Posner are correct that there can
be no opinio juris, and that law does little work. This is not new to CIL doctrine, but it is
useful to emphasize. It is also useful to emphasize that Goldsmith and Posner seem to
assume a purity of motivation that may not exist in the real world.
Goldsmith and Posner suggest that many instances of observed CIL may be
understood in terms of bilateral cooperation along the lines of a bilateral prisoner’s
dilemma game. They then argue that “Although game theory does not rule out the
possibility of n-state cooperation, the assumptions required for such an outcome are quite
strong and usually unrealistic. For this reason, we doubt the utility of n-player prisoner's
dilemmas as an explanation for multilateral or ‘universal’ behavioral regularities.”9 Their
views with respect to coordination games are similar.
In addition to developing this theoretical perspective, Goldsmith and Posner
examine several examples of CIL. The areas they consider are neutrality, diplomatic
immunity and maritime jurisdiction. They find that in these areas, states were motivated
by coincidence of interest, coercion or a bilateral reciprocity along the lines of the
prisoner’s dilemma. They conclude that if state behavior can be explained by
coincidence of interest or coercion, or any other self-interested-motivation, then neither
opinio juris nor CIL does any motivational work.
ii. Social Norms
We might ask, however, whether the CIL problem is different in structure from
the social norms context, and whether if social norms can affect behavior, CIL can as
9 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, at 1130.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
6
well. Since the publication by Robert Ellickson of Order Without Law10 in 1991, legal
scholars have examined the role of informal norms in society, and the relationship of
these norms to law. Ellickson investigates how cattle farmers in Shasta County,
California, manage to establish and apply their own non-legal rules, with a notable level
of compliance, without direct intervention by the state. It is an insightful story about how
order can arise without law, or in spite of law.11
We may draw a rough, and limited, analogy between the development of social
norms in a municipal, or private setting,12 and the development of CIL in the international
public setting. In the international community, CIL is substantively similar to the
phenomenon Ellickson describes.13 In international political science, regime theorists
such as Robert Keohane,14 Stephen Krasner, and Beth Simmons15 have told a similar
story of the possible rise of order in international society. However, regime theory has
generally avoided CIL.16 Moreover, recognition that a rule has become part of CIL may
signal its support by, or linkage with, the multi-sector CIL system. This system of
accepted and enforced linkage may distinguish legal rules from non-legal regimes.
The difference between law and social norms in the municipal setting is that law
is the province of the state (setting aside for the moment religious law, other non-state
rules, and circumstances in which non-state made rules are incorporated in the state-
enforced law).17 However, this distinction is inapposite to the international system,
which has been characterized as a horizontal, as opposed to vertical, system, where there
10 ROBERT ELLICKSON, ORDER WITHOUT LAW (1991).
11 However, one might argue that the general legal system, including especially its rules
against violence, forms an important background or infrastructure that may provide
support to the farmers' social norms.
12 For a recent work synthesizing and extending some of the social norms learning, see
ERIC A. POSNER, LAW AND SOCIAL NORMS (2000). See also Richard H. McAdams, Book
Review: Signaling Discount Rates: Law, Norms and Economic Methodology, 110 YALE
L.J. 625 (2001).
13 For an example of this type of analogical allegory, comparing domestic custom to
international custom, see Mendelson, supra note 8, at 165-168. For an early statement
that CIL is produced in an evolutionary fashion, see ANTHONY A. D'AMATO, THE
CONCEPT OF CUSTOM IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 104 (Cornell 1971).
14 See, e.g., ROBERT O. KEOHANE, AFTER HEGEMONY: COOPERATION AND DISCORD IN
THE WORLD POLITICAL ECONOMY (1984); ROBERT O. KEOHANE, INTERNATIONAL
INSTITUTIONS AND STATE POWER: ESSAY IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS THEORY (1989).
15 See, e.g., STEPHEN D. KRASNER, INTERNATIONAL REGIMES (1983); Stephen D.
Krasner & Beth Simmons, Theories of International Regimes, 41 INT’L ORG. 491 (1987).
16 Duncan Snidal, Political Economy and International Institutions, 16 INT'L REV. L. &
ECON. 121, 124 (1996).
17 While there is no state at the global level, there is an international legal and
organizational order, which is quite a bit more fragmented than most nation-states.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
7
is no overarching state, per se.18 So, in the international system, there is more overlap,
and an indistinct border, between law and social norms. This overlap is perhaps easier to
see in the international context than in the domestic context, as, in the international
context, a significant subset of social norms is termed "law."
Ellickson states that the social norms literature defines a “social norm” as “a rule
governing an individual’s behavior that third parties other than state agents diffusely
enforce by means of social sanctions.”19 The focus of this definition on decentralized
means of enforcement shows the strong analogy between social norms in the municipal
setting and CIL in the international setting. Of course, to the extent that courts may
apply, and institutions of global governance may enforce, CIL, there is a difference. But
this application and enforceability is quite limited. There are few circumstances in which
CIL rules benefit from mandatory adjudication in international tribunals. We would not
consider application of CIL by domestic courts to amount to the action of “state agents”
at the international level, although action by domestic courts would certainly be
considered action of “state agents” at the municipal level. This is because in the
international context, domestic courts are simply internal deliberative processes of
national governments. The application by domestic courts of CIL may be understood as
a kind of norm internalization.20
One important set of explanations of social norms understands norms as
preferences that individuals (or in our case states) acquire through education,
acculturation or other processes, such as an expressive or articulation function.21 Elster
states that “social norms provide an important kind of motivation for action that is
irreducible to rationality or indeed to any other form of optimizing mechanism . . . .”22 It
18 We add this qualification, because one might argue that the CIL and conventional law
framework, as it exists, is at least comparable to a municipal state, or at least that this
framework is comparable to the constitution that a municipal state might have. Of
course, while it responds to some of the same questions, including a rule of recognition, it
is not as detailed or fertile as a constitution.
19 Robert Ellickson, The Evolution of Social Norms: A Perspective from the Legal
Academy, in SOCIAL NORMS 35 (Michael Hechter & Karl-Dieter Opp eds., 2001). Note
that Ellickson assumes multilateral, as opposed to bilateral, retaliation.
20 See Harold Hongju Koh, Why Do Nations Obey International Law?, 106 YALE L.J.
2599 (1997) (reviewing Abram Chayes & Antonia Handler Chayes, THE NEW
SOVEREIGNTY: COMPLIANCE WITH INTERNATIONAL REGULATORY AGREEMENTS (1995)).
This internalization may be desirable under certain circumstances, and may be developed
as a tool of enforcement of CIL. That is, states may persuade one another to harness their
domestic legal system for certain of their international legal obligations, effectively
holding the domestic legal system hostage. See also Philip Moremen & Joel P.
Trachtman, Whose Right is it Anyway? Private Parties in EC-U.S. Dispute Settlement at
the WTO, 44 HARV. INT’L L. J. 221 (2003).
21 See Robert D. Cooter, Expressive Law and Economics, 27 J. LEG. STUDS. 585 (1998).
22 JON ELSTER, THE CEMENT OF SOCIETY 15 (1989).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
8
may well be possible to modify preferences of states through social norms. It seems
obvious that the way to modify the preferences of states is to modify the preferences of
individual government officials, or voters. Indeed, it may be appropriate to consider
epistemic communities and networks among government officials. While this approach
may have traction in the CIL setting, and may re-emphasize the role of legitimacy, justice
and morality as bases for preference-modification, this article will bypass that discussion,
and focus on exogenous explanations of social norms.23 Modeling always involves
simplification, and our goal in this paper is to elaborate a rationalist model for future
testing. In fact, testing a rationalist model would help to clarify the debate between
exogenous preferences and endogenous preferences.
In connection with exogenous explanations, the law-based social norms literature
has not embraced the iterated n-person prisoner’s dilemma.24 This is due to two types of
concerns. First, there are concerns that game theory does not reflect the nuance of social
interaction. We hope that the incorporation in our model of multi-issue contact helps to
address this concern. Second, there are concerns about individual rationality: the
subgame perfection of third-party enforcement.25 We address these concerns below.
iii. Industrial Organization
Much of our understanding of the utility, structure and dynamics of n-player
prisoner’s dilemma games comes from the economics literature of industrial
organization. This literature considers the possibility that firms may enter into cartels or
other restrictions of competition that violate antitrust laws. While firms may find
opportunities to communicate, their communications and agreements must be kept secret
from the regulatory authorities and are not enforceable at law. An important concern for
industrial organization economists is to identify circumstances under which such
agreements can be made self-sustaining through the self-interest of the parties to the
agreement.
23 Robert D. Cooter, Do Good Laws Make Good Citizens? An Economic Analysis of
Internalized Norms, 86 VA. L. REV. 1577 (2000); Robert C. Cooter, Models of Morality
in Law and Economics: Self-Control and Self-Improvement for the “Bad Man” of
Holmes, 78 B.U. L. REV. 903, 911-912 (1998); JON ELSTER, THE CEMENT OF SOCIETY: A
STUDY OF SOCIAL ORDER (1989). Basu refers to these as “preference-changing norms.”
See Kaushik Basu, Social Norms and the Law, 3 THE NEW PALGRAVE DICTIONARY OF
ECONOMICS AND THE LAW 476 (1998).
24 See Paul G. Mahoney & Chris William Sanchirico, Norms, Repeated Games, and the
Role of Law, 91 CAL. L. REV. 1281, 1284 (2003). Mahoney and Sanchirico explain the
state of the social norms literature with respect to the n-person prisoner’s dilemma. They
explain that the objection to these models is that third party enforcement is not
individually rational: that the incentives of the players break down.
25 Id. at note 12, citing work by Ellickson, Katz, McAdams and Posner.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
9
While the analogy is apparent, we must recognize, of course, that in the CIL
setting, public communication is possible, as are agreements that at least purport to be
binding: treaties. The degree to which agreements may actually constrain behavior is a
question for another paper, but we point out that the international legal rule that treaties
must be observed (pacta sunt servanda) is itself part of CIL.
Another, perhaps more important, distinction is that a cartel has certain
characteristics that may differ from any particular CIL setting. That is, in a cartel, the
more others adhere to the cartel, the greater the monetary incentives for any particular
member to defect. This context is more like a commons problem than like a public good
problem. We will discuss some of these distinctions based on payoff structures below.
iv. International Organization
Political scientists and economists working in the field of international
organization have made a good deal of progress in analyzing the problem of international
cooperation more generally. In various works, they have examined most of the
parameters that we utilize here.26 This literature has not examined CIL.
We have structured our model to match most closely the CIL context, rather than
attempt to structure a model that would address other international cooperation devices.
However, we recognize that the question of which device—treaty, CIL or softer law—
itself depends on a set of variables. We also recognize that CIL may be understood as a
phase in the formalization of law, or in “legalization.”27 CIL is often codified by the
International Law Commission of the United Nations, and CIL often forms the basis for
treaties. This article does not present an explanation of choice between custom and
treaty, or of the relationship among these instruments.28
26 There is disagreement between institutionalists and “realists,” who claim that states’
interests in international relations are characterized by a search for relative gains, rather
than absolute gains. These realists reject the possibility of cooperation where it results in
relative gains to a competitor. See Marc Busch & Eric Reinhardt, Nice Strategies in a
World of Relative Gains: The Problem of Cooperation under Anarchy 37 J. CONFL. RES.
427 (1993); Robert Powell, Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations
Theory, 85 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 1303 (1991); Duncan Snidal, Relative Gains and the
Pattern of International Cooperation, 85 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 701 (1991).
27 See the special issue of International Organization devoted to the phenomenon of
“legalization.” 54:3 INT’L ORG. (2000).
28 See Kenneth Abbott & Duncan Snidal, Hard and Soft Law in International
Governance, 54 INT’L ORG. (2000); John K. Setear, Treaty, Custom, Iteration and Public
Choice, February 2004, available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=492604 (arguing that custom
is more attractive to executive branches). To the extent that CIL is less detailed—less
specific—than treaty norms, it is amenable to a rules versus standards type of analysis.
See Louis Kaplow, Rules versus Standards: An Economic Analysis, 42 DUKE L.J. 557,
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
10
The model we present here formalizes certain considerations that remain informal
in much of the political science literature, and has other varying features that we describe
below.
2. The N-Person Prisoner’s Dilemma
In this section we explain our choice of the n-person prisoner’s dilemma as the
basic model for the CIL problem, examine the potential strategies that might be played
within this game, and explain some of our assumptions. The n-person iterated prisoner’s
dilemma is really a group of varying models, with a number of varying features,
including the number of players and their preferences.
a. Choice of Game
As we consider the application of game theory to the CIL setting, it should be
noted that there is a wide choice of potential game structures to apply.29 The basic payoff
structure assumed in the prisoner’s dilemma game captures the essential problem of
cooperation in a horizontal social setting with externalities,30 in which parties have a
choice between compliance and defection under circumstances in which they can enrich
themselves individually through defection while they could enrich society through
compliance.31 Of course, some CIL contexts might be better modeled using other
577 (1992); Joel P. Trachtman, The Domain of WTO Dispute Resolution, 40 HARV. INT'L
L.J. 333, 346-47 (1999).
29 For a useful analysis of the “fit” of other games, including “battle of the sexes” and
“stag hunt,” see Swaine, supra note 2. See also Fiona McGillivray & Alastair Smith,
Trust and Cooperation Through Agent-Specific Punishments, 54 INT'L ORG. 809, 810
(2000) (noting that the prisoner’s dilemma is often used to model international
cooperation).
30 By use of the term “externalities,” we mean to be quite inclusive, including both
pecuniary and non-pecuniary externalities: any circumstance in which an action by one
state has adverse or beneficial effects on another state.
31 At another level of complexity, it would be possible to model the game of formation of
a CIL rule separately from enforcement. See James D. Fearon, Bargaining,
Enforcement, and International Cooperation, 52:2 INT’L. ORG. 269 (1998) (separating
the bargaining problem, modeled as a coordination game, from the enforcement problem,
modeled as a prisoner’s dilemma); Stephen D. Krasner, Global Communications and
National Power: Life on the Pareto Frontier, 43 WORLD POL. 336 (1991) (arguing that
many international issues are better modeled as coordination games). Fearon’s two stage
approach may be more appropriate to the treaty context than to the custom context.
Fearon points out that relatively large “shadows of the future” might inhibit bargaining to
achieve an initial coordination game agreement, while making the enforcement game
more tractable. In the CIL context, there is less natural separation, and there may even be
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
11
methods, but by using the prisoner’s dilemma we hope to capture the essence of informal
contracting under opposed interests.32
One of the reasons that we choose this game is because it allows us to
contextualize a number of insights and concerns that cannot easily be included in other
analytical models. For example, we believe that the n-person prisoner’s dilemma can
take account of a number of the diverse considerations often referred to together as
“reputation” or “reputational sanctions.”33 We also believe that the n-person prisoner’s
dilemma must be at the core of a rationalist explanation of the effectiveness of social
norms. Finally, we believe that the n-person prisoner’s dilemma offers parsimony: the
factors that it takes into account seem necessary, and there are no factors that seem
superfluous.
In a non-cooperative, single-play circumstance, with a standard prisoner’s
dilemma payoff structure, we would expect non-compliance.34 This is each player’s
dominant strategy, and a Nash equilibrium.35 This is because under the payoffs assumed
in the prisoner’s dilemma, each party is better off defecting, no matter what the other
party does. Therefore, under the rather restrictive assumptions of the true prisoner’s
dilemma, the parties each invariably choose the strategy that results in reduced individual
welfare, and reduced aggregate welfare, compared to the non-defecting strategy. This is
an inefficient outcome. By analogy, states playing the CIL game (assuming prisoner’s
dilemma-type payoffs) in a bilateral single-play setting would fail to form or comply with
a CIL rule that increased individual and aggregate welfare. Cooperation is strongly
dominated, and the unique Nash equilibrium is for both states to defect.36 The same is
true of a prisoner’s dilemma game repeated a finite number of times known in advance to
the players. Now the unique sub-game perfect equilibrium is for each player to defect in
each period. “A subgame perfect equilibrium is a strategy profile that induces a Nash
equilibrium in every subgame.”37
first mover advantages that would counteract the effect Fearon suggests. Finally, our
interest in this article is not so much in establishing CIL rules, as in enforcing them.
32 For a discussion of the use of coordination games to model certain types of
international contexts, see Barbara Koremenos, Charles Lipson, & Duncan Snidal, The
Rational Design of International Institutions, 55:4 INT’L ORG. 761, 774 (2001); Duncan
Snidal, Coordination versus Prisoner’s Dilemma: Implications for International
Cooperation and Regimes, 79:4 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 923 (1985).
33 See Guzman, supra note 2.
34 STEPHEN MARTIN, ADVANCED INDUSTRIAL ECONOMICS 98 (1993).
35 A “dominant strategy” is one which, no matter what the other player does, will
provide a higher payoff to the acting player. A “Nash equilibrium” is a set of “strategies
such that each player’s strategy is an optimal response to the other players’ strategies.”
DREW FUDENBERG & JEAN TIROLE, GAME THEORY 11 (1991).
36 Id. at 111.
37 M.J. OSBORNE, AN INTRODUCTION TO GAME THEORY (Oxford University Press, 2004).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
12
This conclusion is inescapable in theory, given the constraints of the game: by
definition, the outcome of the prisoner’s dilemma game is an inefficient strategic
equilibrium. This conclusion presents a normative goal: to modify the real world
circumstances so as to produce stable equilibria that are efficient. This is the major role
of CIL, and of international law generally.
Of course, in a world of effective third-party enforcement of agreements, the
response to the prisoner’s dilemma is clear: the parties enter into a binding agreement to
cooperate, thereby modifying the payoff structure and escaping the prisoner’s dilemma.
The prisoner’s dilemma assumes, however, that its prisoners are held separately and have
violated the law, so they cannot negotiate, reach or enforce a binding agreement.
In the CIL setting, there is no court of general mandatory jurisdiction nor any
publicly-appointed “policeman.” While we may draw analogies to the World Court and
the U.N., these institutions have substantial differences compared to domestic courts and
police. Therefore, we begin by assuming that there is no capacity to make agreements
that are binding. This is obviously a simplifying assumption. Our model is meant to
show that there are substitutes for formal binding agreements.
In the CIL game, there are five important distinctions from the assumptions of
non-cooperative game theory in general, and the prisoner’s dilemma in particular. First,
the players can communicate with one another, and can do so more readily today than
during the classical period of formation of CIL. Second, the players can enter into
treaties that are at least somewhat binding. Third, states play an iterated game with one
another with no defined end date, and so can respond at a later time to something done at
an earlier time. Updating of information and punishment are possible. Fourth, not only
is the narrow game characterized by a particular CIL rule, like the three-mile territorial
sea, but it is embedded in a dense fabric of relationships. Fifth, information regarding
compliance is often readily accessible; more so today, it would appear, than during the
19th century. Each of these distinctions alone may be sufficient to transform the game
into something quite different from the prisoner’s dilemma—while nothing resolves the
true prisoner’s dilemma, modifications may result in stable and efficient equilibria.
Indeed, it may be useful to use cooperative game theory to analyze some CIL
circumstances.38
As will be illustrated below, one of the more difficult types of multilateral
cooperation problem is a commons problem in which, as in the cartel context, incentives
to defect increase with the number of other states that comply. Where incentives to
defect increase with the number of players, we would expect the most severe challenge to
cooperation. Not all CIL contexts exhibit this characteristic.
38 For an application of cooperative game theory in the international context, see Daniel
G. Arce M. & Todd Sandler, A Cooperative Game Theory of Non-Contiguous Allies, 3 J.
PUB. ECON. THEORY 391 (2000) (applying cooperative game theory to international
security arrangements).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
13
Observation suggests that even certain commons problems, or other prisoner’s
dilemma-type circumstances, may achieve resolution despite theory. Elinor Ostrom
states that “[a] substantial gap exists between the theoretical prediction that self-
interested individuals will have extreme difficulty in coordinating collective action and
the reality that such cooperative behavior is widespread, although far from inevitable.”39
Ostrom cites considerable evidence regarding the amount and circumstances of
cooperation by individuals in n-person collective action problems. The evidence shows
that individuals contribute to the resolution of these problems in substantially greater
amounts than the standard prisoner’s dilemma model would suggest. Of course, much of
the evidence is obtained in circumstances where the assumptions of the prisoner’s
dilemma are violated—by allowing individuals to communicate, enter into agreements
and iterate play.
We do not deploy any data in this article. However, we advance a plausible
theory of potentially stable and efficient equilibria in the n-player prisoner’s dilemma,
and suggest some possible approaches to empirical testing.
b. Choice of Strategy
Within the prisoner’s dilemma, we must postulate a particular strategy for states
to play. There are many choices. We mention only three: tit-for-tat, grim trigger, and
penance.
i. Bilateral or Multilateral Retaliation
An important aspect of the structure of the game pertains to the ability to impose
sanctions in a discriminatory manner. States may have trouble discriminating in the
application of sanctions for several reasons. First, they may not be able to obtain
information regarding the author of the violation. This might occur, for example, with
respect to pollution at sea, or terrorist attack. Second, it may be costly for states to
respond in a discriminating way. For example, if the sanction involves trade barriers, the
sanctioning state must instruct its customs officers to discriminate among goods by
origin. Third, and most important, the relevant good being produced by cooperation may
be non-excludable. This would occur with the provision of public goods or the protection
of international commons. To the extent that states are unable to discriminate, their
retaliation, if any, must be multilateral, instead of bilateral. This obviously limits the
strategy that they are able to play and the relationships that they may enter into. Thus,
given that the strategies available to a state are “cooperate” or “defect,” there are at least
two possibilities that we need to consider in connection with a multilateral game:
39 Elinor Ostrom, Collective Action and the Evolution of Social Norms, 14:3 J. ECON.
PERSP. 137, 138 (2000).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
14
(i) Defection by state i against state j leads to punishment of i only by state j:
bilateral defection leads to bilateral punishment; or
(ii) Defection by state i against state j leads to punishment of i by all states:
bilateral defection leads to multilateral punishment.
We focus our analysis on (i) for three reasons. First, it makes the analysis simpler
without changing any of the qualitative conclusions. Second, multilateral retaliation
simply increases the incentives to comply over bilateral retaliation. Since (i) involves
milder punishment of defection than (ii), the conditions that support cooperation with
bilateral punishment under (i) will certainly support cooperation with multilateral
punishment under (ii). In other words, where multilateral punishment is possible, the
conditions that we identify below are sufficient but not necessary to support a multilateral
rule: any discount factor that supports a multilateral CIL rule with bilateral punishment
will also support such a rule with multilateral punishment. Third, there is some force to
the argument that (i) is a more plausible scenario than (ii) in most of the situations in
which the formulation of CIL is likely to be considered. Articles 42, 48 and 54 of the
International Law Commission’s Rules on State Responsibility40 generally prevent
retaliation by third states for truly bilateral injury, while there seems no basis for
retaliation by an injured state against non-injuring states. These rules seem to limit the
formal possibility for multilateral sanctions against truly bilateral defection.
Thus, in our model, we assume that retaliation is applied bilaterally—that if state i
defects vis-à-vis state j, only state j will respond, and only against state i. If multiple
states responded against state i, it would simply make cooperation more likely by
increasing the punishment for defection.
Given (i), we can represent a multilateral prisoner’s dilemma game as a set of
bilateral games, with a typical bilateral game being as specified in Table 1 (page 29). As
will be seen below, this is not the same as assuming a bilateral game. Rather, it is a
multilateral game with bilateral punishment.
ii. Tit-for-Tat
Under “tit-for-tat,” states may respond to defection with a single defection. Tit-
for-tat is one of the most frequently-discussed strategies in connection with iterated
prisoner’s dilemmas. While tit-for-tat may win evolutionary games,41 it is not subgame
40 Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, in Report of
the International Law Commission on the Work of Its Fifty-third Session, UN GAOR,
56th Sess., Supp. No. 10, at 43, UN Doc. A/56/10 (2001), available at
<www.un.org/law/ilc>, subsequently noted by the General Assembly in A/RES/56/83,
Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts, adopted 12 Dec. 2001. These
articles do not themselves represent international law, but are an attempt to codify
existing custom.
41 See ROBERT AXELROD, THE EVOLUTION OF COOPERATION (1984).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
15
perfect: after a defection, the wronged state will have incentives to accept an undertaking
from the defecting state that it will cooperate in future. Subgame perfection means that at
every stage of an iterated game, no player will have an incentive to deviate from the
equilibrium strategy, even when others do. Even more devastating to tit-for-tat is the fact
that once one state defects the game cycles endlessly between defection and
compliance.42
iii. Grim Trigger
Second, states may respond to defection with defection forever: a bilateral “grim
trigger” strategy. There are two basic approaches that have been developed in the theory
of repeated games. The first assumes that any deviation is met with a response that
maximizes the loss that the deviator suffers – a “minmax” strategy – even if this imposes
costs on the punishers. The second approach assumes that deviation results in reversion
to the one-shot Nash equilibrium of the prisoner’s dilemma game. We adopt the latter
approach since it appears to be more appealing to players. Essentially, we assume that in
the event of deviation the states revert to the strategies that they would have adopted if no
CIL rule had developed in the first place. The grim trigger strategy is subgame perfect,
as it calls for a reversion to the dominant strategy of defection in response to an initial
defection.
Goldsmith and Posner appear to recognize the possibility for stable and efficient
equilibria under certain circumstances where states play the grim trigger strategy.43
However, using an overfishing of commons context as their example, they suggest that
the grim trigger is not used and would be collectively irrational. In his interesting work
on treaties relating to environmental commons problems,44 Barrett also rejects the grim
trigger strategy because it fails to satisfy the criterion of collective rationality. The
collective rationality consideration is a formal articulation of an intuitive concern that it
would be extraordinarily wasteful to abandon an efficient multilateral agreement because
of a single defection. While it would be individually rational to respond with defection
forever—it is subgame perfect as the reversion to the Nash equilibrium—it is collectively
irrational insofar as rational negotiators will have incentives to renegotiate a cooperative
arrangement after defection.
With respect to the more empirical question of whether a grim trigger is used, if
we think not about the CIL that exists, but about the CIL that does not exist, it is clear
that states do play the grim trigger strategy at least in some contexts. In fact, one might
argue that the multilateral grim trigger is the existing default strategy in CIL. That is,
where a CIL rule exists or is proposed for formation, and one state deviates, that may be
42 Id., at 138.
43 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, at 1129-1130.
44 Scott Barrett, A Theory of Full International Cooperation, 11 J. THEORETICAL POL.
519 (1999); SCOTT BARRETT, ENVIRONMENT AND STATECRAFT: STRATEGIES OF
ENVIRONMENTAL TREATY-MAKING (2003).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
16
sufficient provocation to cause others to deviate forever in response: to kill the rule
multilaterally.
The theoretical problem with grim trigger is that because it is collectively
irrational it is not “renegotiation-proof.”45 That is, after a defection, a coalition of states
will have incentives to come together and cooperate with the defector, depriving the grim
trigger of credibility and therefore effectiveness. The reasoning is that equilibrium
strategies that enforce cooperative outcomes by the use of this type of punishment can be
undermined by the deviator offering to renegotiate, proposing that the punishment phase
be abandoned in favor of a return to cooperation: a “let bygones be bygones” argument.46
An obvious counterargument to this, of course, is that renegotiation unravels by “forward
induction.” That is, once the players understand that defection and promises of future
compliance will go on indefinitely, would they not decline to renegotiate the first time?
Also, in the CIL context, we are operating on the assumption that states do not have the
possibility of forming binding agreements through renegotiation, preventing this
indefinite defection. 47
Nevertheless, there may be circumstances in which such renegotiation is possible,
and the offer to renegotiate and abide by the results is credible. If so, an alternative
“renegotiation-proof” equilibrium is needed. We offer the penance strategy described
below as a “weakly renegotiation proof” alternative.
iv. Penance
While a precise definition of renegotiation-proofness has not yet been agreed, the
treatment by Farrell and Maskin is worth considering.48 They define a “weak
renegotiation proof” (WRP) equilibrium for an infinitely repeated game to be a subgame
perfect equilibrium strategy profile that is not Pareto-dominated by any other subgame
perfect strategy profile. Using this definition, the grim trigger strategy profile is not
WRP, since after defection the payoffs to cooperation Pareto-dominate those of
punishment. If renegotiation is possible and credible, the states will prefer to renegotiate
after a defection.
45 See, e.g., Joseph Farrell & Eric Maskin, Renegotiation in Repeated Games, 1 GAMES
& ECON. BEHAVIOR (1989); Fudenberg & Tirole, supra note 36, at 174.
46 Indeed, this is not uncommon in international law discourse. See, e.g., Scott M.
Sullivan, Changing The Premise Of International Legal Remedies: The Unfounded
Adoption Of Assurances And Guarantees Of Non-Repetition, 7 U.C.L.A. J. INT’L L. &
FOR. AFF. 265 (2002-2003).
47 Barrett notes that collective rationality is less of an issue in the field of domestic
antitrust law, because renegotiation of an agreement in restraint of trade is illegal.
Barrett, supra note 44, at 11.
48 Farrell & Maskin, supra note 45.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
17
“Penance”49, by contrast, is subgame perfect and is “weakly renegotiation-
proof.”50 Under penance, the response to defection is counter-defection that is continued
until the original defector accepts a period of punishment after which all players return to
cooperation. That is, in the event of defection, the victim retaliates by defecting until the
initial defector accepts a period of punishment, by cooperating while the victim defects.
A form of penance seems to be endorsed by the International Law Commission of
the United Nations for application in international law generally. Articles 49 to 54 of the
Articles on State Responsibility provide that countermeasures may be used only to induce
a state to cease a wrongful act and to make reparations;51 they must be commensurate
with the injury.52
v. Equilibrium Selection and Coordination
One of the problems in an n-player prisoner’s dilemma is identifying the strategy
that other players are playing and coordinating on a single strategy. Fudenberg and
Tirole conclude: “Thus, repeated play with patient players not only makes
‘cooperation’—meaning efficient payoffs—possible, it also leads to a large set of other
equilibrium outcomes. Several methods have been proposed to reduce this multiplicity of
equilibria; however, none of them has yet been widely accepted, and the problem remains
a topic of research.”53 Under circumstances of multiple equilibria, “anything that tends to
focus the players’ attention on one particular equilibrium, in a way that is commonly
recognized, tends to make this the equilibrium that the players will expect and thus
actually implement.”54 While there is no formal solution to this problem, states may
coordinate through diplomacy, through other communication, or through their actions
advancing particular customary rules. The selection among multiple equilibria may be
understood as a separate, coordination game. Here, CIL, for example as reflected in the
Rules of State Responsibility, may also play a role.
3. Assumptions Within the N-Player Prisoner’s Dilemma
49 See Fudenberg & Tirole, supra note 36, at 179-182. “Penance” is sometimes referred
to as “getting even.” See ROGER B. MYERSON, GAME THEORY: ANALYSIS OF CONFLICT
326-27 (1991).
50 Fudenberg & Tirole, supra note 36, at 180, citing Farrell & Maskin, supra note 45, at
327; Eric van Damme, Renegotiation-Proof Equilibria in Repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma,
47 J. ECON. THEORY 206 (1989).
51 See The Chorzow Factory Case, 1928 P.C.I.J., Ser. A, Nos. 7, 9, 17, 19 (obligation to
make reparations).
52 See David J. Bederman, Counterintuiting Countermeasures, 96 AM. J. INT’L L. 817
(2002).
53 Id. at 112.
54 Myerson, supra note 49, at 371.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
18
Having selected the n-person iterated prisoner’s dilemma game, and the penance
or grim trigger strategy, in this section, we develop the more specific parameters and
assumptions of our model.
a. Efficiency and Symmetry
We assume that failure to reach a cooperative equilibrium—failure to reach an
implicit agreement—is inefficient. Of course, there are many circumstances in which no
implicit agreement is needed, and reaching one would be inefficient. However, our goal
is to examine strategic barriers to implicit agreement; reducing these barriers would
always increase efficiency, just as reducing the general barriers to contract between
private parties would always increase efficiency without requiring that parties contract in
every circumstance. This perspective is consistent with the first theorem of welfare
economics, the Coase Theorem, and the “efficiency principle”: “If people are able to
bargain together effectively, and can effectively implement and enforce their decisions,
then the outcomes of economic activity will tend to be efficient (at least for the parties to
the bargain).”55 If the barriers to bargaining are eliminated, and parties reach no bargain,
we may assume that there was no Pareto improving bargain available.
So, we assume payoffs along the lines of the classic prisoner’s dilemma. Even
within this category, there is variation. Some circumstances will be more like a commons
problem, or a cartel, in which the greater the number of players that comply, the greater
the incentives to defect. Others will be the opposite, based on network effects, public
goods or economies of scale: the more players that comply, the greater the incentives to
comply. In other cases, the payoffs from defection may not be substantially greater than
the payoffs to compliance.
Different players may be affected differently by defection or compliance.
Certainly in the CIL field there are notable cases of asymmetry. For example, a state
with an extensive diplomatic service will have more at stake in connection with a rule of
diplomatic immunity. A land-locked state may have a different perspective on the
territorial sea than a state with extensive coastlines. Asymmetry affects each state’s
incentives to comply. Linkage among varying issues may either increase or decrease
asymmetry.56
b. Identity and Number of Players
55 PAUL MILGROM & JOHN ROBERTS, ECONOMICS, ORGANIZATION AND MANAGEMENT
24 (1992).
56 While our model deals with games in which information is common knowledge,
Parisi develops the Harsanyian concept of stochastic symmetry and role reversibility: the
longer the shadow of the future, the less any one state can be certain of the way in which
it will be affected by a particular rule See Parisi, supra note 2. See also, Robert O.
Keohane, The Demand for International Regimes, 36:2 INT’L ORG. 325 (1982).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
19
The skepticism of prior work regarding the possibility for non-defecting
multilateral equilibria even in non-cooperative games is misplaced. The industrial
organization literature recognizes important possibilities for cooperative outcomes in
multilateral settings. The same seems to apply to the CIL game.
The number of players in any particular instance of the CIL game will vary. The
maximum number of players is the total number of states in the world, although even this
may ignore some detail. There are other players besides states, including sub-state
governmental entities, international government entities, non-government organizations
and individuals, so we have a potentially unlimited universe. In this paper, we assume
“billiard ball” states. While we recognize that we lose nuance by doing this, we are
trying to work with a simple model that assumes that states have unitary preferences.
Even limiting our universe to states, with approximately 200 in the world, there
would seem to be a significant problem of obtaining information about positions and
practices, as well as coordination. However, while states may possess formal sovereign
equality, they are not substantively equal, and their participation in the CIL formation
process is not homogeneous.57
Oscar Schachter writes that “As a historical fact, the great body of CIL was made
by remarkably few States. Only the States with navies—perhaps 3 or 4—made most of
the law of the sea. Military power, exercised on land and sea, shaped the customary law
of war and, to a large degree, the customary rules on territorial rights and principles of
State responsibility.”58 This leaves us with a game in which the number of players varies,
depending on the degree of implication of their interests, and depending on their ability to
affect outcomes. In this game, players are heterogeneous across a number of parameters,
including interest and power, and as will be seen below, discount factors. In this sense,
we may think of powerful states engaging in the CIL formation and maintenance game as
exerting power through the articulation, formation and maintenance of CIL rules.
Schachter wrote of general CIL, but it is also possible to have regional or other
plurilateral CIL.59
57 See Lisa L. Martin, The Rational State Choice of Multilateralism, in
MULTILATERALISM MATTERS 91, 99 (John G. Ruggie, ed. 1993) (suggesting techniques,
including delegation as in the Security Council, of reducing the effective number of
players).
58 Oscar Schachter, New Custom: Power, Opinio Juris, and Contrary Practice, in Jerzy
Makarczyk, ed., THEORY OF INTERNATIONAL LAW AT THE THRESHOLD OF THE 21ST
CENTURY: ESSAYS IN HONOUR OF KRZYSZTOF SKUBISZEWSK, 531, 536 (Kluwer 1996).
See also Mendelson, supra note 8, at 194, 215, 225 (in the past, “civilized” states were
considered sufficient, and the applicable group of states need not be geographically
constrained).
59 See Asylum Case (Haya de la Torre), 1950 I.C.J. 266; Case Concerning the Right of
Passage Over Indian Territory, 1960 I.C.J. 6. Cf. MALCOLM N. SHAW, INTERNATIONAL
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
20
“Number of actors refers to the actors that are potentially relevant to joint welfare
because their actions affect others or others’ actions affect them.”60 The number of
players may vary widely, depending on the subject matter at issue, the preferences of
states that are implicated, the information dynamics, the ability of states to organize to
influence the development of legal rules, and other parameters. There will also be wide
asymmetries of interest that reduce the effective number of players. Small states would
ordinarily find it futile to try to influence the development of norms that interest large
states, unless the small states are able to form a coalition to press their interests. So, as
we consider the number of players, we will make some simplifying assumptions.
Some of the leading authors in this field are skeptical of the possibility for
multilateral customary processes to result in stable and efficient strategic equilibria under
circumstances other than pure self-interest or coercion. For example, Goldsmith and
Posner see little possibility for either coordination or cooperation (the term they use for
resolution of a prisoner’s dilemma) in multilateral settings.61 While they see the
possibility for stable and efficient equilibria in certain bilateral settings, they assume that
"the bilateral prisoner's dilemma cannot in any event be generalized to the situation of
multilateral cooperation, which is such an important part of the traditional account."62 In
this connection, they follow an established tradition, led by Mancur Olson in 1965:
[U]nless the number of individuals in a group is quite small, or unless there is
coercion or some other special device to make individuals act in their common
interest, rational, self-interested individuals will not act to achieve their common
or group interests.63
Olson based his perspective on the assumptions that the benefit of cooperation
declines with the number of players, that the costs of monitoring increase with the
number of players, and that the costs of organizing retaliation increase with the number
of players.64 However, it can readily be seen that these are conjectures about the world,65
and are not necessarily true of any particular circumstance. Moreover, these are only a
subset of the parameters worth considering. Finally, technological and social change has
LAW 72-73 (4th ed. 1997); Edward T. Swaine, The Local Law of Global Antitrust, 43 WM.
& MARY L. REV. 627, 706-25 (2001).
60 Koremenos, Lipson & Snidal, supra note 32, at 777.
61 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, at 1132.
62 Id.
63 MANCUR OLSON, THE LOGIC OF COLLECTIVE ACTION 2 (1965). See also Kenneth A.
Oye, Explaining Cooperation Under Anarchy: Hypotheses and Strategies, in
COOPERATION UNDER ANARCHY (Kenneth A. Oye, ed. 1986).
64 Olson, supra note 63, at 48.
65 RUSSELL HARDIN, COLLECTIVE ACTION 43 (1982).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
21
made it easier in some circumstance to monitor and to organize retaliation.66 Our model
provides a broader context in which to consider these, and other, parameters.
Oye identifies three slightly different ways in which increasing the number of
players reduces the likelihood of cooperation: (i) increasing transaction costs, (ii)
increased heterogeneity of discount factors67 among larger numbers of players, and (iii)
the second order collective action problem, suggesting that players would not retaliate
against a defector.68 The transaction cost problem, compared to transaction benefits, with
increasing numbers of players is merely a conjecture and seems to be countervailed by
the possibility of economies of scale and scope. The second order collective action
problem is based on the collective rationality issue discussed above. With respect to
heterogeneous discount rates, much depends on the ability to discriminate among players,
and the degree of variation among players. Generally, cooperation would depend on the
discount rate of the least patient state, which would result in the possibility that states
with high discount factors (low discount rates) would find it useful to exclude states with
low discount factors from certain cooperative arrangements.
c. Information
The relative scale of information in the international system is somewhat different
from that in a municipal setting. That is, the cost of producing and distributing
information regarding state behavior may be a much smaller fraction of the utility of
cooperation in the international setting than it may be in municipal inter-firm contexts.
Furthermore, there are significant asymmetries among states in terms of the relative cost
and value of producing information. Epistemic communities among government officials
may play an important role in information transmission.
66 See Arthur Lupia & Gisela Sin, Which Public Goods are Endangered?: How
Evolving Communication Technologies Affect the Logic of Collective Action, 117 PUBLIC
CHOICE 315 (2003); Ronald B. Mitchell, Sources of Transparency: Information Systems
in International Regimes, 42 INT’L STUDS. Q. 109 (1998)..
67 A “discount factor” is a mathematical factor structured to reflect the degree of
patience of a player. It represents the present value today of a payoff in a future period.
A discount factor of 1 means that future payoffs are valued equally to present payoffs. A
discount factor of .75 means that future payoffs are valued at 75% of present payoffs. A
high discount factor indicates patience, while a low discount factor indicates impatience.
Discount factors should be contrasted with “discount rates” applied to future payoffs in
order to reduce them to a present value, where the discount factor equals 1/(1+r), with r
representing the discount rate. Therefore, discount factors are less than 1 (assuming a
positive discount rate). A low discount rate corresponds to a high discount factor. For
example, a discount rate of 10% would result in a discount factor of approximately 91%.
We discuss below the circumstances under which a state might be thought to have a high
or low discount factor.
68 Oye, supra note 63, at 18-19.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
22
There are significant differences between a bilateral game and an n-player game,
and between an n-player game with bilateral retaliation and one with multilateral
retaliation. Under bilateral retaliation, information problems are significantly reduced.
As stated above, our model assumes bilateral retaliation, but multilateral retaliation
would sustain cooperation in a wider range of circumstances.
Under multilateral retaliation, we are concerned about the ability of players to
find out about the compliance or defection history or characteristics of other players. On
the one hand, it may be costly for an individual to find out for himself the history of
many other players. On the other hand, the potential responses of many other players, if
engaged, may add to the disincentives for defection. There are economies of scale and
scope in this type of system, which may countervail increased information costs that exist
in an n-player setting.69
As Milgrom, North and Weingast argue with respect to the non-state institutions
that enforced compliance among early medieval merchants, “It is the costliness of
generating and communicating information—rather than the infrequency of trade in any
particular bilateral relationship—that, we argue, is the problem that the system of private
enforcement was designed to overcome.”70
Kandori explains that informal enforcement mechanisms fall into two categories:
those that use personal enforcement and those that use community enforcement. These
correspond to what we have been referring to as bilateral retaliation and multilateral
retaliation. Kandori examines circumstances in which social norms work to support
efficient outcomes in infrequent transactions—absent iteration that can allow personal
enforcement, but under circumstances where community enforcement may occur.71 This
differs somewhat from what we have assumed about the CIL context, but there may be
circumstances in which multilateral retaliation could substitute for iteration. Kandori
argues that “for a social norm to be sustainable, it must provide proper incentives to the
members in every respect.”72 Where members of a community can observe each other’s
behavior, community enforcement works in much the same way as personal
enforcement.73 Kandori assumes this is the case in small communities. We might
suggest that the global community can be understood as a small community in this sense.
CIL rules generally involve matters that are public knowledge and are reported in the
69 See Samuel Bowles & Herbert Gintis, The Moral Economy of Communities:
Structured Populations and the Evolution of Pro-Social Norms, 19 EVOLUTION & HUMAN
BEHAVIOR 3, 11-14 (1997).
70 Paul R. Milgrom, Douglass C. North and Barry R. Weingast, The Role of Institutions
in the Revival of Trade: The Law Merchant, Private Judges and the Champagne Fairs, 2
ECON. & POL. 1,3 (1990).
71 Michihiro Kandori, Social Norms and Community Enforcement, 59 REV. ECON.
STUDS. 63 (1992).
72 Id. at 64.
73 Id..
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
23
press. Imagine a municipal community where each individual’s behavior is subject to
journalistic and intelligence investigation.
Kandori assumes private information that is not shared among community
members. When observability is not perfect, private information regarding compliance
with a norm, as well as the distribution of the private information, will be more
complicated, and costly. Cooperation may be difficult to sustain because the community
may not have defined adequately the social norm or the determination and labeling of
defectors. Kandori shows, in theoretical terms, that even where an agent does not have
any direct information of other agents’ behavior vis-à-vis other members of the
community, cooperative behavior can sometimes be sustained. In the CIL game, with
seemingly greater relative ability to observe treatment of third parties compared to private
society, we would expect a greater basis for cooperation.
Of course, multilateral sanctions are dependent on information regarding
defection, and a judgment that the subject has violated the relevant norm. Information
may be a trivial problem in certain areas of CIL, but a difficult problem in others.
Various institutional responses are possible to provide greater certainty in judging
violations. Judgments can depend on individual state determinations, or on community
views, or consensus, which may be led by a “reputation entrepreneur” or other opinion
leader. On the other hand, it can be achieved through an independent institution such as a
court. And it must be recalled that in this type of setting, even a court’s views can be
criticized and challenged.
Unlike in the municipal setting, the international setting provides no system of
courts with broad mandatory jurisdiction. Milgrom, North and Weingast argue that third-
party dispute settlement can assist in developing cooperation. Third-party dispute
settlement can solve the following information problem. If two parties have a dispute, in
which one accuses the other of defection, how can other members of the community
determine whether the accusation is true?74 Third-party dispute settlement, along the
lines of the “law merchant,” may be more valuable to resolve information problems in the
municipal context among traders than in the international context among states. First,
there may be fewer states than there are potential traders in the medieval traders’ setting.
Second, again, the cost of information about state compliance may be a smaller
proportion of the value of CIL “transactions.” Milgrom, North and Weingast conclude
within the municipal context that, given the lack of empirical evidence about the costs of
running different kinds of institutions, it is not possible to develop a formal model to
show that their third-party dispute settlement minimizes information costs. However,
they opine that the system seems to incur only the kind of costs that are inevitable and
seems well-designed to minimize those costs.75
74 Milgrom, North & Weingast, supra note 70, at 8.
75 Id. at 15.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
24
The Milgrom, North and Weingast “law merchant” is a private purveyor of
information and evaluation. Its use is accepted by the players in order to develop an
efficient equilibrium. We might consider the extent to which formal international
institutions such as the International Court of Justice, the WTO’s dispute settlement
process or its Trade Policy Review Mechanism fill a similar role in connection with
states, and whether NGOs such as Amnesty International or the World Wildlife Fund, or
informal institutions such as the Basle Committee (bank regulation) or the Waasenar
Arrangement (export controls on dual use commodities), can do so in particular niches.
We assume perfect information in our model. This assumption is especially apt
given our assumption of bilateral retaliation. However, in order for multilateral
retaliation to operate, information problems must be overcome.
d. Patience/Discount Factors
In iterated prisoner’s dilemmas, theorists have shown that the degree to which
players value future payoffs will have an effect on players’ incentives to comply with a
norm. All things being equal, the extent to which the player values future payoffs will
determine the extent to which these future payoffs affect the player’s behavior.76
We represent the extent of valuation of future payoffs as a discount factor—a
factor used to reflect the present value of future payoffs. The discount factor reflects the
preference of the player for payoffs now versus payoffs in the future. We may
understand the discount factor as a central variable, which interacts with other variables
such as the per-period magnitude of future payoffs, the relative payoffs of defection
versus cooperation, the horizon or number of periods predicted, frequency of iteration,
the number of other players under multilateral retaliation, and multi-sector contact.
e. Horizon: Duration of Interaction
While it might be argued that the CIL game will continue infinitely, in order to
emphasize the role of patience, it is useful to assume that the game will be finite, but that
at any given time it is unknown when it will end. Thus, we assume a low probability that
the game will be short. At any given moment, there will be a long, but finite, horizon.
Public choice considerations would counsel that horizons vary. After all, if the
real interaction is not between states but between governments, we must recognize that
governments have varying effective horizons. Governments come and go. The
relationship between state and government horizons is to some extent determined by the
degree of accountability of the government—the degree to which it represents the
76 Of course, to the extent that players may exchange future payoffs for present payoffs,
the patience variable becomes less important, or less diverse. Thus, where efficient
capital markets allow for the exchange of future cash or non-cash payoffs for cash
payoffs, we would expect the patience variable to be constant across players. See
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
25
interests of the state. However, a democracy may have a shorter horizon than a
dictatorship. Some states may have more frequent or more imminent elections at
particular moments. Separately from the frequency or imminence of elections, we would
want to model the relative stability of the ruling party or coalition. Much depends on the
prospects for reelection, the stability of the dictatorship, and the stability of the
dictatorship’s policies, including their susceptibility to variation due to corruption.
Furthermore, it may be useful to examine whether the real actor is neither the state nor
the government, but a more entrenched bureaucracy. Transnational networks may have
greater durability than international networks. We combine this question of an individual
state’s or government’s time horizon with “patience.”
f. Iteration: Frequency and Continuity
Included in the set of assumptions underlying the prisoner’s dilemma is the
assumption of the isolation of the game under analysis. However, casual observation of
international society suggests that there are many linkages,77 with the result that few
issues can be isolated. Players can bind one another in a variety of ways, including by
linking the present game to other games in a “supergame.”
It is generally understood that a mutually beneficial outcome can exist as a
subgame-perfect equilibrium of the prisoner’s dilemma where the game is repeated,
subject to conditions relating to the players’ discount rates and the time horizon.78 The
reason is simple to see. With repeated play current actions can be conditioned on past
actions, introducing the possibility of rewarding cooperation and punishing defection.
Repetition of itself is not, however, sufficient to secure continued cooperation. If the
game is repeated a known finite number of times, both players will have an incentive to
defect in the final period, and the game unravels from there to immediate defection.79 By
contrast, if the game is repeated indefinitely, then “all players defect every period” will
remain a subgame perfect equilibrium, but there may be additional subgame perfect
equilibria, depending on the parties’ discount factors.80
77 See ROBERT KEOHANE, AFTER HEGEMONY 91 (1984); Ernst Haas, Why Collaborate?
Issue Linkage and International Regimes 32 WORLD POLITICS 357 (1980); Michael D.
McGinnis, Issue Linkage and the Evolution of International Cooperation, 30:1 J. CONFL.
RES. 141 (1986); Robert E. Tollison & Andrew D. Willett, An Economic Theory of
Mutually Advantageous Issue Linkage in International Negotiations, 33 INT’L ORG. 425
(1979). McGinnis shows formally that in a prisoner’s dilemma “multisupergame”
players may adopt strategies that create linkages across time and games, providing
opportunities for cooperation where cooperation would not be possible for isolated
games.
78 See ROGER B. MYERSON, GAME THEORY: ANALYSIS OF CONFLICT 308-369 (1991).
79 Fudenberg & Tirole, supra note 36, at 111.
80 Id.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
26
“The ‘folk theorems’ for repeated games assert that if the players are sufficiently
patient, then any feasible, individually rational payoffs can be enforced by an
equilibrium. Thus, in the limit of extreme patience, repeated play allows virtually any
payoff to be an equilibrium outcome.”81 Under circumstances of high discount factors,
when players are “patient,” the short-term gain from defection in one play is outweighed
by the aggregation of even small losses in all future periods. Fudenberg and Maskin
show that frequent transactions with the same partner, regardless of the number of
players, the number of strategies available, or the size of the payoffs, make it possible to
reach an equilibrium with efficient trading.82
g. Multi-Sector Contact
Firms, and states, operate in multiple markets and encounter other firms, or states,
in multiple contexts: as competitor here, as supplier there, as co-conspirator elsewhere.
Industrial organization economists studying the effect of multi-market contact have found
that this cross-sectoral activity may support cooperation. 83 “With multimarket contact
collusion can be viable in a set of markets even when in the absence of multimarket
contact it could not be supported in any of these markets.”84
81 Id. at 150.
82 Drew Fudenberg & Eric Maskin, The Folk Theorem in Repeated Games with
Discounting or with Incomplete Information, 54 ECONOMETRICA 533 (1986).
83 See, e.g., D.B. Bernheim & M.D. Whinston, Multimarket Contact and Collusive
Behavior, 21 RAND J. ECON. 115 (1990); Corwin Edwards, Conglomerate Bigness as a
Source of Power, in “Business Concentration and Price Policy,” NBER Conference
Report (Princeton University Press 1955); Hitoshi Matsushima, Multimarket Contact,
Imperfect Monitoring and Implicit Collusion, 98 J. ECON. THEORY 158 (2001); Giancarlo
Spagnolo, On Interdependent Supergames: Multimarket Contact, Concavity and
Collusion, 89 J. ECON. THEORY 127 (1999).
84 Spagnolo, supra note 83, at 128 (emphasis in original). Spagnolo shows that when
players have a concave objective function in respect of profits, inducing wealth effects
and therefore generating scale economies in cooperation, multi-market contact can
enhance cooperation. A concave objective function in this context arises from an interest
in smoother payoffs, and less interest in unusually high payoffs in any given period.
There are reasons why a political “manager” might also have a concave objective
function. See Edward D. Mansfield, Helen V. Milner, & B. Peter Rosendorff, Why
Democracies Cooperate More: Electoral Control and International Trade Agreements
56:3 INT’L ORG. 477 (2002) (modeling trade agreements as signaling and commitment
devices in the domestic context of democracies). In the international relations context, in
which executives play a two-level game, a concave objective function may arise from
accountability via elections, or in the trade context, from a desire to avoid disruption to
particular constituencies. This is Corden’s “conservative social welfare function.” W.M.
CORDEN, TRADE POLICY AND ECONOMIC WELFARE 107 (1974).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
27
“Multimarket contact allows firms to use the threat of a simultaneous punishment
in more markets, which is stronger than the sum of the independent punishments because
a firm being punished in one market has a higher marginal valuation of profits, therefore
it values more the losses from punishments in other markets.”85
One important difference between the commercial context and the international
relations context is that state relations in the international context almost always cross a
number of sectors.86 States relate to one another in a variety of contexts, with varying
roles in each context. Thus, in one context, State A may be concerned about the scope of
its territorial sea, while in another context it may be concerned about the scope of its
responsibilities to protect foreign diplomats. As a result, while there may be a “territorial
seas game” that is separate from the “diplomatic immunity game,” these games may be
linked. In fact, states regularly link issues in international relations,87 with the result that
it is not possible to establish precise boundaries of any particular game.
Defection in one area may have consequences in another, with the possibility of
cross-sectoral ostracism or other punishment. Thus, it is not enough to examine whether
states have sufficient incentives for compliance within a particular sector; one must also
analyze the effect of activity in other sectors.
Matsushima argues that multimarket contact can take the place of perfect
information as a basis for a stable equilibrium of implicit collusion. Matsushima shows
that with multimarket contact, cooperation can take place even under circumstances of
relatively low discount factors.88
This conclusion suggests that international cooperation in different sectors may be
mutually supportive, and that there may be a kind of network effect that makes each
additional instance of cooperation more attractive than it would be absent existing
instances.89 This game theoretic perspective provides support for the early neo-
functionalist hypotheses regarding international economic integration.90
Again, however, the possibility that the “real” actor is a subnational actor,91 such
as a bureaucracy with a limited sectoral mandate, may affect the possibility of effective
85 Spagnolo, supra note 83, at 133.
86 See Guzman, supra note 2, at 1869-1870; Snidal, supra note 32, at 939.
87 See note 77, supra.
88 Matsushima, supra note 83, at 164-65.
89 See Barbara Koremenos, Charles Lipson, and Duncan Snidal, The Rational Design of
International Institutions, 55:4 INT’L ORG. 761, 764-65 (2001).
90 See, e.g., ERNST B. HAAS, BEYOND THE NATION-STATE: FUNCTIONALISM AND
INTERNATIONAL ORGANIZATION (1968); Jeppe Tranholm-Mikkelsen, Neofunctionalism:
Obstinate or Obsolete? 20:1 MILLENIUM: JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL STUDIES 1 (1991).
91 See Anne-Marie Slaughter, The Real New World Order, 76 FOREIGN AFFAIRS 183
(1997).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
28
multi-sector contact. This may be a reason why assignment of broad international
relations authority to centralized ministries of foreign affairs may be useful. While as
argued by Downs and Jones,92 a particular state may have multiple reputations, within
multiple contexts, segmentation need not be complete, so that it may be that defection in
one context may have consequences within another context. Without further empirical
study, it is not possible to know how much segmentation exists in states’ reputations.
Such study would examine the extent to which different ministries within states, and
different “epistemic communities” on a transnational basis, communicate across sectors.
It is important to note, however, that particular segments, such as trade, environment or
arms control, have within them multiple relationships. Finally, it may be that
segmentation or reputation is efficient, allowing different parts of a national government
to take responsibility for their own relations, and to develop the kind of reputation that
maximizes returns within the relevant segment.
Furthermore, Downs’ and Jones’ argument is explicitly about treaty, not custom.
In a treaty setting, states might be understood as implicitly accepting only intra-treaty
remedies for breach. However, in the custom context, there is no explicit or implicit
limitation on responsive or remedial action. Therefore, it may well be that in this more
delicate and nuanced context, where there is no implicit consent to limitation, states
would consider themselves less constrained in their responsive or remedial action. In
addition, much responsive action in this informal setting is likely to take the form of
abstention from future transactions, rather than some form of punishment within the
context of the present transaction.
Milgrom, North and Weingast, examining the behavior of medieval merchants,
explain that “if the relationship itself is a valuable asset that a party could lose by
dishonest behavior, then the relationship serves as a bond. . . .”93 This shadow of the
future effect is intensified by multi-market contact and perfect information. The broader
this effect, the greater the likelihood that individual states will respect individual rules.
4. The CIL Supergame
Our discussion in parts 2 and 3 indicates that there are many possible assumptions
that we might make in developing a CIL supergame. As noted above, we choose to focus
on one such supergame – the iterated prisoner’s dilemma game – for two principal
reasons. First, this is a setting in which all of the relevant states prefer formation of and
compliance with a CIL rule to the other possible outcomes. Second, it is a setting in
which each state can gain from deviating from the cooperative outcome and in which
there are no centralized means to enforce any agreement not to deviate.
92 George W. Downs & Michael A. Jones, Reputation, Compliance and International
Law, 31 J. LEG. STUDIES 95, 101 (2002) (suggesting that reputation varies by field of
activity, and that this segmentation reduces the effects of reputation).
93 Milgrom, North & Weingast, supra note 70, at 1.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
29
The games we develop allow us to identify plausible circumstances under which
the iterated prisoner’s dilemma can result in stable and efficient equilibria both bilaterally
and multilaterally. Moreover, they show what types of contexts, including malleable
institutional features, may affect the ability of states to reach such equilibria.
The iterated prisoner’s dilemma game has two important features, in common
with all repeated games. First, the strategies played by each state at time t can be made
conditional on the history of play up to time t. Second, these strategies can include the
possibility of punishment if a state deviates from an agreement to follow a particular
strategy.
Consider the game illustrated in Table 1. In this game, state A is a representative
state in an n-state group that is considering cooperating on some aspect of their
international relations—for example, fishing rights, protection of diplomats,
expropriation, or technology standards. Given that we focus on bilateral rather than
multilateral punishment, we can confine our attention to a typical bilateral game, played
between State A and State B, that is embedded in the full n-player game. If both states
cooperate, it is assumed that state i receives Ci(n). If both states defect, each receives
Di(n). If state A defects while state B cooperates, state A receives GA(n), while if state A
cooperates while state B defects, state A receives LA(n).
Table 1: A Multilateral Prisoner’s Dilemma Game with Bilateral Punishment
State B
Cooperate Defect
Cooperate
CA(n); CB(n)
LA(n); GB(n)
State A
Defect
GA(n); LB(n)
DA(n); DB(n)
This is a prisoner’s dilemma game when the following is true:
(i) Gi(n) > Ci(n): Both states prefer to defect when the other state cooperates;
(ii) Di(n) > Li(n): Both states prefer to defect when the other state defects;
(iii) Di(n) < Ci(n): Bilateral cooperation is better for both states than bilateral
defection.
It follows from (i) – (iii) that Gi(n) > Ci(n) > Li(n). The multilateral context of
this game is captured first, by the implicit assumption that (i)-(iii) are independent of the
number of other states in the multilateral context that are playing Cooperate or Defect and
second, by the assumption that some or all of the payoffs in each of the component
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
30
bilateral games are functions of the number of states n in the multilateral context. The
subscripts allow for the possibility of asymmetric payoffs to the different states.
Given that conditions (i) – (iii) are satisfied, and the implicit assumption
regarding states other than A and B, we have the standard result that the Nash equilibrium
to both the bilateral game in Table 1 and to the overall multilateral game, given that this
game is played only once, or a finite number of times known in advance to all the
participants, is that all states play Defect. In other words, even if a CIL rule is articulated
it will not be followed.
Assume instead that the game is repeated indefinitely. To make this more
concrete, assume that in any period t state i believes that this game will be played again in
period t + 1 with probability ri < 1. Further suppose that state i has discount factor Ri,
where 0 < Ri < 1 is a measure of impatience: the smaller is Ri the less patient state i is –
the more that state i favors current benefits over future benefits. We can then construct a
“probability adjusted” discount factor di = ri.Ri for each state.
Now consider whether the strategy combination {Cooperate, Cooperate} can be
sustained as an equilibrium to the game in Table 1 when it is repeated indefinitely. For
this to be the case, {Cooperate, Cooperate} must be a subgame perfect equilibrium. One
such strategy profile that has the potential to support such an equilibrium is the grim
trigger strategy for each state i in each bilateral game:
1. Cooperate in period t if both states have cooperated in all periods up to and
including t – 1;
2. Defect in period t and all subsequent periods if either state has defected in any
period prior to t.
As discussed above, an alternative strategy, addressing the problem of collective
rationality, is “penance.” Fudenberg and Tirole show that the following “penance”
strategy profile is “weakly renegotiation proof” (WRP): “Begin in the cooperative phase
where both states play Cooperate. If a single state A switches to Defect, switch to the
punishment phase for A. In this phase, state A plays Cooperate and the other state plays
Defect. Play remains in this phase until the first time state A plays Cooperate, at which
point play returns to the cooperative phase.”94 The logic of this strategy is that a state
having defected from a rule can have the rule reinstated only by accepting a period of
punishment, in which it cooperates while the other state defects against it. The penance
strategy works in the following manner. A defects once. B defects subsequently and in
each future play until A cooperates while B defects. Then B cooperates, expecting A to
continue cooperating since B has “stuck with” the “agreed” strategy.
94 Fudenberg & Tirole, supra note 36, at 180. The “defect for deviate” strategy proposed
by Mahoney and Sanchirico, supra note 24, can be seen as the multilateral punishment
equivalent of this penance strategy.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
31
Whether we use the grim trigger or the penance strategy profile, standard analysis
indicates that we need only consider a single-period defection by a state.95 Suppose, then
that state i chooses to Defect in period 0.96 Its return from doing so is:
( ) ( )
( ) ( ) ( )
d-
d+d+
d-
d+
=
penancewith1
triggergrimwith1
2
i
i
iiii
i
i
ii
D
nCnLnG
nDnG
S
If, by contrast, state i chooses Cooperate in every period, its return is:
( )
i
i
C
nCS
d-= 1
For Cooperate to be preferable for state i we must have SC > SD which, after some
manipulation, requires:
( ) ( )
( ) ( )
( ) ( )
( ) ( )
-
-=d
-
-=d
>d>
*
*
penance.with
triggergrimwith
ifonly and if:Condition Patience
nLnC
nCnG
nDnG
nCnG
SS
ii
ii
p
ii
ii
g
iDC
In each of these equations, of course, i = A or B.
We know from condition (iii) above that 1<d*g , so we have the familiar result
that, with the grim trigger strategy and provided the participants to the potential rule are
sufficiently patient, multilateral cooperation is sustainable. This need not be the case
with the penance strategy. This is because 1<d*p if and only if Ci(n) > (Gi(n) + Li(n))/2,
for i = A, B. In other words, the penance strategy will sustain cooperation only if for both
states the single-period return to cooperation exceeds the average of the single-period
return to cheating and return to being punished.
It should not be thought, however, that grim trigger is necessarily a tougher
punishment regime than patience and so more able to sustain a cooperative rule. We note
that ** d<d gp if and only if Gi(n) – Ci(n) < Di(n) – Li(n), in other words, if the gain to
95 We could also assume with grim trigger that states switch to Defect for a finite number
of periods T without affecting the qualitative conclusions.
96 Again, standard analysis indicates that we can always choose the first period in which
Defect is played as the beginning of the game.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
32
defection when the other state cooperates is less than the gain to defection when the other
state defects.
The Patience Condition can be interpreted in other ways that are directly relevant
to our analysis. First, CIL is more likely to emerge and be sustainable when the returns to
cooperation are high relative to non-cooperation and when the returns to unilateral
defection are low. Second, CIL is more likely to be formed between relatively patient
states: those with relatively high discount factors. Third, CIL is more likely where the
probability of continued interaction between the participating states is high.
The important question to which we now turn is that raised by Goldsmith and
Posner. Does increasing the number of participants make it tougher to sustain
cooperation? For this to be the case it is necessary that *d rises as n increases.
With some manipulation we can show (suppressing n in the interests of brevity)
that
( ) ( ) ( )
---+-=
?
d? *
dn
dCDG
dn
dDCG
dn
dGDCsign
nsign
i
ii
i
ii
i
ii
g
( ) ( ) ( )
---+-=
?
d? *
dn
dCCG
dn
dLCG
dn
dGLCsign
nsign
i
ii
i
ii
i
ii
p
We are interested in the signs of these derivatives: whether they are positive or negative
determines whether *d rises as n increases. This is important since, the higher the critical
discount factor the less likely it is that the CIL rule is sustainable multilaterally. Note that
from (i) – (iii) above, all of the bracketed terms (Ci – Di) and so on are positive. It
follows that the signs of the derivatives n?d? /* are determined by the signs of the
derivatives of the payoffs with respect to the number of states in the multilateral rule.
The simplest, but probably least likely case is that in which none of the pay-offs
are affected by n, that is dGi/dn = dDi/dn = dCi/dn = dLi/dn = 0. If this is the case then
the multilateral CIL rule is no more than the aggregation of a series of independent
bilateral CIL rules and so is no more difficult to sustain than the individual bilateral rules.
It is more likely, however, that the multilateral context has some force in that at
least the number of states that are effectively party to the multilateral CIL rule affects
some of the payoffs.97 This force could derive from the public goods or network aspect
97 For a recognition by the International Court of Justice that even diplomatic protection
has an important multilateral dimension, see Diplomatic and Consular Personnel Case,
I.C.J. Reports, 1980 p. 3 at pp. 42-3 (para. 92). In that case, the ICJ made the following
statement:
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
33
of the establishment of the CIL rule itself. But the situation that is most often considered
is one in which states have to share gains from cooperation, so that dCi/dn < 0, have more
to gain from defection the greater the number of states that continue to abide by a CIL
rule, so that dGi/dn > 0, and where non-formulation of a CIL rule leaves states in an
autarkic situation, so that dDi/dn ? 0. Where this is the case, it follows that the critical
discount factor is increasing in n so that multilateral CIL is, indeed, harder to sustain than
bilateral CIL. This is, however, not the same as saying that such CIL rules are
impossible to sustain or even highly unlikely to be sustained.
The critical condition is, as noted above, that each state i that is party to the CIL
rule has probability adjusted discount factor di > d*. This is more likely to arise if each
state believes that the probability of continuation ri is high and has a high discount factor
Ri. The implication is first, that we are more likely to see multilateral CIL among states
that have, and are expected to have, interactions over an extended period. Second,
multilateral CIL rules are more likely between “patient” states, meaning states that tend
to value future payoffs more highly than others. Third, multilateral CIL rules are more
likely to hold when the relevant interactions are frequent. This is because Ri is a “per
period” discount factor and ri is a “per period” probability. The shorter the time period
between transactions the higher is the effective probability adjusted discount factor and
so the more likely it is that the di > d* condition will be satisfied.
Moreover, there are at least two potentially countervailing forces that can work to
sustain multilateral CIL.
The first follows from our analysis above. It is not difficult to imagine
circumstances in which dGi/dn < 0 and/or dCi/dn >0. Where this is the case the
conventional argument is actually reversed. Multilateral CIL rules are easier to sustain
than bilateral rules.
In recalling yet again the extreme importance of the principles of law [diplomatic
protection] which it is called upon to apply in the present case, the Court
considers it to be its duty to draw the attention of the entire international
community, of which Iran itself has been a member since time immemorial, to the
irreparable harm that may be caused by events of the kind now before the Court.
Such events cannot fail to undermine the edifice of law carefully constructed by
mankind over a period of centuries, the maintenance of which is vital for the
security and well-being of the complex international community of the present
day, to which it is more essential than ever that the rules developed to ensure the
ordered progress of relations between its members should be constantly and
scrupulously respected.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
34
Under what circumstances might this arise? One possibility98 is that the rule
relates to the investment by each participating state in the provision of a public good.99
As more states participate, the investment in provision increases as does the benefit to the
individual state from cooperation. By contrast, the gains from defection are likely to
decrease with n. The same is likely to be true for policies with strong network effects –
for example, common international technology standards.100 A single state may gain
from going it alone but the potential gains are likely to be less the more isolated the state
is, that is, the more that the state looks like a single stand-out where others adopt a
common standard. A third possibility is that there are reputation effects built into Gi(n).
A state gains from defecting on a rule but the act of defection harms the state’s
reputation, making it less likely that the state will be able to make agreements with other
states. In the context of the game in Table 1, this implies that the gains from current
defection will tend to decrease with n.
The second countervailing effect arises when states are involved in a series of
international rules (including treaty rules) with overlapping groups of partners. In such a
case, defection on one rule has potentially harmful effects for all of the rules to which a
particular state is party. This is similar to the analysis of the potential for multimarket
contact to maintain tacit agreements between firms.101 Rather than provide a general
analysis, the basic idea can be illustrated by using a variant of one of the examples from
Goldsmith and Posner,102 illustrated in Table 2, assuming bilateral punishment and the
grim trigger strategy profile.103 In this game, cooperation by all states gives each state a
share 6/n. Defection by all states gives each a share 4/n. Defection by a single state
gives that state 4 and leaves the remaining states a share 2/n.
98 See, e.g., Robert Pahre, Multilateral Cooperation in an Iterated Prisoners' Dilemma,
38:2 J. CONFL. RES., 326 (1994); Snidal, supra note 32, at 929.
99 For a discussion of global public goods, see PROVIDING GLOBAL PUBLIC GOODS:
MANAGING GLOBALIZATION (I. Kaul et. al, eds. 2003).
100 Other areas of international law, including the law of sovereignty, diplomatic
protection, etc., may exhibit network effects. These may arise simply from efficiencies
due to consistency of arrangements. For a relevant analysis in the corporate law field, see
Michael Klausner, Corporations, Corporate Law and Networks of Contracts, 81VA. L.
REV. 757 (1995).
101 The classic reference on this is Bernheim & Whinston, supra note 83.
102 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, at 1125, table 2. Goldsmith & Posner’s
table 2, relating to the protection of coastal fishing boats, appears as follows:
State i
Attack Ignore
Attack 2, 2 4, 1
State j Ignore 1, 4 3, 3
103 The more general analysis is available on request.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
35
Suppose that there are 2 states, i.e. n = 2. Then the critical probability adjusted
discount factor above which a bilateral rule is sustainable is, from the analysis above:
( ) 2124 342 =--=d*g
By contrast, if there are 4 states the critical discount factor to maintain a
multilateral rule between all four is:
( ) 6514 4/644 =--=d*g
Now suppose that each state enters into a bilateral rule or agreement with one of
the other three states as well as a multilateral rule with all four. Consider the following
strategy.
1. Cooperate in period t if all states have Cooperated in all periods up to and
including t – 1;
2. Defect in period t and all subsequent periods on both rules if any state has
Defected on either rule in any period prior to t.
Table 2: A Multilateral Prisoner’s Dilemma Game with Multi-Sector Contact
State B
Cooperate Defect
Cooperate
n
6 ;
n
6
n
2 ; 4
State A
Defect 4 ;
n
2
n
4 ;
n
4
Clearly, if any state is going to Defect it will Defect on both the bilateral and
multilateral rules, since the strategy calls for its partner to react to defection by defecting
on both rules. The returns to the defecting state from defection are:
d-
d+=
d-
d++
d-
d+
1
38
141
24
The returns from continued cooperation are:
( ) ( )d-
=d-+d- 12 912 31 3
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
36
It follows that the critical probability adjusted discount factor above which the
multilateral and single bilateral rules are sustainable is
( ) 1071,4* =d
By the same argument, if a state enters into two bilateral rules and a four-state
multilateral rule, the probability adjusted critical discount factor is
( ) 1492,4* =d
More generally, this example has the property that the critical probability adjusted
discount factor increases as the number of potential partner states increases, making the
multilateral CIL rule in this example more difficult to sustain as the number of
participants to the rule increases, as Goldsmith and Posner argue. However, our example
also illustrates the countervailing power that derives from states being able to enter into
bilateral as well as multilateral agreements. In any multilateral context, the critical
discount factor decreases as the number of bilateral rules that each state enters into
increases. This leads to a simple but compelling proposition. A state can use slack
enforcement power in bilateral rules to sustain multilateral rules.
The third possibility is related to the second. Recall that the discount factor
relates to a particular period of time: the time between “transactions”. In other words, if
transactions occur every three months then d* is a three-month discount factor, whereas if
transactions occur every month then d* is a one-month discount factor. To see what this
means, consider once again the multilateral game of Table 2 with 4 states and assume that
this game is played every quarter. Then the critical quarterly probability adjusted
discount factor is 5/6, or 83%. Now suppose that the game is played every month. The
critical monthly probability adjusted discount factor to sustain cooperation is again 5/6 or
83%, but this is equivalent to a quarterly probability adjusted discount factor of (5/6)3, or
58%. In other words, multilateral rules are more easily sustained when they involve
frequent interactions between the member states.
These two possibilities can, of course, interact. States may be able to enter into
multiple rules, some with frequent interaction and some with infrequent interaction. By
the same argument as above, a state can use slack enforcement power from rules with
frequent transactions to sustain rules with infrequent transactions.
The implication of this analysis is that there exists a significant set of cases in
which it will be possible to form multilateral customary rules of international law. The
likelihood of formation in any particular circumstance will depend on a number of
factors, including (i) the relative value of cooperation versus defection, (ii) the number of
states effectively involved, (iii) the extent to which increasing the number of states
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
37
involved increases the value of cooperation or the detriments of defection, including
whether the particular issue has characteristics of a commons problem, a public good, or
a network, (iv) the information available to the states involved regarding compliance and
defection, (v) the relative patience of states to realize benefits of long-term cooperation
compared to short-term defection, (vi) the expected duration of interaction, (vii) the
frequency of interaction, and (viii) whether there are also bilateral relationships or other
multilateral relationships between the involved states.
5. Implications
The model presented above suggests that CIL may affect behavior, and that it will
do so to varying extents under varying circumstances. This model has implications for
international legal theory, for CIL doctrine, for policy and for research.
a. International Legal Theory Implication: CIL May Affect Behavior
The discussion in parts 2 and 3 and the model in part 4 suggest that there exists a
significant set of cases in which CIL will affect behavior. As we cannot here assess in
any particular case the actual value to states of cooperation, or their discount rates, or
many of the other factors included in the model, it is impossible to say with certainty that
CIL affects behavior, how often, or how much. But it is equally impossible to say that it
does not affect behavior, that it seldom does so, or even that it only has marginal effects.
So, we believe that CIL is plausible. It seems no less plausible than social norms in the
domestic context. In fact, there are reasons to believe that it may be more plausible,
based on economies of scale and scope in information and multi-sector contact. On the
other hand, there are countervailing factors, including the possibility that individuals in
small communities have a greater sense of permanence than governments in international
society. Interestingly, this analysis suggests that states generally have an interest in the
development of domestic political institutions that will instill “patience” in other states.
b. Normative Implications: Institutional Modifications
The prior analysis suggests a number of potential implications for policy.
“Perhaps game theory’s greatest potential for contributing to international law is to
provide a rigorous means of describing and articulating important aspects of state
interaction and cooperation. The hope is that fully developed game theoretic models will
help states design law that creates or enhances the conditions for cooperation, if such
cooperation is desirable.”104
i. The Role of Regional or Plurilateral Custom
As demonstrated above, the number of states involved in forming a particular
customary rule may have a significant effect on the ability to form a rule. As we have
104 Chinen, Game Theory and Customary International Law, supra note 2, at 155.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
38
suggested, this effect will differ in direction, depending on the context. Therefore, states
may find that they can develop regional or other plurilateral rules of CIL in circumstances
where multilateral rules are more difficult to establish. Regional or other plurilateral
intensification of relationships, such as in the European Community or the OECD, may
establish the conditions for greater use of custom.
ii. Network Effects in Institutionalism
International cooperation in different sectors may be mutually supportive, and
there may be a kind of network effect that makes each additional instance of cooperation
more attractive than it would be absent existing instances. This game theoretic
perspective provides support for the early neo-functionalist hypotheses regarding
international economic integration, and suggests the potential value of cooperation “for
its own sake” or in order to facilitate further cooperation. It also provides theoretical
support for strategies of “constructive engagement” outside the CIL context. Network
effects may be enhanced in regional or other plurilateral contexts, by concentrating and
intensifying relationships.
iii. The Information Role of NGOs and International Courts
By disseminating information regarding compliance with particular norms, NGOs
or international organizations may play a critical role in assuring perfect information,
facilitating the development of custom. In cases of complex rules or facts, where under a
regime of autointerpretation states may argue over compliance, courts or other
“independent” third parties may resolve this information problem more definitively.
iv. Custom and Treaty
This article applies the literature of law and social norms in a way that suggests a
bridge over the gulf between law and social norms. It recognizes that law on the one
hand, and social norms on the other hand, are alternative or sometimes complementary
means of social control, or social cooperation. It thus suggests the utility of comparative
institutional analysis105 between law, on the one hand, and social norms, on the other.
Custom is a mechanism for international “legislation” that requires only a degree
of consensus,106 not unanimity. Given the difficulty of establishing multilateral treaties
without significant holdouts, and given the need to avoid free riders, we might understand
the CIL process as an alternative mechanism for global legislation. A rule of consensus
acts as a default rule that promotes compliance, and increases the bureaucratic costs of
“persistent objectors.” We recognize that this type of strategy would raise concerns
regarding democratic legitimacy. However, this type of legislative technique is not more
105 See NEIL KOMESAR, IMPERFECT ALTERNATIVES (1996); HERVé MOULIN,
COOPERATIVE MICROECONOMICS: A GAME-THEORETIC INTRODUCTION (1995).
106 “Consensus” is here understood as an absence of express objection.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
39
invasive than majority voting, and the “persistent objector” rule allows states to opt-out
of rules that raise sufficient concern.
There is less of a distinction between CIL and treaty, on the one hand, than there
is between social norms and either contract or law, on the other hand. As treaty is in
legal theory only supported by CIL and by institutions created by treaty, rather than by an
external state, it is something less than contractual. In fact, we may understand treaty in
the international law context as an extension of custom, or of social norms. It is an
important extension, with the capacity to specify required performance in greater detail,
establishing greater agreement on the content of the relevant norm, and thereby
overcoming important information problems. Of course, to the extent the treaty specifies
binding dispute settlement, the additional information problem of the application of law
to facts may be overcome.
Furthermore, treaty has a greater capacity for concreteness than custom, and
treaty lends itself more to specificity—to rules as opposed to broad standards. Treaty
also is more amenable to domestic ratification, which is both a burden in terms of
efficiency of agreement, and a benefit in terms of accountability. As in the rules and
standards context, custom may serve as a pathfinder for later-established specific treaty
rules. Conversely, treaty structures, including dispute settlement, may serve as an
institutional setting to promote custom.
Further analysis of the relationship between treaty and custom, and the choice of
instruments in particular contexts, is beyond the scope of this article.
c. Doctrinal Implications: A Contractual Approach to Opinio Juris
We have not yet directly addressed the argument by Goldsmith and Posner that
CIL generally does no work—that state behavior is not motivated by CIL, but only by
self-interest.107 The implication of this argument, not made explicit by Goldsmith and
Posner, is that CIL does not exist, because CIL doctrine requires practice motivated by
opinio juris—by CIL. This argument is subject to several lines of attack.
i. CIL Rules May Affect Behavior
First, our discussion in parts 2, 3 and 4 shows that CIL may affect behavior. So
our refutation of the assumption that the n-person prisoner’s dilemma is unlikely to bind
states shows that it is plausible that state behavior is affected by CIL.
ii. A Contractual Approach to Opinio Juris
107 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2 at 1131-1133.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
40
Recall that under the Restatement Third formulation, CIL does not exist without
opinio juris, or the sense of legal obligation. However, as D'Amato suggests,108 it seems
on first analysis that this requirement is circular: the first state that complies "from a
sense of legal obligation" must do so erroneously. There may be a solution to this
paradox.
Analogizing CIL to social norms, we might postulate that instead of a "sense of
legal obligation," the Restatement Third formulation might more correctly refer to an
"intent to create or accept a rule of law."109 As suggested by the formulation contained in
Article 38(1)(b) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice, we may in addition
refer to a "sense of incipient legal obligation."110 CIL may arise in the international
system in just the way that social norms arise in the domestic setting, with the same
possible beneficial effects in terms of cooperation and coordination. The social norms
analogy suggests, with McDougal, Mendelson, Swaine, and Thirlway111 that we may
understand the initial act of “compliance” not necessarily as an error, but as an offer or an
act of leadership.
Consider the development of social norms in the municipal setting. The first time
that in Shasta County, a cattle farmer returned a lost calf to its owner without charge,
108 ANTHONY A. D'AMATO, THE CONCEPT OF CUSTOM IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 5
(Cornell 1971).
109 It is worth noting the relationship of this proposition to the first formulation of
Kant’s categorical imperative: “Act only on that maxim through which you can at the
same time will that it should become universal law.” IMMANUEL KANT, GROUNDWORK
OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS (Mary Gregor trans. & ed., Cambridge Univ. Press
1997) (1785).
110 See Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.),
1986 I.C.J. 14, 109 (June 27) (“Reliance by a State on a novel right, or an unprecedented
exception to the principle, might if shared in principle by other States, tend towards a
modification of customary international law.”).
111 “[A]t the initial stage of the development of the custom, it is sufficient that the States
concerned regard the practice as what the Court . . . referred to as ‘potentially norm-
creating’, as conforming to a rule which either already exists or is a useful and desirable
rule which should exist.’” Hugh Thirlway, The Law and Procedure of the International
Court of Justice 1960-1989 (Part Two), 1990 BRIT. Y.B. INT’L L. 1, 43, citing North Sea
Continental Shelf (F.R.G. v. Den.; F.R.G. v. Neth.), 1969 I.C.J. 3, 42 (Feb. 20). See
MCDOUGAL ET AL, STUDIES IN WORLD PUBLIC ORDER 773-74 (1960); Mendelson, supra
note 8; Swaine, supra note 2, at 615 (suggesting that states that initiate a custom might be
analogized to offerors in a constractual setting, and that this conditional obligation is
consistent with opinio juris). See also D’Amato, supra note 108, at 73-102. And what of
the circumstances in which initial acts are unreciprocated? We might understand these
acts as transaction costs: as costs of identifying feasible transactions or appropriate
partners. This is not very different from gift-giving practices in many village and other
social circumstances. See Posner, supra note 12, 49-67.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
41
despite a lack of legal obligation, there existed no relevant social norm. Yet that action,
perhaps recognized by its author to provide efficiencies that would eventually benefit him
if multilateralized, or perhaps motivated by something else but interpreted as a proposal
to initiate a rule, began a process that resulted in a “social norm.”
If we understand the "sense of legal obligation" referenced in the Restatement
Third not as a sense of a fully-formed legal rule, but as a perception or assertion that a
legal rule would be beneficial, the circularity problem is resolved. Thus, custom must be
understood not as mere action, but as an initial or continuing proposal for collective
action over time, with acceptance evidenced by compliance. A state may test a proposed
rule of collective action informally, without the domestic or international costs that
otherwise might attend the proposal.112 “Run it up the flagpole and see if anyone
salutes.” Supporting this approach, a recent report of the International Law Association
explained that opinio juris requires practice "in circumstances which give rise to a
legitimate expectation of similar conduct in the future."113 This understanding also offers
a plausible explanation of changing rules of CIL. In fact, there is no real difference
between initiation and change: initiation of a rule is a change from a laissez-faire rule.
Thus, there is a rationale for the opinio juris requirement in terms of general state
intent:114 mere regularity of action, or mere action based on motives that do not include
the formation of a legal rule, cannot form a rule of CIL. This is recognized in Article 38
of the Statute of the International Court of Justice, which specifies "international custom,
112 See Parisi, supra note 2, at 18 (describing "articulation theories" of CIL in these
terms). Parisi suggests special deference to rules chosen prior to conflict: "Articulations
that are made prior to unveiling of conflicting contingencies can be analogized to rules
chosen under a Harsanyian veil of uncertainty." Id. At 19. This condition is referred to
as “stochastic uncertainty.” However, one might ask why there would be an incentive to
produce new rules in the absence of conflict. Perhaps the answer to this problem is that
the formation of custom is a process occurring over time, and states may participate
before they know their individual contingent position. Furthermore, one might question
whether the veil of uncertainty does not apply even after conflict arises, to the extent that
states may not know their position in future instances of conflict.
113 COMM. ON FORMATION OF CUSTOMARY (GEN.) INT'L LAW, INT'L LAW ASS'N, FINAL
REPORT: STATEMENT OF PRINCIPLES APPLICABLE TO THE FORMATION OF GENERAL
CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW §1(i) (2000),
http://www.ila.hq.org/pdf/CustomaryLaw.pdf, citing Maurice H. Mendelson, The
Formation of Customary International Law, 272 COLLECTED COURSES 188, 399 (1998).
114 What of states that have no relevant intent, or that object to the formation of a legal
rule? We will not deal with the doctrinal problem of the persistent objector. But it seems
plausible that states would accept a rule of consensus legislation in international custom:
a rule may be formed that binds states that do not object. For an analysis of consensus-
based decision-making within the GATT/WTO system, see Richard Steinberg, In the
Shadow of Law or Power: Consensus-Based Bargaining and Outcomes at the
GATT/WTO, 56 INT’L ORG. 399 (2002).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
42
as evidence of a general practice accepted as law."115 Goldsmith and Posner seem correct
that motivation by narrow coincidence of interest (the behavior intrinsically benefits the
actor) or narrow coercion (of a more direct and unilateral type than the retaliation
included in our model) are inconsistent with opinio juris and so do not contribute to CIL.
But even here, states are likely to act with varying and multiple motivations, and it is
possible that a CIL rule could be formed despite the fact that some states adhere largely
due to narrow coincidence of interest or narrow coercion. Moreover, it is incorrect to
argue that where states act out of self-interest, no opinio juris can exist.
iii. CIL Rules May be Coterminous with Self-Interest
Second, there is a terminological or doctrinal problem with Goldsmith and
Posner’s argument, making it seem tautological. Goldsmith and Posner argue that
“[s]tates do not comply with CIL because of a sense of moral or legal obligation; rather,
CIL emerges from the states' pursuit of self-interested policies on the international
stage.”116 Unless Goldsmith and Posner mean merely to refute the natural law position
that states comply with international law because of its normative appeal or legitimacy or
because it is the right thing to do, this argument is a non-sequitur, as legal obligation and
self-interest are not mutually exclusive categories. Law and economics has long utilized
price theory to understand behavior under legal rules, and there is no question that law
can affect behavior through self-interest. In the CIL setting, the motivating force is wider
or potentially longer-term self-interest that flows from making and achieving compliance
with a rule, or even with rules generally: narrow or diffuse reciprocity.117
Goldsmith and Posner’s main point here must then be understood simply as the
application of an assumption of the rationalist model (and one that is subject to at least
some contention): that agents only care about their own utility, and therefore would not
follow a rule of CIL for intrinsic reasons: for its own sake.118 However, compliance with
international law resulting from a sense of legal obligation is consistent with extrinsic
reasons: there may well be utility in upholding a particular rule, or in upholding the rule
of law in general.
115 The International Court of Justice seems to ignore the text in favor of a reverse
reading, seeking to find evidence of international custom in a general practice accepted as
law. ROSALYNN HIGGINS, PROBLEMS & PROCESS: INTERNATIONAL LAW AND HOW WE
USE IT 18-19 (1994). Of course, there are other formulations. See, e.g., IAN BROWNLIE,
PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 4-11 (5th ed. 1998).
116 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, at 1115.
117 See Robert O. Keohane, Reciprocity in International Relations, 40 INT’L ORG. 1
(1986).
118 Recall that there is an important literature on social norms that considers the
potential for preference modification, holding out the possibility of compliance because
of modified preferences. See sources cited at note 23, supra. It may not be necessary to
choose between static and dynamic preferences: changing preferences may work
together with static preferences and self interest.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
43
iv. Evidentiary Requirements
Third, a marginalist approach would reject the evidence presented by Goldsmith
and Posner as a basis for their argument. Their case-based evidence merely suggests in a
limited range of contexts that there are plausible non-CIL reasons for observed
behavior.119 Goldsmith and Posner adduce no data that suggests the relative magnitude
of these reasons, or that suggests the absence of other reasons. So, they and we have no
way of knowing that CIL was not a contributing, or alternative sufficient, cause of
behavior.120 Survey or interview data might be useful to fill this gap.
Of course, to the extent that a particular instance of compliance is fully and
exclusively explained by self-interest in the sense that the act of compliance intrinsically
benefits the acting state (without any need for any action or reciprocation by other states),
or from coercion of a type not permitted under international law, it cannot be argued that
CIL did any work. Our theory of CIL examines the effects of broader self-interest based
on reciprocity, and accepts the possibility of a different kind of coercion by punishment
for defection, as a normal part of the CIL process. While CIL is endogenous to states in
the aggregate, once formed it is at least largely exogenous to the particular state. As
explained above, we also find it plausible that there are important circumstances in which
CIL would have significant effects on state behavior.
v. Violations or Proposals for Change?
Related to the problem of determining whether a custom has the requisite
motivation under CIL doctrine is the question of how to deal with anomalous conduct.
Does the anomaly constitute the initiation of a revised rule of CIL, or a simple
violation?121 It is important to recognize that no law, in any system, achieves perfect
compliance. Thus we must determine another way to evaluate compliance. The best way
is to evaluate the extent to which law affects behavior. Thus, the fact that wars occur
does not alone mean that the international legal prohibition on the use of force is without
effect, just as the fact that murders occur does not mean a domestic proscription of
murder is meaningless. Goldsmith and Posner argue that variations in levels of
compliance suggest that no multilateral rule exists, or affects state behavior.122 However,
we would expect systematic circumstantial variations in compliance with respect to all
laws. That is, in order to determine that CIL exists, or that we as social scientists should
pay attention to it, it need not in every case determine behavior, so long as it may do so in
119 But see Swaine, supra note 2 (raising concerns regarding Goldsmith and Posner’s
perspective on CIL doctrine).
120 Cf. Guzman, supra note 2, at 1875 (asserting that Goldsmith and Posner’s claim that
CIL does not affect state behavior goes beyond what the evidence suggests).
121 See D’Amato, supra note 108, at 97 (stating that “an ‘illegal’ act by a state contains
the seeds of a new legality”).
122 Goldsmith & Posner 1999, supra note 2, at 1157.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
44
some set of marginal cases. In game theoretic terms, even a small effect of international
law could affect the payoffs from compliance, potentially tipping the balance in favor of
compliance in a marginal case.
Furthermore, in order to maintain the dynamic, evolutionary character of CIL, it is
necessary that any theory of CIL allow for some violations of existing rules to be
understood as proposals for the establishment of new rules.123 This is indeed a subtle and
difficult distinction, but it is necessary in any decentralized system. Thus, we should not
demand that CIL command absolute compliance, or be inflexible. In fact, one might
argue, as some do about the common law, that one of its great virtues is its dynamism.
d. Research Implications: An Empirical Research Agenda
Theory alone tells us little about the world. The next step is to develop and test
hypotheses based on the theory of CIL elaborated here.
i. Assessing the Patience/Horizon of States
In empirical research, it would be useful to determine parameters or proxies by
which to assess the patience (including the horizon) of states and governments, and to
regress these parameters against measures of compliance. Is political stability associated
with patience, and do we see greater compliance with CIL by states with greater political
stability? Are democratic states, or states with better developed financial markets, more
patient? Are autocratic states more patient because they are not concerned about election
cycles? Do we see greater amounts of violation of law before an election than after? Is
patience determined by a bell curve, in which strong autocracies and stable democracies
are patient, and those in between are not? Are corrupt governments “impatient”? What
about more-or-less independent bureaucracies that may be charged with action that
determines compliance with specific rules of CIL? Can these independent bureaucracies
exhibit greater patience than their elected governments? These conjectures are linked to
liberal states theory,124 as well as to theories of transnational governmental networks.125
In fact, the correct level of analysis for compliance with certain rules of CIL, in terms
both of patience and information transmission, may be the bureaucratic division, rather
than the state.
ii. Network Externalities in International Law: More Relationships
Make Each Relationship More Reliable
Do we see an acceleration of custom, or a tipping point at which sufficient
relationships are established to make compliance with CIL more likely? Is there a
123 See, e.g., MALCOLM N. SHAW, INTERNATIONAL LAW 69 (4th ed. 1997).
124 See Anne-Marie Slaughter, International Law in a World of Liberal States, 6 EUR. J.
INT’L L. 538 (1995).
125 See Anne-Marie Slaughter, The Real New World Order, 76 FOR. AFF. 183 (1997).
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
45
synergy between treaty and CIL? This hypothesis might be tested by examining the
relationship between entry into treaties and compliance with CIL. Again, the possibility
of network externalities is inconsistent with a disaggregation of the state into independent
functional components.
iii. Regional Custom
To what extent can we identify regional or other plurilateral CIL, and how does it
compare in terms of compliance to universal CIL?
iv. Information
Is there a relationship between the establishment of NGOs that enhance
information regarding compliance and defection, or the establishment of adjudicative
bodies, and compliance with CIL?
6. Conclusions
This article shows the rational plausibility of CIL. It thus serves as a basic
defense of the international law system. Indeed, this article presents not just a theory of
CIL, but a theory of international law more generally. The theory presented here is based
on methodological and normative individualism. It thus departs substantially from the
airy idealism of natural law theory. It serves as a positive social scientific theoretical
basis for international legal positivism and a nuanced realism, basing law on the action of
states or their agents in pursuit of their self-interest, broadly understood.126 It shows that
CIL, and with it treaty law, is something of a levitation trick. It therefore rests not on a
rock-solid natural law basis of divine principles, but on a fabric of rational acts, woven
through a multiplicity of relations over time.
This article also serves as a refutation of the central claim of political science
realism with respect to international law: that it is epiphenomenal. This article shows
that law may well be a social expression of rules that achieve real collective goals, are
backed by real sanctions, and have real behavioral effects. It is a strange realism that
would ignore this.
If social norms theory in the domestic sphere finds social norms attractive as a
mechanism for production and enforcement of rules, perhaps CIL holds promise as an
alternative to treaty. Perhaps the main distinguishing feature, and potential value, of CIL
is systemic. That is, although we have assumed sectoral divisions for modeling purposes,
international law may also be understood as a set of linked games, or one extensive game.
Once a particular rule is absorbed into the CIL system, or is established through treaty, it
126 This article does not by any means challenge the theory that law can affect behavior
by modifying preferences. It merely presents a theory that does not depend on modifying
preferences.
The Customary International Law Supergame
February 23, 2004
46
may benefit from linkage to other rules of CIL, and of treaty.127 The special nature of
legal rules may derive simply from their reception into this linked system. It is order and
law.
Like all positive social science, this theory has normative implications. CIL has
advantages and disadvantages as a process for making rules. As states identify these
advantages and disadvantages in particular contexts, they may decide in some contexts to
facilitate the development of CIL through institutional modifications.
* * *
127 See Swaine, supra note 2 (“states do not, in fact, interact solely with respect to one
rule or the other, and it is also possible to understand their interaction with respect both to
an individual rule and to the system of customary international law”).