The Limits of Corporate Law in Promoting Good Corporate
Governance
December 2004
Michael D. Klausner
Stanford Law School
Stanford Law School
John M. Olin Program in Law and Economics
Working Paper No. 300
This paper can be downloaded without charge from the
Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection:
http://ssrn.com/abstract=637021
The Limits of Corporate Law in Promoting Good Corporate Governance
Michael Klausner
Nancy and Charles Munger Professor of Business and
Professor of Law
Stanford Law School
Discussions of corporate governance reform often combine prescriptions for legal
reform with prescriptions for better governance practices. Both sets of prescriptions—for
better law and for better practices —typically focus on the board of directors, and
particularly outside or “independent” directors. The assumption is that the law can affect
the governance behavior of the board by establishing roles for outside directors and by
motivating independent directors to do a good job. The extent to which law can promote
good governance in the boardroom, however, is quite limited. To a large extent, good
corporate governance must come from other sources of motivation, especially to the
extent that a source of good governance is the independent director. This comment will
briefly outline the limits of corporate law in promoting good corporate governance and in
doing so help clarify the gap that must be filled by nonlegal influences, including the sort
of norms that Martin Lipton and Jay Lorsch emphasize.
A. Traditional Corporate Law
Traditionally, there have been three sets of legal rules designed to induce directors
to govern in the interest of shareholders. First, there are fiduciary duties and procedural
rules that provide lawyers with incentives to bring suits to enforce those duties. Second,
there are shareholder voting rules, which allow shareholders to replace directors whom
they view as having failed to act in their interests. Third, there are disclosure rules that
require management to disseminate information regarding a company’s finances and
operations. One might also add as a fourth set of rules those rules governing hostile
acquisitions, which allow shareholders to separate themselves from inadequate
management by selling all their shares to an acquiror. These bodies of law, however,
impose a fairly minimal inducement to directors, particularly to independent directors, to
govern well. They can be severe in cases of self-dealing by corrupt management, but they
are actually weak—and necessarily so—when it comes to promoting affirmatively good
governance practices in the boardroom.
In contrast to many other areas of activity, the fiduciary duties applicable to
outside directors do not, as a practical matter, pose a realistic threat of out-of-pocket
liability unless a director has engaged in theft or blatant self-dealing. In other areas, one
can expect to pay damages if one fails to meet a certain standard of competence and care.
Negligence standards apply, for example, to doctors, automobile drivers, engineers and
others. Although these people have other motivations to do a good job, the threat of
liability, at least for some, provides an additional motivation. Notwithstanding reports
in the press about the legal risks directors face, their risk of out-of-pocket damage
payments is negligible. In ongoing research with Bernard Black and Brian Cheffins, we
have found virtually no case in which an outside director has actually paid money out of
his or her own pocket, despite the fact that every year dozens of suits are brought under
corporate or securities laws naming them as defendants, and hundreds of suits are filed
against their companies.
1
In many cases, suits fail at the outset because the rules
governing the pleading of shareholder suits impose a significant bar to plaintiffs
regarding what they must credibly allege regarding outside directors’ misdeeds. Others
are dismissed later under the “business judgment rule,” a judicial doctrine under which
courts decline to second-guess a board’s business decision so long as the decision was
informed and so long as there was no conflict of interest involved. Cases that are not
dismissed almost always settle on terms that have the corporation and the corporation’s
directors’ and officers’ (D&O) liability insurer make a payment to the shareholders.
There is nothing nefarious going on in these settlements. What happens is a logical
consequence of the rules governing shareholder suits, a corporation’s power to indemnify
its directors, D&O insurance, and most importantly, the incentives of all sides to settle
shareholder suits without reaching inside the defendants’ own pockets.
We have found that this pattern of de facto immunity to out-of-pocket liability
exists not just in the U.S., but also in Australia, Britain, Canada, France, Germany, and
Japan—countries that span both common and civil law traditions. We suspect that the
pattern is universal. Moreover, looking back at the history of legal rules governing the
liability of corporate directors, one finds that when this pattern is disturbed, and outside
directors are threatened with liability, either the market or lawmakers step in to reinstate
directors’ protection.
2
Shareholder voting has a similarly weak impact on directors’ incentives to do a
good job. Under the law, shareholders have the power to replace a board of directors, but
they virtually never even try to do so outside the context of a hostile acquisition, which I
discuss below. The reason for their passivity is the classic collective action problem that
shareholders face. A shareholder who mounts such a campaign must pay the cost of
doing so up front. The shareholder’s gain, if it materializes, will take the form of a better
managed company and higher share value. Unless that shareholder holds a large block of
shares, his personal cost-benefit analysis of a campaign to replace the boad will not
support mounting the campaign. . Moreover, even for a large shareholder, unless a
substantial proportion of a company’s other shares are also held by one or more block
holders, it will be difficult to get the attention of enough other shareholders, let alone
1
See “Outside Director Liability,” by Bernard S. Black, Brian R. Cheffins, and Michael Klausner, available
online at http://ssrn.com/abstract=382422; Bernard Black, Brian Cheffins & Michael Klausner, "Liability
Risk for Outside Directors: A Cross-Border Analysis", European Financial Management, vol. 11,
(forthcoming 2005), available online at http://ssrn.com/abstract=557070.
2
See Bernard Black, Brian Cheffins & Michael Klausner, "Liability Risk for Outside Directors: A Cross-
Border Analysis", European Financial Management, vol. 11, (forthcoming 2005), available online at
http://ssrn.com/abstract=557070; Bernard S. Black and Brian R. Cheffins, "Outside Director Liability
Across Countries", available online at http://ssrn.com/abstract=438321.
induce them to spend time analyzing whether the insurgent slate of directors will create
value that the incumbents have not.
The third area of law that may be of some help to shareholders is the securities
laws. These laws require a company to disclose, on a periodic basis and prior to issuing
securities, all material information regarding its finances and operations. These laws
work very well in day-to-day settings. Companies regularly disclose material
information to the market and market prices generally respond with amazing speed. The
disclosure process is managed by company executives. Difficulties occasionally arise,
however, when a company is having financial or operational trouble, and management
cuts corners in its disclosures. It is exceedingly difficult for outside board members to
discover that this is going on. As a matter of the law on the books, they are potentially
liable for failure to disclose material information, but they are rightfully accorded
defenses if they have exercised a reasonable degree of oversight. Consequently, suits
brought under the securities laws against outside directors are commonly dismissed.
Moreover, even for suits that are not dismissed early on, the rules governing
indemnification and D&O insurance, and the incentives of all parties to settle, render the
threat of out-of-pocket liability essentially illusory for an outside director. Thus, once
again, the threat of sanction has little direct effect on governance behavior in the
boardroom.
The law of hostile takeovers may be somewhat more helpful, but not by much.
Theoretically, if management of a company fails to maximize the value of the business,
someone else will be interested in stepping in to do so. If management is not willing to
turn over the reins, a prospective acquiror can instead approach the shareholders directly
by making a “tender offer” to buy their shares at a premium. Under law developed
during the 1980s, however, a board is permitted to obstruct this transaction by adopting a
“poison pill,” a dilutive mechanism that will stop the acquiror in its tracks until the target
board of directors removes it. The law governing a target board’s decision whether to
remove a poison pill and allow a takeover to proceed is oddly schizophrenic. It allows
the board to keep the pill in place in the face of a premium bid, if the board believes the
bid is for some reason inadequate. (“Grossly inadequate” is the preferred term of targets,
their bankers and their lawyers, for whom no bid is ever merely “inadequate.”) The law
even allows a board to sell the company to a party offering a lower bid—but only if the
competing bid would provide target shareholders with stock in the combined company.
Thankfully, the law does not allow a board to sell the company for cash if a higher cash
bid is available. Once the board decides to sell the company for cash, it must sell to the
highest bidder.
Fortunately for shareholders, there is an end-run around a board that uses its legal
power to resist an attractive takeover offer. Shareholders can vote out an incumbent
board and replace it with a board that will disable the pill and allow the acquisition to
proceed. Experience has shown that the immediate prospect of a premium bid is enough
to get shareholders to overcome their collective action problem and vote their shares in
this context.
The threat that an acquiror will appear in the future, and that shareholders will
replace their board in order to sell their company, may provide some incentive for a board
to govern well. Hostile takeovers, however, typically occur at price premiums of thirty
percent or more over market. This suggests that management must be doing a very bad
job—running a company at less than 70 percent of potential—for an acquiror to step in
and rescue shareholders. So perhaps the threat of a hostile takeover creates an incentive
for a board not to govern horribly, but it does not create an incentive for the board to
govern well.
In sum, it is difficult to imagine that these sets of legal rules have a significant
direct effect on the incentives of a board of directors to govern in an affirmatively
effective manner. To the extent boards are attentive and diligent in their oversight of
management, it is not (or at least should not be) out of a fear of out-of-pocket liability, or
a fear of being voted out of office, or a fear of having their company acquired. Their
motivation must lie elsewhere.
Moreover, if the law were changed to increase the likelihood that outside directors
would be penalized more severely for inadequate governance, corporate governance
could well suffer. Many people would decline to serve as directors, particularly those
with substantial assets or reputations at stake, and others would become excessively
defensive in their oversight role. In addition, directors’ fees would have to increase to
compensate for the heightened personal risk borne by those who do serve. Paradoxically,
this could have the effect of compromising the independence of directors for whom fees
become a meaningful portion of total income. Directors in this position might hesitate to
rock the boat, let alone resign, in the face of management decisions that they find
troubling.
B. Sarbanes-Oxley and Subsequent Reform Efforts
The Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 and the related changes in New York Stock
Exchange and NASDAQ rules, all following in the wake of the Enron and other
corporate scandals, imposed a set of structure and process rules on boards. For example,
a majority of directors must be “independent,” a term the rules define in great detail;
audit, compensation, and nominating/governance committees must be constituted with all
independent directors; and independent directors must meet alone periodically, with one
among them identified publicly as the director presiding over those meetings.
Leaving aside whether these legal rules, on balance, promote good governance
more than other structures and procedures that boards might instead adopt on their own, it
is reasonable to expect that structure and process, in general, will have an impact on
directors’ governance behavior, and that many of the recent reforms may have a positive
impact on the governance of many companies. The nature of the impact, however, is to
place directors in settings in which other motivations will ideally take effect and lead
them to govern effectively. For example, an independent director, sitting in a
compensation committee meeting, will not challenge a management recommendation or
recommend firing a CEO solely because management is not present at the meeting. Nor
will independent directors meeting out of management’s presence necessarily put in the
hard work needed to understand a difficult issue that they fear the CEO is minimizing,
solely because the CEO is not present at the meeting. A director will not become
diligent as a result of structure or process alone. There must be further inducements,
whether they be carrots or sticks, and the recent reforms do not alter the stick of liability
risk, nor do they provide any carrots.
C. If Not Law, What Can Promote Good Governance?
A full discussion of the extra-legal forces that can motivate good governance in
the boardroom lies beyond the scope of this brief essay. One obvious source of extra-
legal influence is economic. If board members hold substantial blocks of a company’s
shares throughout their tenure on the board, they would presumably be more attentive in
the boardroom. It would be impractical for the law to impose such a requirement, since
the number of shares that constitute a block substantial enough to motivate good
governance depends on how wealthy a particular board member is. Nonetheless, boards
could adopt this policy on their own and disclose the policy, the directors’ shareholdings,
and at least some additional details in their filings with the Securities and Exchange
Commission. Shareholder advocates have been pressing for this arrangement for some
time.
Professional norms are another potential force motivating good governance,
presumably a force that already explains in part why governance fiascos, prominent as
they have been, have actually been rare. These norms are fostered by the financial press
every time they write a story that exposes bad board behavior, and, on occasion, when
they write a story applauding good board behavior. Shareholder suits that shine a light on
bad behavior, and that at times generate court decisions, help create and disseminate
norms as well—even if they do ultimately settle at no out-of-pocket cost to the directors.
3
Codes of best practices written by management and shareholder associations, while often
bland in the extreme and resembling lessons one learned in kindergarten, have an impact
as well. Lipton and Lorsch’s prescription of more deliberate norm creation and
dissemination and director education is certainly worth a try as well.
In conclusion, while the law can deter egregious self-serving behavior, it can only
go so far in promoting good governance in the boardroom. The slack must be picked up
by economic and social forces. Those forces already exist, but perhaps they can be
enhanced as Lipton and Lorsch suggest.
3
Edward Rock, Saints and Sinners: How Does Delaware Corporate Law Work?, 44 U.C.L.A. L. REV. 1009 (1997).