Economics 2010a
Fall 2003
Edward L. Glaeser
Lecture 3
3. Comparative Statics
a. Indirect Utility Functions
b. Expenditure Functions and Duality
c. Expenditure Function and Price
Indices
d. Slutsky via Utility Functions
e. Slutsky via Preferences
f. Composite Commodity Theorem
g. Application: Labor Supply
Indirect Utility Functions
Indirect Utility functions represent the level
of utility as a function of prices and wages,
and we write v?p,w?.
It is useful many times, to have utility solely
as a function of "exogenous" parameters.
Define the indirect utility function as
v?p,w? ? u?x?p,w??
where x?p,w? is the Marshallian demand
function, which solves the consumers
problem to maximize u?x? subject to
w ? p ? x.
As an aside, remember that utility or
indirect utility units have no meaning. The
same preferences are u?x? and f?u?x?? if
f?. ? is a strictly monotonic function.
Properties of the indirect utility function.
MWG Proposition 3.D.3: Suppose that
u?. ? is a continuous utility function
representing a locally non-satiated
preference relation ? defined on the
consumption set ?
?
L
. The indirect utility
function
v?p,w? is:
(a) homogeneous of degree zero,
(b) strictly increasing in w and
non-increasing in p,
(c) quasiconvex; that is, the set
??p,w? : v?p,w? ? v? is convex for any v,
and
(d) continuous in p and w.
We have already proven that
Marshallian demand is homogeneous of
degree zero, this implies that indirect utility
is homogeneous of degree zero.
Nonincreasing in p follows from the
fact that if p falls you can always buy the
old bundle, and thus be no worse off.
Increasing in w uses that fact plus local
non-satiation: with an increase in w you
can always buy the old bundle plus a little
bit more of the good that you are not
satiated with.
Continuity I leave up to you.
To show quasi-convexity, assume that
v?p,w? ? v and v?p
?
,w
?
? ? v . For any
? ? ?0,1? consider the price wealth pair
?p
??
,w
??
? ? ??p ? ?1 ? ??p
?
,?w ? ?1 ? ??w
?
?
Assume that v?p,w? is not quasi convex,
i.e. there exists an x, such that
?p ? x ? ?1 ? ??p
?
? x ? ?w ? ?1 ? ??w
?
, but u?x? ? v.
If u?x? ? v, then x must not have been
affordable at the old budget sets
(otherwise it would have been chosen and
would have yielded higher utility), which
implies that p ? x ? w and p
?
? x ? w
?
.
But these together imply that
?p ? x ? ?1 ? ??p
?
? x ? ?w ? ?1 ? ??w
?
which is a contradiction.
Quasi-convexity gives us the idea that
certain types of variation in prices are
actually good, not bad for consumers.
As an obvious example, consider the utility
function x?y?z (three goods), where
consumption is contrained to be
non-negative.
The price of x is always one. Income is
always one.
What is utility if the price of y and z are
both one?
What is utility if the price of y equals 1.5
and the price of z equals .5?
What is utility if the price of y equals .5 and
the price of z equals 1.5?
Roy’s Identity:
MWG Proposition 3.G.4: Suppose that u?. ?
is a continous utility function representing
a locally non-satiated and strictly convex
preference relation ? defined on the
consumption set X ? ?
?
L
.
Suppose also that the indirect utility
function is differentiable at ?p,w? ? 0.
Then
x?p,w? ? ?
1
?
w
v?p,w?
?
p
v?p,w?
that is for every j?1,2,...L,
x
j
?p,w? ? ?
?v?p,w?
?p
j
/
?v?p,w?
?w
In words, marshallian demand for a good
equals the ratio of the derivative of indirect
utility with respect to the price of that good
divided by the derivative of indirect utility
with respect to wealth.
Proof: My favorite is the envelope theorem
argument:
v?p,w? ? U?x
?
? ? ??w ? p ? x
?
?
?v?p,w?
?p
j
? ??x
j
?
?
?x
j
?
?p
j
?U
?x
j
? ?p
But the second term is zero (that’s the
envelope argument) at the maximum.
Likewise
?v?p,w?
?w
? ? and we’re done.
The expenditure function.
Previously, we have discussed the utility
maximization problem (i.e. maximize utility
subject to a fixed budget constraint). In
many cases, it is valuable to discuss the
expenditure minimization problem (i.e.
minimize expenditure subject to a fixed
utility level).
Formally, this problem is Minimize p ? x
subject to u?x? ? u
We define the expenditure function e?p,u?
as the lowest level of income needed to
provide utility level u given prices p,
The value of e?p,u? equals p ? x
?
where
x
?
minimizes p ? x subject to u?x? ? u.
There is a fundamental equivalence
between utility maximization and
expenditure minimization captured in:
MWG Proposition 3.E.1: Suppose that u?. ?
is a continuous utility function representing
a locally non-satiated preference relation
?defined on the consumption set X ? ?
?
L
and that the price vector is
p ? 0 . Then:
(i) if x
?
maximizes utility for w?0, then
x
?
minimizes expenditure when the
required utility level is u?x
?
?. Moreover the
minimized expenditure level is exactly w.
(ii) if x
?
minimizes expenditure then the
required utility level is u then
x
?
maximzes utility when wealth equals
p ? x
?
. Moreover the
maximized utility level is exactly u.
Proof (i): Suppose that x
?
maximizes utility
and does not minimize expenditure, this
implies that there exists an x
?
such that
u?x
?
? ? u?x
?
? and p ? x
?
? p ? x
?
. But then
local nonsatiation implies that by spending
alittlemorethanp ? x
?
on the nonsatiated
good, we can find an x
??
such that
u?x
??
? ? u?x
?
? and p ? x
?
? p ? x
?
? w, and
this contradicts maximization.
The proof to the second part is quite
similar.
Properties of the Expenditure Function
MWG Proposition 3.E.2:
Suppose that u?. ? is a continuous utility
function representing a locally non-satiated
preference relation ?defined on the
consumption set X ? ?
?
L
. The expenditure
function e?p,u? is:
(i) homogeneous of degree one in p.
(ii) strictly increasing in u and
nondecreasing in p
j
for any j.
(iii) Concave in p.
(iv) Continuous in p and u.
Proof: (i) The problem Minimize p ? x
subject to u?x? ? u and minimize ?p ? x
subject to u?x? ? u , yields exactly the
same optimal value for the x vector,
denoted x
?
. As the expenditure function
equals prices times quantities, when prices
are multiplied by ?, the expenditure
function must be multiplied by the same
amount.
(ii) Assume that e?p,u? is not strictly
increasing in u , and let x
?
and x
??
denote
optimal consumption bundles for utility
levels u
?
and u
??
respectively, where u
??
? u
?
and p ? x
?
? p ? x
??
? 0. Continuity ensures
that there exists a value of ? which is less
than one but sufficiently close to one so
that u??x
??
? ? u?x
?
? and
p ? ?x
??
? p ? x
??
? p ? x
?
but then the bundle
?x
??
yields more utility at less cost than the
bundle x
?
so x
?
is not expenditure
minimizing and we have a contradiction.
(iii) Fix a utility level u, and consider two
price level p and p
?
and let
p
??
? ?p ? ?1 ? ??p
?
for ? ? ?0,1?. Let x
??
denote the bundle that minimizes
expenditures and achieves utility level u,
when prices are p
??
. If so then
e?p
??
,u? ? p
??
? x
??
? ?p ? x
??
? ?1 ? ??p
?
? x
??
?
?e?p,u? ? ?1 ? ??e?p
?
,u?
Concavity of the expenditure function with
respect to prices is the natural parallel of
convexity of the indirect utility function with
respect to prices. Under some
circumstances, price variation is good, not
bad.
Again consider the utility function x?y?z,
and think about the expenditures need to
yield one unit of utility. In the case where
the price of all three goods is one, the one
unit of currency is needed.
In the case where one of the goods costs
1.5 and the other .5, then only .5 units of
currency are needed.
Two useful equalities v?p,e?p,u?? ? u and
e?p,v?p,w?? ? w
The Hicksian demand function is defined
as h?p,u? as a function of the price level
and the utility level and Hicksian demand
is defined as the values of x that minimize
expenditures for utility level u.
The following properties of Hicksian
demand are useful:
Proposition 3.E.3: Suppose that u?. ? is a
continuous utility function representing a
locally nonsatiated preference relation ?
defined on consumption set X ? ?
?
L
. Then
for any p ? 0 the Hicksian demand
correspondence h?p,u? possesses the
following properties:
(i) homogeneity of degree zero in p,
(ii) no excess utility: for any x ? h?p,u?,
u?x? ? u
(iii) Convexity, if ? is convex then
h?p,u? is a convex set; and if ?
is strictly convex, so that u?. ? is strictly
quasi-concave then there is a unique
element in h?p,u?.
Proof of (i) h?p,u? solves the problem of
minimizing p ? x such that
u?x? ? u. The same values of x that
minimize p ? x also minimize
?p ? x.
Proof of (ii) Assume that there exists an
x ? h?p,u?, u?x? ? u
Continuity of the utility function implies that
there exists a bundle ?x where ? is less
than one, but sufficiently close to one, so
that u??x? ? u and obviously since 1 ? ? ,
p ? x ? ?p ? x as a result, the vector x
doesn’t minimize expenditures subject to
u?x? ? u
Implication of homogeneity of degree zero
and differentiability:
h??p,u? ? h?p,u?, so differentiate with
respect to ? and evaluate at ? ? 1 to get:
?
j?1
L
?h
i
?p,u?
?p
j
p
j
? 0,or,?
p
h
i
?p,u? ? p ? 0 for all
i ,whichcanbewrittenas
D
p
h?p,u? ? p ? 0 .
Another law of compensated demand:
Proposition 3.E.4: Suppose that u?. ? is a
continuous utility function representing a
locally nonsatiated preference relation ?
and that h?p,u? consists of a single
element for all p ? 0. Then the Hicksian
demand function h?p,u? satisfies the law of
compensated demand, i.e. for all p
?
and p
??
,
we have ?p
??
? p
?
? ? ?h?p
??
,u? ? h?p
?
,u?? ? 0
Proof: Since hicksian demand minimizes
expenditure for a given set of prices,
p
??
? h?p
??
,u? ? p
??
? h?p
?
,u? or
p
??
? ?h?p
??
,u? ? h?p
?
,u?? ? 0 and
p
?
? h?p
??
,u? ? p
?
? h?p
?
,u? or
p
?
? ?h?p
??
,u? ? h?p
?
,u?? ? 0.
Just subtract the two inequalities and you
are done.
The expenditure– hicksian demand link:
Proposition 3.G.1: Suppose that u?. ? is a
continuous utility function
representing a locally nonsatiated and
strictly convex preference relation ?
defined on the consumption set X ? ?
?
L
.
For all p and u , the Hicksian demand
h?p,u? is the derivative of the expenditure
function with respect to prices:
h?p,u? ? ?
p
e?p,u?
That is h
i
?p,u? ?
?e?p,u?
?p
i
for all i?1, 2, ...
L.
Proof in the case where h?p,u? ? 0 and
h?p,u? is differentiable:
Start with the fact that
e?p,u? ?
?
j?1
L
p
j
h
j
?p,u? and differentiate this
totally with respect to p
i
:
?e?p,u?
?p
i
? h
i
?p,u? ?
?
j?1
L
p
j
?h
j
?p,u?
?p
i
? h
i
?p,u?
But what does the last term equal and
why? So we’re done.
Final Expenditure Function Properties:
Proposition 3.G.1: Suppose that u?. ? is a
continuous utility function representing a
locally nonsatiated and strictly convex
preference relation ? defined on the
consumption set X ? ?
?
L
. Suppose also
that h?.,u? is continuously differentiable at
?p,u? amd denote its
L ? L derivative matrix by D
p
h?p,u?. Then:
(i) D
p
h?p,u? ? D
p
2
e?p,u?,
(ii) D
p
h?p,u? is a negative semidefinite
matrix,
(iii) D
p
h?p,u? is a symmetric matrix,
(iv) D
p
h?p,u?p ? 0
Proof: (i) follows from 3.G.1 and
differentiation, (ii) and (iii) follow from (i)
and the fact that e?p,u? is a twice
continuously differentiable concave
function which therefore has a symmetric
and negative semi-definite matrix of
second derivatives. The last property we
already proved as part of homogeneity of
degree zero and even used in the proof of
3.G.1.
Expenditure Functions and Price Indices
The price index problem– we are
interested in knowing how much welfare
has changed over time, given an increase
in prices and wealth, or alternatively how
much more needs to be spent to the same
level of utility.
This is exactly what the expenditure
function is good at– after all it tells us the
answer to exactly that question.
In some cases, things are easy. For
example if all prices change together and
are multiplied by a constant ? then we
know what to do.
Second, for infintesimal changes we also
know what the answer is:
de?p,u? ?
?
i?1
L
?e?p,u?
?p
i
dp
i
?
?
i?1
L
h
i
?p,u?dp
i
So for infinitesimal changes, you can
weight by quantities– but we measure
prices at more discrete intervals than that.
So– some different indices have been
proposed:
Laspeyres
The Laspeyres Price Index is
p
?
?q
p?q
Paasche Price Index is
p
?
?q
?
p?q
?
With w
p
?
?q
p?q
can you do better or worse in
period 2 than you did in period 1?
If utility levels are constant across periods,
can you do better with w
p
?
?q
?
p?q
?
in period 2?
So which index overstates increases in the
cost of living, and which understates it?
Deriving the Slutsky Equation the easy
way:
Start with the equality h?p,u? ? x?p,e?p,u??
Differentiate this totally with respect to
some price p
i
, then we get:
?h
i
?p,u?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?w
?e?p,u?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?w
or in matrix notation
D
p
h?p,u? ? D
p
x?p,w? ? D
w
x?p,w?x?p,w?
T
Deriving the Slutsky Equation via
Preferences (i.e. no utility functions)
You can define the expenditure function on
a reference level of consumption, rather
than a utility function, i.e. e?p,x
0
? is the
minimum amount of expenditure needed to
generate a bundle that is weakly preferred
to x
0
, or more formally:
e?p,x
0
? ? minp ? x, such that x ? x
0
Likewise, you can define the Hicksian
demand such that
h?p,x
0
? ?arg min
?x|x?x
0
?
p ? x
As before:
?e?p,x
0
?
?p
i
? h?p,x
0
?
And as before h?p,x
0
? ? x?p,e?p,x
0
??
Differentiating with respect to p
j
yields:
?h
i
?p,x
0
?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?w
?e?p,x
0
?
?p
j
?
?x
i
?p,w?
?p
j
?
Composite Commodity Theorem
(Hicks/Leontief)
In many cases, we are only interested in
the price movements of a subset of
commodities, and basically want to
agglomerate the other commodities into a
single group. The composite commodity
theorem allows us to do this.
Suppose that u?. ? is a continuous utility
function representing a locally nonsatiated
preference relation ? defined on the
consumption set X ? ?
?
L
, and that for a
subset of commodities j where k ? j ? L,
?p
k
,p
k?1
,...p
L
? ? ??p
k
,?p
k?1
,...?p
L
?, where
?p
k
,p
k?1
,...p
L
? is
constant, then exists a function
??x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
,z?,
where z ?
?
i?k
L
p
i
x
i
, such that values of
?x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
? which maximize
??x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
,z?, subject to the constraint:
?
i?1
k?1
p
i
x
i
? ?z ? w areexactlythesameas
values ?x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
? which maximize
u?x
1
,x
2
,...x
L
? subject to
?
i?1
L
p
i
x
i
? w
Define a preference ordering
?
?
defined on the space X
?
? ?
?
k
,such
that if a bundle
?x
1
,x
2
,...x
L
? ? ?y
1
,y
2
,...y
L
? for all
?y
1
,y
2
,...y
L
? such that p
i
y
i
? w
then the bundle
x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
,
?
i?k
L
p
i
x
i
?
?
?y
1
,y
2
,...y
k?1
,z?
for all bundles:
?
i?1
k?1
p
i
y
i
? ?z ? w.
This preference ordering ?
?
is rational and
continuous if the underlying preference
ordering ? is rational and continuous, so
there must exist a utility function
??x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
,z? that represents these
preferences.
Moreover, the function ??x
1
,x
2
,...x
k?1
,z?
will have all the standard characteristics of
a utility function, the walrasian demand
functions
x
i
?p
1
,p
2
,...p
k?1
,?,w? will have all the
properties of usual demand functions and
the compensated demand function
h
i
?p
1
,p
2
,...p
k?1
,?,u? will have all the usual
properties of a compensated demand
functions.
Labor Supply
(1) Certainly among the most important
decisions people make,
(2) filled with policy relevance and
correlations with policy variables across
time and space
(3) interesting in that income effects
actually may be big (not usually so)
(4) a little twist on what we have been
doing because "wealth" is endogenous
Start with two budget sets– cash and time:
WH ? Y ? ?
i
p
i
x
i
where W is wage, H is hours working, Y is
unearned income, p
i
is prices and x
i
is
commodities purchased.
This is just our usual budget constraint, but
then we also have:
T ? ?
j
t
j
? H
where T is total time budget and t
j
represents a variety of leisure type activity.
Using Walras’ Law (so the budget sets
hold with equality), they can
be combined so that:
WT ? Y ? W?
j
t
j
? ?
i
p
i
x
i
To start, consider the utility function
u ? U?x
1
,x
2
...x
L
,t
1
,t
2,
...t
L
?
Let’s use the composite commodity
theorem to aggregate non-work time, and
commodities so u ? U?c,t?
The budget set is WT ? Y ? Wt ? pc or
c ?
W?T?t??Y
p
Since I’m interested in labor supply, let’s
use the notation S ? T ? t
so we get t ? T ? S and c ?
WS?Y
p
so we
can write:
U?
WS?Y
p
,T ? S? which has first order
condition
U
c
?
WS?Y
p
,T ? S?
W
p
? U
t
?
WS?Y
p
,T ? S? ? 0
Using the implicit function theorem we can
write:
U
c
WS
?
?Z??Y
p
,T ? S
?
?Z?
W
p
? U
t
WS
?
?Z??Y
p
,T ?
where Z represents any exogenous
variable Y, p, W or T.
Differentiation then yields:
?S
?
?Y
?
U
cc
W
p
2
?U
ct
?U
cc
W
2
p
2
?U
tt
?2U
tc
W
p
and
?S
?
?W
?
U
c
1
p
?U
cc
W
p
2
?U
ct
?U
cc
W
2
p
2
?U
tt
?2U
tc
W
p
How would you model a straight income
tax (proportional)?
Among the most interesting things about
labor supply is that the
budget set may not be linear.
For example, there might be a fixed cost of
going to work. What impact would that
have on outcomes?
There might be a minimum number of
hours required for other reasons.
Perhaps most commonly, there might be a
tax rate that varies with income.
What sort of taxes should have the least
impact on hours worked– what sort of
taxes should have the most impact.
One way to formalize utility is to say:
u ? U?Z
1
?x
1
,x
2
...x
L
,t
1
,t
2,
...t
L
?,...Z
K
?x
1
,x
2
...
where utility come’s directly form the Z’s
which are produced using commodities
and time. This yields the first order
conditions:
?
i?1
K
?U
?Z
i
?Z
i
?x
i
? ?p
i
?
i?1
K
?U
?Z
i
?Z
i
?t
i
? ?W
Let’s assume no joint production right now,
so that: Z
i
? Z
i
?x
i
,t
i
?
Then we have
?U
?Z
i
?Z
i
?x
i
? ?p
i
?U
?Z
i
?Z
i
?t
i
? ?W
which means that
?Z
i
?x
i
?Z
i
?t
i
?
p
i
W
The use of time and goods in producing a
particular commodity is
determined only by the technological
tradeoffs between the two.
Furthermore, we can even think about
each commodity separately,
and minimizing costs for producing each
commodity.
In that case the job is to minimize Wt ? px
s.t. Z?t,x? ? Z
dropping the i subscripts for convenience.
This yields the same first order condition:
Z
x
Z
t
?
p
W
which we can then differentiate to get:
WZ
xx
?x
?w
? WZ
xt
?t
?w
? Z
xx
? pZ
xt
?x
?w
? pZ
tt
?t
?w
and using the equality Z?t,x? ? Z we know
?
Z
x
Z
t
?x
?w
?
?t
?w
or ?
p
W
?x
?w
?
?t
?w
Plugging this in, we get:
WZ
xx
?x
?w
? WZ
xt
p
W
?x
?w
? Z
xx
? pZ
xt
?x
?w
? pZ
tt
p
W
or
?x
?w
?
WZ
xx
? W
2
Z
xx
?p
2
Z
tt
?2pWZ
xt
and
?x
?w
?
?pZ
xx
? W
2
Z
xx
?p
2
Z
tt
?2pWZ
xt
The denominator is positive– so we have
some results.